ABU AL-WALID
AL-QURTUBI
AVERROES’
E-text Edition
(The
Incoherence of the Incoherence)
TRANSLATED
FROM THE ARABIC
WITH
INTRODUCTION AND NOTES
PUBLISHED AND DISTRIBUTED BY
TABLE
OF CONTENTS
VOLUME
I
TRANSLATION
THE FIRST DISCUSSION
Concerning the Eternity
of the World
THE
FIRST PROOF
THE
SECOND PROOF
THE THIRD PROOF
THE
FOURTH PROOF
THE
SECOND DISCUSSION: The Refutation of their Theory of the Incorruptibility of the World and
of Time and Motion
THE
THIRD DISCUSSION: The demonstration of their confusion in saying that God is the agent and
the maker of the
world and that the world in His product and act, and the demonstration that
these expressions are in their system only metaphors without any real sense
THE
FOURTH DISCUSSION: Showing that they are unable to
prone the existence of a creator of the world
THE
FIFTH DISCUSSION: To show their incapacity to prove God’s unity and the impossibility of
two necessary existents both without a cause
THE
SIXTH DISCUSSION: To
refute their denial of attributes
THE
SEVENTH DISCUSSION: To
refute their claim that nothing cars share with the First its genus and be
differentiated from it through a specific difference, and that with respect
to its intellect the division into genus and specific difference cannot be
applied to it
THE
EIGHTH DISCUSSION: To
refute their theory that the existence of the First is simple, namely that
it is pure existence and that its existence stands in relation to no
quiddity and to no essence, but stands to necessary existence as do other
beings to their quiddity
THE
NINTH DISCUSSION: To
refute their proof that the First is incorporeal
THE
TENTH DISCUSSION: To prove their incapacity to
demonstrate that the world has a creator and a cause, and that in fact they
are forced to admit atheism
THE
ELEVENTH DISCUSSION: To show the incapacity of those philosophers who believe that the First
knows other things besides its own self and that it knows the genera and the
species in a universal way, to prone that this is so
THE
TWELFTH DISCUSSION: About the impotence of the
philosophers to prone that Cod knows Himself
THE
THIRTEENTH DISCUSSION: To refute those who arm that
Gad is ignorant of the individual things which are divided in time into
present, past, and future
THE
FOURTEENTH DISCUSSION: To refute their proof that
heaven is an animal mowing in a circle in obedience to God
THE
FIFTEENTH DISCUSSION: To refute the theory of the
philosophers about the aim which moves heaven
THE
SIXTEENTH DISCUSSION: To refute the philosophical
theory that the souls of the heavens observe all the particular events of
this world
THE
FIRST DISCUSSION: The
denial of a logical necessity between cause and effect
THE
SECOND DISCUSSION: The impotence
of the philosophers to show by demonstrative proof that the soul is a
spiritual substance
THE
THIRD DISCUSSION: Refutation of
the philosophers’ proof for the immortality of the soul
THE FOURTH DISCUSSION: Concerning the philosophers’ denial of bodily resurrection
The
End: E-text note
<<Note the rest of the Table of contents is provided for informational purposes and is not available on-line>>
APPENDIX:
Changes proposed in the Arabic Text
365
INDEX
of Proper Names
374
VOLUME (II)
NOTES
1
Index of Proper Names mentioned in the Introduction and in the Notes 207
Index
of Subject/ mentioned in the Notes
211
Some
contradictions in Aristotle’s System
215
Arabic-Greek
Index to the Notes
216
Greek-Arabic Index to the Notes 218
I
wish to express my warmest thanks to the Trustees of the Gibb
Memorial Fund for making the publication of this work possible, and especially
to Professor Sir Hamilton Gibb, who asked me to
undertake the work and who has not only read the proofs but has continually
given me his interest and encouragement. I am
also deeply indebted to Dr. R. Walzer, who has
read the proofs, carefully checked the references in my notes, and composed the
indexes and the Greek-Arabic
and Arabic-Greek
vocabularies. I have also to thank Dr.
S. M. Stern for his help in completing the subject-index. Finally, I
wish to pay a tribute to one who is no longer amongst us, Father
Maurice Bouyges, without whose admirable text the work could never have
been undertaken.
The
marginal numbers in Vol. I refer to the text of Father
Bouyges’s edition of the Tahafut al Tahafut in his Bibliotheca
Arabica Scholasticorum, vol. iii, Beyrouth, 1930.
The asterisks indicate different readings from those to be found in Bouyges’s text: cf. the Appendix, Vol. I, pp, 364 ff.
If
it may be said that Santa Maria sopra Minerva is a symbol of our European
culture, it should not be forgotten that the mosque also was built on the Greek
temple. But whereas in Christian Western theology there was a gradual and
indirect infiltration of Greek, and especially Aristotelian ideas, so that it
may be said that finally Thomas Aquinas baptized Aristotle,
the impact on Islam was sudden, violent, and short. The great conquests
by the Arabs took place in the seventh century when the Arabs first came into
contact with the Hellenistic world. At that time Hellenistic culture was still
alive; Alexandria in Egypt, certain towns in Syria-Edessa for instance-were
centres of Hellenistic learning, and in the cloisters of Syria and Mesopotamia
not only Theology was studied but Science and Philosophy also were cultivated.
In Philosophy Aristotle was still ‘the
master of those who know’, and especially his logical works as
interpreted by the Neoplatonic commentators were studied intensively. But also
many Neoplatonic and Neopythagorean writings were still known, and also, very
probably, some of the old Stoic concepts and problems were still alive and
discussed.
The
great period of translation of Greek into Arabic, mostly through the
intermediary of Christian Syrians, was between the years 750 and 850, but
already before that time there was an impact of Greek ideas on Muslim theology.
The first speculative theologians in Islam are called Mu‘tazilites (from about
A. D. 723), an exact translation of the Greek word σχισματικοί
(the general name for speculative theologians is Mutakallimun,
διαλεκτικοί,
dialecticians, a name often given in later Greek philosophy to the Stoics).
Although they form rather a heterogeneous group of thinkers whose theories are
syncretistic, that is taken from different Greek sources with a preponderance of
Stoic ideas, they have certain points in common, principally their theory, taken
from the Stoics, of the rationality of religion (which is for them identical
with Islam), of a lumen
naturale which burns in the heart of every man, and the optimistic
view of a rational God who has created the best of all possible worlds for the
greatest good of man who occupies the central place in the universe. They touch
upon certain difficult problems that were perceived by the Greeks. The paradoxes
of Zeno concerning movement and the infinite
divisibility of space and time hold their attention, and the subtle problem of
the status of the nonexistent, a problem long neglected in modern philosophy,
but revived by the school of Brentano, especially
by Meinong, which caused an endless controversy
amongst the Stoics, is also much debated by them.
A
later generation of theologians, the Ash‘arites, named after Al
Ash‘ari, born A. D. 873, are forced by the weight of evidence to admit
a certain irrationality in theological concepts, and their philosophical
speculations, largely based on Stoicism, are strongly mixed with Sceptical
theories. They hold the middle way between the traditionalists who want to
forbid all reasoning on religious matters and those who affirm that reason
unaided by revelation is capable of attaining religious truths. Since Ghazali
founds his attack against the philosophers on Ash‘arite principles, we
may consider for a moment some of their theories. The difference between the
Ash‘arite and Mu‘tazilite conceptions of God cannot be better expressed than
by the following passage which is found twice in Ghazali
(in his Golden
Means of Dogmatics and his Vivification
of Theology) and to which by tradition is ascribed the breach between
Al Ash‘ari and the Mu‘tazilites.
‘Let
us imagine a child and a grown-up in Heaven who both died in the True Faith, but
the grown-up has a higher place than the child. And the child will ask God, “Why
did you give that man a higher place?” And
God will answer, “He has done many good works.”
Then the child will say, “Why did you let me
die so soon so that I was prevented from doing good?”
God will answer, “I knew that you would grow up
a sinner, therefore it was better that you should
die a child.” Then a cry goes up from the
damned in the depths of Hell, “Why,
O Lord, did you not let us die before we became
sinners?” ’
Ghazali
adds
to this: ‘the imponderable decisions of God cannot be weighed by the scales of
reason and Mu‘tazilism’.
According
to the Ash‘arites, therefore, right and wrong are human concepts and cannot be
applied to God. ‘Cui mali nihil est nec esse potest
quid huic opus est dilectu bonorum et malorum?’ is the argument of the
Sceptic Carneades expressed by Cicero
(De natura
deorum, iii. 15. 38). It is a dangerous theory for the theologians,
because it severs the moral relationship between God and man and therefore it
cannot be and is not consistently applied by the Ash‘arites and Ghazali.
The
Ash‘arites have taken over from the Stoics their epistemology, their
sensationalism, their nominalism, their materialism. Some details of this
epistemology are given by Ghazali in his
autobiography: the clearness of representations is the
criterion for their truth; the soul at birth is a blank on which the
sensations are imprinted; at the seventh year of a man’s life he acquires the
rational knowledge of right and wrong. Stoic influence on Islamic theology is
overwhelming. Of Stoic origin, for instance, are the division of the acts of man
into five classes; the importance placed on the motive of an act when judging
its moral character; the theory of the two categories of substance and accident
(the two other categories, condition and relation, are not considered by the
Muslim theologians to pertain to reality, since they are subjective); above all,
the fatalism and determinism in Islam which is often regarded as a feature of
the Oriental soul. In the Qur’an, however, there is no definite theory about
free will. Muhammad was not a philosopher. The
definition of will in man given by the Ash‘arites, as the instrument of
unalterable fate and the unalterable law of God, is Stoic both in idea and
expression. (I have discussed several other theories in my notes.)
Sometimes,
however, the theologians prefer to the Stoic view the view of their adversaries.
For instance, concerning the discussion between Neoplatonism and Stoicism
whether there is a moral obligation resting on God and man relative to animals,
Islam answers with the Neoplatonists in the affirmative (Spinoza,
that Stoic Cartesian, will give, in his Ethica,
the negative Stoic answer).
The
culmination of the philosophy of Islam was in the tenth and eleventh centuries.
This was the age also of the great theologians. It was with Greek ideas, taken
in part from Stoics and Sceptics, that the theologians tried to refute the ideas
of the philosophers. The philosophers themselves were followers of Aristotle
as seen through the eyes of his Neoplatonic commentators. This
Neoplatonic interpretation of Aristotle,
although it gives a mystical character to his philosophy which is alien
to it, has a certain justification in the fact that there are in his philosophy
many elements of the theory of his master Plato, which lend themselves to a
Neoplatonic conception. Plotinus regarded himself
as nothing but the commentator of Plato and Aristotle,
and in his school the identity of view of these two great masters was
affirmed. In the struggle in Islam between Philosophy and Theology, Philosophy
was defeated, and the final blow to the philosophers was given in Ghazali’s
attack on Philosophy which in substance is incorporated in Averroës’
book and which he tries to refute.
Ghazali, who was born in the middle of
the eleventh century, is one of the most remarkable and at the same time most
enigmatic figures in Islam. Like St. Augustine,
with whom he is often compared, he has told us in his autobiography how he had
to pass through a period of despair and scepticism until God, not through
demonstration but by the light of His grace, had given him peace and certitude.
This divine light, says Ghazali, is the basis of
most of our knowledge and, he adds, profoundly, one cannot find proofs for the
premisses of knowledge; the premisses are there and one looks for the reasons,
but they cannot be found. Certitude is reached, he says, not through scholastic
reasoning, not through philosophy, but through mystical illumination and the
mystical way of life. Still Ghazali is not only
a mystic, he is a great dogmatist and moralist. He is regarded as Islam’s
greatest theologian and, through some of his books, as a defender of Orthodoxy.
It is generally believed that the Tahafut, the book in which he
criticizes Philosophy, was written in the period of his doubts. The book,
however, is a Defence of Faith, and though it is more negative than positive,
for it aims to destroy and not to construct, it is based on the theories of his
immediate predecessors, many of whose arguments he reproduces. Besides, he
promises in this book to give in another book the correct dogmatic answers. The
treatise to which he seems to refer does not contain anything but the old
theological articles of faith and the Ash‘arite arguments and solutions. But
we should not look for consistency in Ghazali;
necessarily his mysticism comes into conflict with his dogmatism and he himself
has been strongly influenced by the philosophers, especially by Avicenna,
and in many works he comes very near to the Neoplatonic theories which he
criticizes. On the whole it would seem to me that Ghazali
in his attack on the philosophers has taken from the vast arsenal of
Ash‘arite dialectical arguments those appropriate to the special point under
discussion, regardless of whether they are destructive also of some of the views
he holds.
Averroës was the last great philosopher
in Islam in the twelfth century, and is the most scholarly and scrupulous
commentator of Aristotle. He is far better known in Europe than in the Orient,
where few of his works are still in existence and where he had no influence, he
being the last great philosopher of his culture. Renan,
who wrote a big book about him, Averroes
et l’Averro’asme, had never seen a line of Arabic by him. Lately some of
his works have been edited in Arabic, for instance his Tahafut al Tahafut, in a most
exemplary manner. Averroës’ influence on
European thought during the Middle Ages and the Renaissance has been immense.
The
name of Ghazali’s book in which he attacks the
philosophers is Tahafut
al Falasifa, which has been translated by the medieval Latin
translator as Destructio
Philosophorum. The name of Averroës’
book is Tahafut
al Tahafut, which is rendered as Destructio
Destructionis (or destructionum).
This rendering is surely not exact. The word ‘Tahafut’
has been translated by modern scholars in different ways, and the title of Ghazali’s
book has been given as the breakdown, the disintegration, or the incoherence, of
the philosophers. The exact title of Averroës’
book would be The Incoherence of the Incoherence.
In
the Revue des Deux Mondes there was an
article published in 1895 by Ferdinand Brunetiere,
‘La Banqueroute de la Science’, in which he
tried to show that the solutions by science, and especially by biology, of
fundamental problems, solutions which were in opposition to the dogmas taught by
the Church, were primitive and unreasonable. Science had promised us to
eliminate mystery, but, Brunetiere said, not only
had it not removed it but we saw clearly that it would never do so. Science had
been able neither to solve, nor even to pose, the questions that mattered: those
that touched the origin of man, the laws of his conduct, his future destiny.
What Brunetiere tried to do, to defend Faith by
showing up the audacity of Science in its attempt to solve ultimate problems, is
exactly the same as Ghazali tried to do in
relation to the pretensions of the philosophers of his time who, having based
themselves on reason alone, tried to solve all the problems concerning God and
the world. Therefore a suitable title for his book might perhaps be ‘The
Bankruptcy of Philosophy’.
In
the introduction to his book Ghazali says that a
group of people hearing the famous names Socrates,
Hippocrates, Plato,
and Aristotle, and
knowing what they had attained in such sciences as Geometry, Logic, and Physics,
have left the religion of their fathers in which they were brought up to follow
the philosophers. The theories of the philosophers are many, but Ghazali
will attack only one, the greatest, Aristotle;
Aristotle, of whom
it is said that he refuted all his predecessors, even Plato,
excusing himself by saying ‘amicus Plato, amica
veritas, sed magis amica veritas’. I may add that this well-known
saying, which is a variant of a passage in Plato’s Phaedo
and in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, is found in
this form first in Arabic. One of the first European authors who has it in this
form is Cervantes (Don Quijote, ii, c. 52).
I quote this saying-Ghazali
adds-to show that there is no surety and evidence in Philosophy.
According to Ghazali, the philosophers claim for
their metaphysical proofs the same evidence as is found in Mathematics and
Logic. But all Philosophy is based on supposition and opinion. If Metaphysics
had the same evidence as Mathematics all philosophers would agree just as well
in Philosophy as in Mathematics. According to him the translators of Aristotle
have often misunderstood or changed the meaning and the different texts
have caused different controversies. Ghazali considers
Farabi and Avicenna
to be the best commentators on Aristotle in
Islam, and it is their theories that he will attack.
Before
entering into the heart of the matter I will say a few words about Ghazali’s
remark that Metaphysics, although it claims to follow the same method as
Mathematics, does not attain the same degree of evidence. Neither Aristotle
nor his commentators ever asked the question whether there is any
difference between the methods of Mathematics and Metaphysics (it is a
significant fact that most examples of proof in the Posterior
Analytics are taken from Mathematics) and why the conclusions reached
by Metaphysics seem so much less convincing than those reached by Mathematics.
It would seem that Metaphysics, being the basis of all knowledge and having as
its subject the ultimate principles of things, should possess, according to Aristotle,
the highest evidence and that God, as being the highest principle, should
stand at the beginning of the system, as in Spinoza.
In fact, Aristotle could not have sought God if
he had not found Him. For Aristotle all necessary
reasoning is deductive and exclusively based on syllogism. Reasoning-he says-and
I think this is a profound and true remark-cannot go on indefinitely. You cannot
go on asking for reasons infinitely, nor can you reason about a subject which is
not known to you. Reason must come to a stop. There must be first principles
which are immediately evident. And indeed Aristotle acknowledges
their existence. When we ask, however, what these first principles are, he does
not give us any answer but only points out the Laws of Thought as such. But from
the Laws of Thought nothing can be deduced, as Aristotle
acknowledges himself. As a matter of fact Aristotle
is quite unaware of the assumption on which his system is based. He is
what philosophers are wont to call nowadays a naive realist. He believes that
the world which we perceive and think about with all it contains has a reality
independent of our perceptions or our thoughts. But this view seems so natural
to him that he is not aware that it could be doubted or that any reason might be
asked for it. Now I, for my part, believe that the objectivity of a common world
in which we all live and die is the necessary assumption of all reasoning and
thought. I believe indeed, with Aristotle,
that there are primary assumptions which cannot be deduced from other
principles. All reasoning assumes the existence of an objective truth which is
sought and therefore is assumed to have an independent reality of its own. Every
thinking person is conscious of his own identity and the identity of his fellow
beings from whom he accepts language and thoughts and to whom he can communicate
his own ideas and emotions. Besides, all conceptual thought implies
universality, i.e. belief in law and in objective necessity. I can only infer
from Socrates being a man that he is mortal
when I have assumed that the same thing (in this case man in so far as he is
man) in the same conditions will always necessarily behave in the same way.
In
his book Ghazali attacks the philosophers on
twenty points. Except for the last two points which are only slightly touched by
Averroës, Averroës
follows point for point the arguments Ghazali uses
and tries to refute them. Ghazali’s book is
badly constructed, it is unsystematic and repetitive. If Ghazali
had proceeded systematically he would have attacked first the
philosophical basis of the system of the philosophers-namely their proof for the
existence of God, since from God, the Highest Principle, everything else is
deduced. But the first problem Ghazali mentions
is the philosphers’ proof for the eternity of the world. This is the problem
which Ghazali considers to be the most important
and to which he allots the greatest space, almost a quarter of his book. He
starts by saying rather arbitrarily that the philosophers have four arguments,
but, in discussing them, he mixes them up and the whole discussion is
complicated by the fact that he gives the philosophical arguments and
theological counter arguments in such an involved way that the trend is
sometimes hard to follow. He says, for instance, page 3, that to the first
arguments of the philosophers there are two objections. The first objection he
gives on this page, but the second, after long controversy between the
philosophers and theologians, on page 32. I will not follow here Ghazali
and Averroës point for point in their
discussions but will give rather the substance of their principal arguments (for
a detailed discussion I refer to my notes).
The
theory of the eternity of the world is an Aristotelian one. Aristotle
was, as he says himself, the first thinker who affirmed that the world in
which we live, the universe as an orderly whole, a cosmos, is eternal. All the
philosophers before him believed that the world had come into being either from
some primitive matter or after a number of other worlds. At the same time Aristotle
believes in the finitude of causes. For him it is impossible that
movement should have started or can continue by itself. There must be a
principle from which all movement derives. Movement, however, by itself is
eternal. It seems to me that this whole conception is untenable. If the world is
eternal there will be an infinite series of causes and an infinite series of
movers; there will be an infinite series, for instance, of fathers and sons, of
birds and eggs (the example of the bird and egg is first mentioned in ‘Censorinus,
De die natali,
where he discusses the Peripatetic theory of the eternity of the world), and
we will never reach a first mover or cause, a first father or a first bird. Aristotle,
in fact, defends the two opposite theses of Kant’s first antinomy. He
holds at the same time that time and movement are infinite and that every causal
series must be finite. The contradiction in Aristotle is
still further accentuated in the Muslim philosophers by the fact that they see
in God, not only as Aristotle did, the First
Mover of the movement of the universe, but that they regard Him, under the
influence of the Plotinian theory of emanation, as the Creator of the universe
from whom the world emanates eternally. However, can the relation between two
existing entities qua existents be
regarded as a causal one? Can there be a causal relation between an eternally
unchangeable God and an eternally revolving and changing world, and is it sense
to speak of a creation of that which exists eternally? Besides, if the relation
between the eternal God and the eternal movement of the world could be regarded
as a causal relation, no prior movement could be considered the cause of a
posterior movement, and sequences such as the eternal sequence of fathers and
sons would not form a causal series. God would not be a first cause but the Only
Cause of everything. It is the contradiction in the idea of an eternal creation
which forms the chief argument of Ghazali in
this book. In a later chapter, for instance, when he refutes Avicenna’s proof
for God based on the Aristotelian concepts ‘necessary by itself’, i.e.
logical necessity, and ‘necessary through another’, i.e. ontological
necessity, in which there is the usual Aristotelian confusion of the logical
with the ontological, Ghazali’s long argument
can be reduced to the assertion that once the possibility of an infinite series
of causes is admitted, there is no sense in positing a first cause.
The
first argument is as follows. If the world had been created, there must have
been something determining its existence at the moment it was created, for
otherwise it would have remained in the state of pure possibility it was in
before. But if there was something determining its existence, this determinant
must have been determined by another determinant and so on ad infinitum, or we must accept an eternal God in whom eternally new
determinations may arise. But there cannot be any new determinations in an
eternal God.
The
argument in this form is found in Avicenna, but
its elements are Aristotelian. In Cicero’s Academics
we have a fragment of one of Aristotle’s earlier and more popular
writings, the lost dialogue De
philosophia, in which he says that it is impossible that the world
could ever have been generated. For how could there have been a new decision,
that is a new decision in the mind of God, for such a magnificent work? St.
Augustine knows this argument from Cicero and he too denies that God
could have a novum
consilium. St. Augustine is well aware
of the difficulty, and he says in his De
civilate dei that God has always existed, that after a certain time,
without having changed His will, He created man, whom He had not wanted to
create before, this is indeed a fact too profound for us. It also belongs to
Aristotle’s philosophy that in all change there is a potentiality and all
potentiality needs an actualizer which exists already. In the form this argument
has in Avicenna it is, however, taken from a book
by a late Greek Christian commentator of Aristotle,
John Philoponus, De
aeternitate mundi, which was directed against a book by the great
Neoplatonist Proclus who had given eighteen
arguments to prove the eternity of the world. Plato himself
believed in the temporal creation of the world not by God Himself but by a
demiurge. But later followers of Plato differed
from him on this point. Amongst the post-Aristotelian schools only the Stoics
assumed a periodical generation and destruction of the world. Theophrastus
had already tried to refute some of the Stoic arguments for this view, and it
may well be that John Philoponus
made use of some Stoic sources for his defence of the temporality of the world.
The
book by Proclus is lost, but John
Philoponus, who as a Christian believes in
the creation of the world, gives, before refuting them, the arguments given by Proclus.
The book by Philoponus was translated into Arabic
and many of its arguments are reproduced in the Muslim controversies about the
problem (arguments for the temporal creation of the world were also given by Philoponus
in a work against Aristotle’s theory of the eternity of the world, arguments
which are known to us through their quotation and refutation by Simplicius
in his commentary on Physics viii; one of these
arguments by Philoponus was well known to the
Arabs and is also reproduced by Ghazali, see
note 3. 3). The argument I have mentioned is the third as given by Proclus.
Philoponus’ book is extremely important for
all medieval philosophy, but it has never been translated into a modern language
and has never been properly studied. On the whole the importance of the
commentators of Aristotle for Arabic and medieval
philosophy in general has not yet been sufficiently acknowledged.
To
this argument Ghazali gives the following
answer, which has become the classic reply for this difficulty and which has
been taken from Philoponus. One must distinguish,
says Philoponus, between God’s eternally
willing something and the eternity of the object of His Will, or, as St.
Thomas will say later, ‘Deus
voluit ab aeterno mundus esset sed non ut ab aeterno esset’. God
willed, for instance, that Socrates should be
born before Plato and He willed this from
eternity, so that when it was time for Plato to
be born it happened. It is not difficult for Averroës
to refute this argument. In willing and doing something there is more than just
the decision that you will do it. You can take the decision to get up tomorrow,
but the actual willing to get up can be done only at the moment you do it, and
there can be no delay between the cause and the effect. There must be added to
the decision to get up the impulse of the will to get up. So in God there would
have to be a new impulse, and it is just this newness that has to be denied.
But, says Averroës, the whole basis of this
argument is wrong for it assumes in God a will like a human will. Desire and
will can be understood only in a being that has a need; for the Perfect Being
there can be no need, there can be no choice, for when He acts He will
necessarily do the best. Will in God must have another meaning than human will.
Averroës therefore
does not explicitly deny that God has a will, but will should not be taken in
its human sense. He has much the same conception as Plotinus,
who denies that God has the power to do one of two contraries (for God will
necessarily always choose the best, which implies that God necessarily will
always do the best, but this in fact annuls the ideas of choice and will), and
who regards the world as produced by natural necessity. Aristotle also held that for the Perfect Being no voluntary action
is possible, and he regards God as in an eternal blissful state of
self-contemplation. This would be a consequence of His Perfection which, for Averroës
at least, involves His Omniscience. For the Perfect the drama of life is ended:
nothing can be done any more, no decision can be taken any more, for decisions
belong to the condition of man to whom both knowledge and ignorance are given
and who can have an hypothetical knowledge of the future, knowing that on his
decisions the future may depend and to whom a sure knowledge of the future is
denied. But an Omniscient Being can neither act nor decide; for Him the future
is irremediable like the past and cannot be changed any more by His decisions or
actions. Paradoxically the Omnipotent is impotent. This notion of God as a
Self-contemplating Being, however, constitutes one of the many profound
contradictions in Aristotle’s system. And this profound contradiction is also
found in all the works of Aristotle’s commentators. One of Aristotle’s
proofs for the existence of God-and according to a recent pronouncement of the
Pope, the most stringent -is the one based on movement. There cannot be an
infinite series of movers; there must be a Prime Agent, a Prime Mover, God, the
originator of all change and action in the universe. According to the conception
of God as a Self-Contemplating Being, however, the love for God is the motive
for the circular motion of Heaven. God is not the ultimate Agent, God is the
ultimate Aim of desire which inspires the Heavens to action. It is Heaven which
moves itself and circles round out of love for God. And in this case it is God
who is passive; the impelling force, the efficient cause, the spring of all
action lies in the world, lies in the souls of the stars.
Let
us now return to Ghazali. We have seen that his
first argument is not very convincing, but he now gives us another argument
which the Muslim theologians have taken from John
Philoponus and which has more strength. It runs:
if you assume the world to have no beginning in time, at any moment which we can
imagine an infinite series must have been ended. To give an example, every one
of us is the effect of an infinite series of causes; indeed, man is the finite
junction of an infinite past and an infinite future, the effect of an infinite
series of causes, the cause of an infinite series of effects. But an infinite
series cannot be traversed. If you stand near the bed of a river waiting for the
water to arrive from an infinitely distant source you will never see it
arriving, for an infinite distance cannot be passed. This is the argument given
by Kant in the thesis of his first antimony. The
curious fact is that the wording in Kant is almost identical with that of John
Philoponus.
The
answers Averroës gives are certainly not
convincing. He repeats the Aristotelian dictum that what has no beginning has no
end and that therefore there is never an end of time, and one can never say that
at any moment an infinite time is ended: an infinite time is never ended. But
this is begging the question and is surely not true, for there are certainly
finite times. He denies that an infinite time involves an infinite causal series
and the negation of a First Cause. The series involved is but a temporal
sequence, causal by accident, since it is God who is its essential cause. Averroës
also bases his answer on the Aristotelian theory that in time there is only a
succession. A simultaneous infinite whole is denied by Aristotle
and therefore, according to Aristotle,
the world must be limited in space; but in time, according to him, there
is never a whole, since the past is no longer existent and the future not yet.
But
the philosophers have a convincing argument for the eternity of the world.
Suppose the world had a beginning, then before the world existed there was empty
time; but in an empty time, in pure emptiness, there cannot be a motive for a
beginning and there could be nothing that could decide God to start His
creation. This is Kant’s antithesis of his first antinomy. It is very old and
is given by Aristotle, but it is already found in
the pre-Socratic philosopher Parmenides. Ghazali’s
answer is that God’s will is completely undetermined. His will does not depend
on distinctions in outside things, but He creates the distinctions Himself. The
idea of God’s creative will is of Stoic origin. According to the Neoplatonic
conception God’s knowledge is creative. We know because things are; things are
because God knows them. This idea of the creative knowledge of God has a very
great diffusion in philosophy (just as our bodies live by the eternal spark of
life transmitted to us by our ancestors, so we rekindle in our minds the
thoughts of those who are no more); it is found, for instance, in St.
Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, Spinoza,
and Kant-who calls it intellektuelle Anschauung, intellectual
intuition, and it is also used by the Muslim philosophers when it suits them.
Against Ghazali’s conception, however, Averroës
has the following argument: If God creates the world arbitrarily, if His Will
establishes the distinctions without being determined by any reason, neither
wisdom nor goodness can be attributed to Him. We have here a difficulty the
Greeks had seen already. Either God is beyond the laws of thought and of morals
and then He is neither good nor wise, or He Himself stands under their dominion
and then He is not omnipotent.
Another
argument for the eternity of the world is based on the eternity of time: God
cannot have a priority to time, as the theologians affirm, because priority
implies time and time implies movement. For the philosophers God’s priority to
the world consists solely in His being its simultaneous cause. Both parties,
however, seem to hold that God’s existence does not imply time, since He
exists in timeless eternity. But in this case, what neither of the parties has
seen, no causal relation between God and the world can exist at all, since all
causation implies a simultaneous time.
We
come now to the most important argument which shows the basic difference between
the philosophical and theological systems. For Aristotle
the world cannot have come to be because there is no absolute becoming.
Everything that becomes comes from something. And, as a matter of fact, we all
believe this. We all believe more or less unconsciously (we are not fully aware
of our basic principles: a basement is always obscure) in the dictum rien
ne se crée, rien ne se perd. We believe that everything that comes
to be is but a development, an evolution, without being too clear about the
meaning of these words (evolution means literally ‘unrolling’, and Cicero
says that the procession of events out of time is like the uncoiling of a rope-quasi
rudentis explicatio), and we believe that the plant lies in the seed,
the future in the present. For example: when a child is born we believe it to
have certain dispositions; it may have a disposition to become a musician, and
when all the conditions are favourable it will become a musician. Now, according
to Aristotle, becoming
is nothing but the actualization of a potentiality, that is the becoming actual
of a disposition. However, there is a difficulty here. It belongs to one of the
little ironies of the history of philosophy that Aristotle’s philosophy is
based on a concept, i.e. potentiality, that has been excluded by a law that he
was the first to express consciously. For Aristotle is
the first to have stated as the supreme law of thought (or is it a law of
reality?) that there is no intermediary between being and non-being. But the
potential, i.e. the objective possible, is such an intermediary; it is namely
something which is, still is not yet. Already the Eleatics had declared that
there is no becoming, either a thing is or it is not. If it is, it need not
become. If it is not-out of nothing nothing becomes. Besides, there is another
difficulty which the Megarians have shown.
You
say that your child has a disposition to become a musician, that he can become a
musician, but if he dies as a child, or when conditions are unfavourable, he
cannot become a musician. He can only become one when all the conditions for his
being a musician are fulfilled. But in that case it is not possibly that he will
be a musician, necessarily he will be one. There is in fact no possibility of
his being a musician before he actually is one. There is therefore no
potentiality in nature and no becoming of things out of potencies. Things are or
are not. This Megarian denial of potentiality has been taken over by the
Ash‘arites, and Ghazali in this book is on the
whole, although not consistently, in agreement with them. I myself regard this
problem as one of the cruces of philosophy. The Ash‘arites and Ghazali
believed, as the Megarians did, that things do not become and that the
future does not lie in the present; every event that occurs is new and
unconnected with its predecessor. The theologians believed that the world is not
an independent universe, a self-subsistent system, that develops by itself, has
its own laws, and can be understood by itself. They transferred the mystery of
becoming to the mystery of God, who is the cause of all change in the world, and
who at every moment creates the world anew. Things are or are not. God creates
them and annihilates them, but they do not become out of each other, there is no
passage between being and non-being. Nor is there movement, since a thing that
moves is neither here nor there, since it moves-what we call movement is being at rest at different
space-atoms at different time-atoms. It is the denial of potentiality,
possibility in
rerum natura, that Ghazali uses to
refute the Aristotelian idea of an eternal matter in which the potentialities
are found of everything that can or will happen. For, according to Aristotle,
matter must be eternal and cannot have become, since it is, itself, the
condition for all becoming.
It
maybe mentioned here that the modern static theory of movement is akin to the
Megarian-Ash‘arite doctrine of the denial of movement and becoming. Bertrand
Russell, for instance, although he does not accept the Megarian atomic
conception, but holds with Aristotle that
movement and rest take place in time, not in the instant, defines movement as being
at different places at different times. At the same time, although he
rejects the Megarian conception of ‘jumps’, he affirms that the moving body
always passes from one position to another by gradual transition. But
‘passing’ implies, just as much as ‘jumping’, something more than mere
being, namely, the movement which both theories deny and the identity of the
moving body.
On
the idea of possibility another argument for the eternity of the world is based.
It is affirmed that if the world had been created an infinite number of
possibilities of its creation, that is, an eternal duration of its possibility,
would have preceded it. But nothing possible can be eternal, since everything
possible must be realized. The idea that everything possible has to be realized
is found in Aristotle himself, who says that if
there could be an eternal possible that were not realized, it would be
impossible, not possible, since the impossible is that which will never be
realized. Aristotle does not see that this
definition is contrary to the basic idea of his own philosophy-the reality of a
possibility which may or may not become real-and that by declaring that the
possible will have to happen he reduces it to a necessity, and by admitting that
everything that happens had to happen he denies that the possibility of its not
happening could precede it, i.e. he accepts, in fact, the Megarian conception of
possibility which he himself had tried to refute. Averroës,
who agrees with his master on this point, is not aware either of the implication
of the definition. On the other hand, the Ash‘arites, notwithstanding their
denial of potentiality, maintain that for God everything is possible, a theory
which implies objective possibility (the same inconsistency was committed by the
Stoics). Both philosophers and theologians, indeed, hold about this difficult
problem contradictory theories, and it is therefore not astonishing that Ghazali’s
and Averroës’ discussion about it is full of
confusion (for the details I refer to my notes).
In
the second chapter Ghazali treats the problem of
the incorruptibility of the world. As Ghazali says
himself; the problem of the incorruptibility of the world is essentially the
same as that of its being uncreated and the same arguments can be brought
forward. Still, there is less opposition amongst the theologians about its
incorruptibility than about its being uncreated. Some of the Mu‘tazilites
argued, just as Thomas Aquinas was to do later,
that we can only know through the Divine Law that this world of ours will end
and there is no rational proof for its annihilation. Just as a series of numbers
needs a first term but no final term, the beginning of the world does not imply
its end. However, the orthodox view is that the annihilation of the world,
including Heaven and Hell, is in God’s power, although this will not happen.
Still, in the corruptibility of the world there is a new difficulty for the
theologians. If God destroys the world He causes ‘nothingness’, that is, His
act is related to ‘nothing’. But can an act be related to ‘nothing’? The
question as it is posed seems to rest on a confusion between action and effect
but its deeper sense would be to establish the nature of God’s action and the
process by which His creative and annihilating power exercises itself. As there
cannot be any analogy with the physical process through which our human will
performs its function, the mystery of His creative and annihilating action
cannot be solved and the naive answers the theologians give satisfy neither Averroës
nor Ghazali himself. Averroës
argues that there is no essential difference between production and destruction
and, in agreement with Aristotle,
he affirms that there are three principles for them: form, matter, and
privation. When a thing becomes, its form arises and its privation disappears;
when it is destroyed its privation arises and its form disappears, but the
substratum of this process, matter, remains eternally. I have criticized this
theory in my notes and will only mention here that for Aristotle
and Averroës this process of production
and destruction is eternal, circular, and reversible. Things, however, do not
revolve in an eternal cycle, nor is there an eternal return as the Stoics and Nietzsche
held. Inexorably the past is gone. Every ‘now’ is new. Every flower in the
field has never been, the up-torn trees are not rooted again. ‘Thou’ll
come no more, Never, never, never, never, never!’ Besides, Averroës,
holding as he does that the world is eternally produced out of nothing, is
inconsistent in regarding with Aristotle production
and destruction as correlatives.
In
the third chapter Ghazali maintains that the
terms acting and agent are falsely applied to God by the philosophers. Acting,
according to him, can be said only of a person having will and choice. When you
say that fire burns, there is here a causal relation, if you like, but this
implies nothing but a sequence in time, just as Hume will affirm later. So when
the philosophers say that God’s acting is like the fire’s burning or the
sun’s heating, since God acts by natural necessity, they deny, according to Ghazali,
His action altogether. Real causation can only be affirmed of a willing
conscious being. The interesting point in this discussion is that, according to
the Ash‘arites and Ghazali, there is no
causation in this world at all, there is only one extra-mundane cause which is
God. Even our acts which depend on our will and choice are not, according to the
Ash‘arites, truly performed by ourselves. We are only the instruments, and the
real agent is God. But if this is true, how can we say that action and causation
depend on will and choice? How can we come to the idea of any causal action in
God depending on His Will if we deny generally that there is a causal relation
between will and action? The same contradiction is found in modern philosophy in
Mach. Mach holds
that to speak of causation or action in material things-so to say that fire
burns-is a kind of fetishism or animism, i.e. that we project our will and our
actions into physical lifeless things. However, at the same time he, as a
follower of Hume, says that causation, even in
acts caused by will, is nothing but a temporal sequence of events. He denies
causation even in voluntary actions. Therefore it would follow that the relation
of willing and acting is not different from the relation of fire and burning and
that there cannot be any question of fetishism or animism. According to such a
theory there is no action at all in the universe but only a sequence of events.
Then,
after a second argument by which Ghazali sets
out to show that an eternal production and creation are contradictions in terms,
since production and creation imply the generation of something after its
non-existence, he directs a third argument against the Neoplatonic theory, held
by the philosophers, of the emanation of the world from God’s absolute
Oneness.
Plotinus’
conception of God is prompted by the problem of plurality and relation. All
duality implies a relation, and every relation establishes a new unity which is
not the simple addition of its terms (since every whole is more than its parts)
and violates therefore the supreme law of thought that a thing is what it is and
nothing else. Just as the line is more than its points, the stone more than its
elements, the organism transcending its members, man, notwithstanding the
plurality of his faculties, an identical personality, so the world is an
organized well-ordered system surpassing the multitude of the unities it
encloses. According to Plotinus the Force binding
the plurality into unity and the plurality of unities into the all-containing
unit of the Universe is the Archetype of unity, the ultimate, primordial Monad,
God, unattainable in His supreme Simplicity even for thought. For all thought is
relational, knitting together in the undefinable unity of a judgement a subject
and a predicate. But in God’s absolute and highest Unity there is no plurality
that can be joined, since all joining needs a superior joining unit. Thus God
must be the One and the Lone, having no attribute, no genus, no species, no
universal that He can share with any creatures of the world. Even existence can
be only referred to Him when it expresses not an attribute, but His very
Essence. But then there is no bridge leading from the stable stillness of His
Unity to the changing and varied multiplicity of the world; all relation between
Him and the world is severed. If the One is the truly rational, God’s
rationality can be obtained only by regarding His relation to the world as
irrational, and all statements about Him will be inconsistent with the initial
thesis. And if God is unattainable for thought, the very affirmation of this
will be self-contradictory.
Now,
the philosophers in Islam hold with Plotinus
that although absolutely positive statements are not admissible about God, the
positive statements made by them can be all reduced to negative affirmations
(with the sole exception, according to Averroës,
of His possessing intellect) and to certain relative statements, for neither
negations nor external relations add
anything to His essence.
In
this and several following chapters Ghazali attacks
the philosophers from two sides: by showing up the inanity of the Plotinian
conception of God as pure unity, and by exposing their inconsistency in
attributing to Him definite qualities and regarding Him as the source of the
world of variety and plurality.
The
infinite variety and plurality of the world does not derive directly from God
according to the philosophers in Islam, who combine Aristotle’s astronomical
view of animate planets circling round in their spheres with the Neoplatonic
theory of emanation, and introduce into the Aristotelian framework Proclus’
conception of a triadic process, but through a series of immaterial mediators.
From God’s single act-for they with Aristotle regard
God as the First Agent-only a single effect follows, but this single effect, the
supramundane Intellect, develops in itself a threefoldness through which it can
exercise a threefold action. Ghazali objects in
a long discussion that if God’s eternal action is unique and constant, only
one single effect in which no plurality can be admitted will follow (a similar
objection can be directed against Aristotle,
who cannot explain how the plurality and variety of transitory movements
can follow from one single constant movement). The plurality of the world
according to Ghazali cannot be explained through
a series of mediators. Averroës, who sometimes
does not seem very sure of the validity of mediate emanation, is rather evasive
in his answer on this point.
In a series of rather intricate discussions which I
have tried to elucidate in my notes, Ghazali endeavours
to show that the proofs of the philosophers for God’s uniqueness, for their
denial of His attributes, for their claims that nothing can share with Him His
genus and species, that He is pure existence which stands in no relation to an
essence, and that He is incorporeal, are all vain. The leading idea of the
philosophers that all plurality needs a prior joining principle, Ghazali
rejects, while Averroës defends it.
Why-so Ghazali asks, for instance-since the
essence in temporal things is not the cause of their existence, should this not
be the case in the Eternal? Or why should body, although it is composite
according to the philosophers, not be the First Cause, especially as they assume
an eternal body, since it is not impossible to suppose a compound without a
composing principle? From the incorporeality of God, the First Principle, Avicenna
had tried to infer, through the disjunction that everything is either matter or
intellect, that He is intellect (since the philosophers in Islam hold with Aristotle
and in opposition to Plotinus that God possesses self-consciousness). Ghazali
does not admit this disjunction and, besides, argues with Plotinus
that self-consciousness implies a subject and an object, and therefore would
impede the philosophers’ thesis of God’s absolute unity.
The
Muslim philosophers, following Aristotle’s Neoplatonic commentators, affirm
that God’s self-knowledge implies His knowledge of all universals (a line of
thought followed, for instance, by Thomas Aquinas
and some moderns like Brentano). In man this
knowledge forms a plurality, in God it is unified. Avicenna
subscribes to the Qur’anic words that no particle in Heaven or Earth escapes
God’s knowledge, but he holds, as Porphyry had done before, that God can know
the particular things only in a universal way, whatever this means. Ghazali
takes it to mean that God, according to Avicenna,
must be ignorant of individuals, a most heretical theory. For Averroës
God’s knowledge is neither universal nor particular, but transcending both, in
a way unintelligible to the human mind.
One
thing, however, God cannot know according to Avicenna
(and he agrees here with Plato’s Parmenides)
and that is the passing of time, for in the Eternal no relation is possible
to the fleeting ‘now’. There are two aspects of time: the sequence of
anteriority and posteriority which remains fixed for ever, and the eternal flow
of the future through the present into the past. It will be eternally true that
I was healthy before I sickened and God can know its eternal truth. But in
God’s timeless eternity there can be no ‘now’ simultaneous with the
trembling present in which we humans live and change and die, there is no
‘now’ in God’s eternity in which He can know that I am sickening now. In
God’s eternal stillness the fleeting facts and truths of human experience can
find no rest. Ghazali objects, erroneously, I
think, that a change in the object of thought need not imply a change in the
subject of consciousness.
In
another chapter Ghazali refutes the
philosophers’ proof that Heaven is animated. He does not deny its possibility,
but declares that the arguments given are insufficient. He discusses also the
view that the heavens move out of love for God and out of desire to assimilate
themselves to Him, and he asks the pertinent question-already posed by Theophrastus
in his Metaphysics, but which scandalizes Averroës
by its prosaicness-why it is meritorious for them to circle round eternally and
whether eternal rest would not be more appropriate for them in their desire to
assimilate themselves to God’s eternal stability.
In
the last chapter of this part Ghazali examines
the philosophers’ symbolical interpretation of the Qur’anic entities ‘The
Pen’ and ‘The Tablet’ and their
theories about dreams and prophecy.
It is interesting to note that, although he refutes them here, he largely adopts
them in his own Vivification of Theology. [?]
In
the last part of his book Ghazali treats the
natural sciences. He enumerates them and declares that there is no objection to
them according to religion except on four points. The first is that there exists
a logical nexus between cause and effect; the second, the selfsubsistent
spirituality of the soul; the third, the immortality of this subsistent soul;
the fourth, the denial of bodily resurrection. The first, that there exists
between cause and effect a logical necessity, has to be contested according to Ghazali,
because by denying it the possibility of miracles can be maintained. The
philosophers do not deny absolutely the possibility of miracles. Muhammad
himself did not claim to perform any miracles and Hugo
Grotius tried to prove the superiority of Christianity over Islam by
saying ‘Mahumetis se missum ait non cum miraculis
sed cum armis’. In later times, however, Muhammad’s followers
ascribed to him the most fantastic miracles, for instance the cleavage of the
moon and his ascension to Heaven. These extravagant miracles are not accepted by
the philosophers. Their theory of the possibility of miracles is based on the
Stoic-Neoplatonic theory of ‘Sympathia’,
which is that all parts of the world are in intimate contact and related. In a
little treatise of Plutarch it is shown how
bodily phenomena are influenced by suggestion, by emotion and emotional states,
and it is claimed by him, and later also by Plotinus,
that the emotions one experiences cannot only influence one’s own body but
also other bodies, and that one’s soul can exercise an influence on other
bodies without the intermediary of any bodily action. The phenomena of
telepathy, for instance the fascination which a snake has on other animals, they
explained in this way. Amulets and talismans can receive through psychological
influences certain powers which can be realized later. This explanation of
occult phenomena, which is found in Avicenna’s Psychology,
a book translated in the Middle Ages, has been widely accepted (for
instance, by Ghazali himself in his Vivification
of Theology), and is found in Thomas
Aquinas and most of the writers about the
occult in the Renaissance, for instance Heinricus
Cornelius Agrippa, Paracelsus,
and Cardanus. It may be mentioned here that Avicenna
gives as an example of the power of suggestion that a man will go calmly over a
.plank when it is on the ground, whereas he will hesitate if the plank be across
an abyss. This famous example is found in Pascal’s Pensées,
and the well-known modern healer, Coué,
takes it as his chief proof for the power of suggestion. Pascal has taken it
from Montaigne, Montaigne
has borrowed it from his contemporary the great doctor Pietro
Bairo, who himself has a lengthy quotation from the Psychology
of Avicenna. Robert
Burton in his Anatomy
of Melancholy also mentions it. In the Middle Ages this example is
found in Thomas Aquinas. Now the philosophers
limit the possibility of miracles only to those that can be explained by the
power of the mind over physical objects; for instance, they would regard it as
possible that a prophet might cause rain to fall or an earthquake to take place,
but they refuse to accept the more extravagant miracles I have mentioned as
authentic.
The
theologians, however, base their theory of miracles on a denial of natural law.
The Megarian-Ash‘arite denial of potentiality already implies the denial of
natural law. According to this conception there is neither necessity nor
possibility in
rerum natura, they are or they are not, there is no nexus between the
phenomena. But the Greek Sceptics also deny the rational relation between cause
and effect, and it is this Greek Sceptical theory which the Ash‘arites have
copied, as we can see by their examples. The theory that there is no necessary
relation between cause and effect is found, for instance, in Galen.
Fire burns but there is, according to the Greek Sceptics, no necessary relation
between fire and burning. Through seeing this happen many times we assume that
it will happen also in the future, but there is no necessity, no absolute
certainty. This Sceptical theory is quasi-identical with the theory of Hume and
is based on the same assumptions, that all knowledge is given through
sense-impression; and since the idea of causation cannot be derived from sense
experience it is denied altogether. According to the theory of the theologians,
God who creates and re-creates the universe continually follows a certain habit
in His creation. But He can do anything He desires, everything is possible for
Him except the logically impossible; therefore all logically possible miracles
are allowed. One might say that, for the theologians, all nature is miraculous
and all miracles are natural. Averroës asks a
good question: What is really meant by habit, is it a habit in man or in nature?
I do not know how Hume would answer this question. For if causation is a habit
in man, what makes it possible that such a habit can be formed? What is the
objective counterpart of these habits? There is another question which has been
asked by the Greek opponents of this theory, but which is not mentioned by Averroës: How many times must such a sequence be observed before
such a habit can be formed? There is yet another question that might be asked:
Since we cannot act before such a habit is formed-for action implies
causation-what are we doing until then? What, even, is the meaning of ‘I
act’ and ‘I do’? If there is nothing in the world but a sequence of
events, the very word ‘activity’ will have no sense, and it would seem that
we would be doomed to an eternal passivity. Averroës’
answer to this denial of natural law is that universals themselves imply already
the idea of necessity and law. I think this answer is correct. When we speak,
for instance, of wood or stone, we express by those words an hypothetical
necessity, that is, we mean a certain object, which in such-and-such
circumstances will necessarily behave in a certain way that the behaviour of
wood, for example, is based on its nature, that is, on the potentialities it
has.
I
may remark here that it seems to me probable that Nicholas
of Autrecourt, ‘the medieval Hume’,
was influenced by Ghazali’s Ash‘arite
theories. He denies in the same way as Ghazali the
logical connexion between cause and effect: ‘ex eo quod aliqua res est cognita esse, non potest evidenter evidentia
reducta in primum principium vel in certitudinem primi principii inferri, quod
alia res sit’ (cf. Lappe, ‘Nicolaus von Autrecourt’, Beitr.
z. Gesch. d. Phil. d. M. B.vi, H.2, p. 11); he gives the same example of ignis
and stupa,
he seems to hold also the Ash‘arite thesis of God as the sole cause of all
action (cf. op. cit., p. 24), and he quotes in one place Ghazali’s
Metaphysics (cf. N. of Autrecourt, ‘Exigit ordo
executionis’, in Mediaeval
Studies, vol. i, ed. by J. Reginald O’Donnell, Toronto, 1931, p. 2o8). Now
Nicholas’s works were burnt during his lifetime in Paris in 1347, whereas the
Latin translation of the Tahafut
al Tahafut by Calo Calonymus was
terminated in Arles in 1328.
The
second point Ghazali wants to refute are the
proofs for the substantiality and the spirituality of the soul as given by the
philosophers. He himself does not affirm that the soul is material, and as a
matter of fact he holds, in other books, the contrary opinion, but the
Ash‘arites largely adopted the Stoic materialism. The ten arguments of the
philosophers for the spirituality of the soul derive all from arguments given by
the Greeks. It would seem to me that Ghazali’s
arguments for the soul’s materiality may be based on the Stoic answers (which
have not come down to us) against the proofs of Aristotle
and the later Platonists for the immateriality of the soul. There is in
the whole discussion a certain confusion, partly based on the ambiguity of the
word ‘soul’. The term ‘soul’ both in Greek and Arabic can also mean
‘life’. Plants and animals have a ‘soul’. However, it is not affirmed by
Aristotle that life in plants and animals is a
spiritual principle. ‘Soul’ is also used for the rational part, the thinking
part, of our consciousness. It is only this thinking part, according to Aristotle,
that is not related to or bound up with matter; sensation and imagination
are localized in the body, and it is only part of our thinking soul that seems
to possess eternity or to be immortal. Now, most of the ten arguments derive
from Aristotle and mean only to prove that the
thinking part of our soul is incorporeal. Still the Muslim philosophers affirm
with Plato and Plotinus
that the whole soul is spiritual and incorruptible, and that the soul is a
substance independent of the body, although at the same time they adopt
Aristotle’s physiological explanations of all the non-rational functions of
the soul and accept Aristotle’s definition of the ‘soul’ as the first
entelechy of an organic body. On the other hand, the Muslim philosophers do not
admit the Platonic theory of the pre-existence of the soul. Aristotle’s
conception of a material and transitory element in the soul and an immaterial
and immortal element destroys all possibility of considering human personality
as a unity. Although he reproaches Plato with
regarding the human soul as a plurality, the same reproach can be applied to
himself. Neither the Greek nor the Muslim philosophers have ever been able to
uphold a theory that does justice to the individuality of the human personality.
That it is my undefinable ego that perceives, represents, wills, and thinks, the
mysterious fact of the uniqueness of my personality, has never been apprehended
by them. It is true that there is in Aristotle’s psychology a faint conception
of a functional theory of our conscious life, but he is unable to harmonize this
with his psycho-physiological notions.
I
have discussed in my notes the ten arguments and will mention here only two
because of their importance. Ghazali gives one
of these arguments in the following form: How can man’s identity be attributed
to body with all its accidents? For bodies are continually in dissolution and
nutrition replaces what is dissolved, so that when we see a child, after
separation from its mother’s womb, fall ill a few times, become thin and then
fat again, and grow up, we may safely say that after forty years no particle
remains of what there was when its mother was delivered of it. Indeed, the child
began its existence out of parts of the sperm alone, but nothing of the
particles of the sperm remains in it; no, all this is dissolved and has changed
into something else and then this body has become another. Still we say that the
identical man remains and his notions remain with him from the beginning of his
youth although all bodily parts have changed, and this shows that the soul has
an existence outside the body and that the body is its organ. Now the first part
of this argument, that all things are in a state of flux and that of the bodily
life of man no part remains identical, is textually found in Montaigne’s Apologv
of Raymond de Sebond. Montaigne has
taken it from Plutarch, and the Arabic
philosophers may have borrowed it from the same source from which Plutarch
has taken it. The argument of the philosophers that matter is evanescent, but
the soul a stable identity, which is also given by the Christian philosopher Nemesius
in his De natura
hominis (a book translated into Arabic), who ascribes it to Ammonius
Saccas and Numenius,
is basically Platonic and Neoplatonic, and strangely enough, although he refutes
it here, it is adduced by Ghazali himself in his
Vivification of
Theology. Socrates says in the Platonic dialogue Cratylus:
‘Can we truly say that there is knowledge, Cratylus,
if all things are continually changing and nothing remains? For knowledge cannot
continue unless it remains and keeps its identity. But if knowledge changes its
very essence, it will lose at once its identity and there will be no
knowledge.’ Plotinus (Enn.
iv. 7. 3) argues that matter, in its continual changing, cannot explain the
identity of the soul. And he says in a beautiful passage (Enn. iv. 7. 10) the idea of which Avicenna
has copied:
‘One should contemplate the nature of everything in its purity,
since what is added is ever an obstacle to its knowledge. Contemplate therefore
the soul in its abstraction or rather let him who makes this abstraction
contemplate himself in this state and he will know that he is immortal when he
will see in himself the purity of the intellect, for he will see his intellect
contemplate nothing sensible, nothing mortal, but apprehending the eternal
through the eternal.’
This
passage bears some relation to Descartes’s dictum cogito ergo sum, but whereas Plotinus
affirms the self-consciousness of a stable identity, Descartes
states only that every thought has a subject, an ego. Neither the one, nor the
other shows that this subject is my ego in the sense of my undefinable unique
personality, my awareness who I am: that I am, for instance, John and not Peter,
my consciousness of the continuity of my identity from birth to death, my
knowledge that at the same time I am master and slave of an identical body,
whatever the changes may be in that body, and that as long as I live I am a
unique and an identical whole of body and soul. Plautus’ Sosia,
who was not a philosopher, expresses himself (Amphitruo,
line 447) in almost the same way as Descartes-‘sed
quom cogito, equidem certo idem sum qui fui semper’-but
the introduction of the words semper
and idem
renders the statement fallacious; from mere consciousness the lasting
identity of my personality cannot be inferred.
Ghazali answers this point by saying
that animals and plants also, notwithstanding that their matter is continually
changing, preserve their identity, although nobody believes that this identity
is based on a spiritual principle. Averroës
regards this objection as justified.
The
second argument is based on the theory of universals. Since thought apprehends
universals which are not in a particular place and have no individuality, they
cannot be material, since everything material is individual and is in space.
Against this theory of universals Ghazali develops,
under Stoic influence, his nominalistic theory which is probably the theory held
by the Ash‘arites in general. This theory is quasi-identical with Berkeley’s
nominalistic conception and springs from the same assumption that thinking is
nothing but the having of images. By a strange coincidence both Ghazali
and Berkeley give the example of a hand:
when we have an idea of a hand as a universal, what really happens is that we
have a representation of a particular hand, since there are no universals. But
this particular hand is capable of representing for us any possible hand, just
as much a big black hand as a small white one. The fallacy of the theory lies,
of course, in the word ‘representing’, which as a matter of fact assumes
what it tended to deny, namely, that we can think of a hand in general which has
neither a particular shape, nor a particular colour, nor is localized in space.
The
next point Ghazali tries to refute is the
argument of the philosophers for the immortality of the soul. According to the
philosophers, the fact that it is a substance independent of a body and is
immaterial shows that a corruption of the body cannot affect it. This, as a
matter of fact, is a truism, since the meaning of substantiality and
immateriality for the philosophers implies already the idea of eternity. On the
other hand, if the soul is the form of the body, as is also affirmed by them, it
can only exist with its matter and the mortality of its body would imply its own
mortality, as Ghazali rightly points out. The
Arabic philosophers through their combination of Platonism and Aristotelianism
hold, indeed, at the same time three theories inconsistent with each other,
about the relation of body and soul: that the soul is the form of the body, that
the soul is a substance, subsistent by itself and immortal, and that the soul
after death takes a pneumatic body (a theory already found in Porphyry). Besides, their denial of the Platonic idea of
pre-existence of the soul vitiates their statement that the soul is a substance,
subsistent by itself, that is, eternal, ungenerated, and incorruptible. Although
Averroës in his whole book tries to come as
near to the Aristotelian conception of the soul as possible, in this chapter he
seems to adopt the eschatology of the late Greek authors. He allows to the souls
of the dead a pneumatic body and believes that they exist somewhere in the
sphere of the moon. He also accepts the theory of the Djinn, the equivalent of the Greek
Daimones.
What he rejects, and what the philosophers generally reject, is the
resurrection of the flesh.
In
his last chapter Averroës summarizes his views
about religion. There are three possible views. A Sceptical view that religion
is opium for the people, held by certain Greek rationalists; the view that
religion expresses Absolute Truth; and the intermediate view, held by Averroës,
that the religious conceptions are the symbols of a higher philosophical truth,
symbols which have to be taken for reality itself by the non-philosophers. For
the unphilosophical, however, they are binding, since the sanctity of the State
depends on them.
When
we have read the long discussions between the philosophers and theologians we
may come to the conclusion that it is sometimes more the formula than the
essence of things which divides them. Both philosophers and theologians Arm that
God creates or has created the world. For the philosophers, since the world is
eternal, this creation is eternal. Is there, however, any sense in calling
created what has been eternally? For the theologians God is the creator of
everything including time, but does not the term ‘creation’ assume already
the concept of time? Both the philosophers and theologians apply to God the
theory that His will and knowledge differ from human will and knowledge in that
they are creative principles and essentially beyond understanding; both admit
that the Divine cannot be measured by the standards of man. But this, in fact,
implies an avowal of our complete ignorance in face of the Mystery of God.
Still, for both parties God is the supreme Artifex who in His wisdom has chosen
the best of all possible worlds; for although the philosophers affirm also that
God acts only by natural necessity, their system, like that of their
predecessors, the Platonists, Peripatetics, and Stoics, is essentially
teleological. As to the problem of possibility, both parties commit the same
inconsistencies and hold sometimes that the world could, sometimes that it could
not, have been different from what it is. Finally, both parties believe in
God’s ultimate Unity.
And
if one studies the other works of Ghazali the
resemblance between him and the philosophers becomes still greater. For
instance, he too believes in the spirituality of the soul, notwithstanding the
arguments he gives against it in this book; he too sometimes regards religious
concepts as the symbols of a higher philosophical or mystical truth, although he
admits here only a literal interpretation. He too sometimes teaches the
fundamental theory of the philosophers which he tries to refute so insistently
in our book, the theory that from the one supreme Agent as the ultimate source
through intermediaries all things derive; and he himself expresses this idea (in
his Alchemy of
Happiness and slightly differently in his Vivification of
Theology)
by the charming simile of an ant which seeing black tracings on a sheet of
paper thinks that their cause is the pen, while it is the hand that moves the
pen by the power of the will which derives from the heart, itself inspired by
the spiritual agent, the cause of causes. The resemblances between Ghazali
and Averroës, men belonging to the same
culture, indeed, the greatest men in this culture, seem sometimes greater than
their differences.
Emotionally
the difference goes deep. Averroës is a
philosopher and a proud believer in the possibility of reason to achieve a
knowledge of ‘was das Innere der Welt zusammenhält’.
He was not always too sure, he knew too much, and there is much wavering and
hesitation in his ideas. Still, his faith in reason remains unshaken. Although
he does not subscribe to the lofty words of his master that man because of the
power of his intellect is a mortal God, he reproaches the theologians for having
made God an immortal man. God, for him, is a dehumanized principle. But if God
has to respond to the needs of man’s heart, can He be exempt from humanity? Ghazali
is a mu’min, that is a believer, he is a
Muslim,
that is he accepts his heart submits to a truth his reason cannot establish, for
his heart has reasons his reason does not know. His theology is the philosophy
of the heart in which there is expressed man’s fear and loneliness and his
feeling of dependence on an understanding and loving Being to whom he can cry
out from the depths of his despair, and whose mercy is infinite. It is not so
much after abstract truth that Ghazali strives;
his search is for God, for the Pity behind the clouds.
IN THE NAME OF THE MERCIFUL AND COMPASSIONATE
GOD: AND AFTER PRAISE TO GOD AND BENEDICTION UPON ALL HIS
MESSENGERS AND PROPHETS:
The
aim of this book is to show the different degrees of assent and conviction
attained by the assertions in The Incoherence of the Philosophers, and to prove
that the greater part has not reached the degree of evidence and of truth.
THE FIRST DISCUSSION
Concerning the Eternity of the
World
Ghazali, speaking of
the philosophers’ proofs for the eternity of the world, says:
Let us restrict ourselves in this chapter to those proofs that make an impression on the mind.
This chapter contains four proofs.
The philosophers say: It is impossible that the temporal should proceed from the absolutely Eternal. For it is clear if we assume the Eternal existing without, for instance, the world proceeding from Him, then, at a certain moment, the world beginning to proceed from Him-that it did not proceed before, because there was no determining principle for its existence, but its existence was pure possibility. When the world begins in time, a new determinant either does or does not arise. If it does not, the world will stay in the same state of pure possibility as before; if a new determinant does arise, the same question can be asked about this new determinant, why it determines now, and not before, and either we shall have an infinite regress or we shall arrive at a principle determining eternally.
I say: This argument is in the highest degree
dialectical and does not reach the
pitch of demonstrative proof. For its premisses are common notions, and common
notions approach the equivocal, whereas demonstrative premisses are concerned
with things proper to the same genus.
For
the term ‘possible’ is used in an equivocal way of the possible that happens
more often than not, of the possible that happens less often than not, and of
the possible with equal chances of happening, and these three types of the
possible do not seem to have the same need for a new determining principle. For
the possible that happens more often than not is frequently believed to have
its determining principle in itself, not outside, as is the case with the
possible which has equal chances of happening and not happening. Further, the
possible resides sometimes in the agent, i.e. the possibility of acting, and
sometimes in the patient, i.e. the possibility of receiving, and it does not
seem that the necessity for a determining principle is the same in both cases.
For it is well known that the possible in the patient needs a new determinant
from the outside; this can be perceived by the senses in artificial things and
in many natural things too, although in regard to natural things there is a
doubt, for in most natural things the principle of their change forms part of
them. Therefore it is believed of many natural things that they move
themselves, and it is by no means self-evident that everything that is
moved has a mover and that there is nothing that moves itself.; But all this
needs to be examined, and the old philosophers have therefore done so. As
concerns the possible in the agent, however, in many cases it is believed that
it can be actualized without an external principle, for the transition in the
agent from inactivity to activity is often regarded as not being a change which
requires a principle; e.g. the transition in the geometer from non-geometrizing
to geometrizing, or in the teacher from non-teaching to teaching.
Further,
those changes which are regarded as needing a principle of change can sometimes
be changes in substance, sometimes in quality, or in quantity, or in place.
In
addition, ‘eternal’ is predicated by many of the eternal-by-itself
and the eternal-through-another. According to some, it is
permissible to admit certain changes in the Eternal, for instance a new
volition in the Eternal, according to the Karramites, and the possibility of
generation and corruption which the ancients attribute to primary matter,
although it is eternal. Equally, new concepts are admitted in the possible
intellect although, according to most authors, it is eternal. But there are also changes which are
inadmissible, especially according to certain ancients, though not according to
others.
Then
there is the agent who acts of his will and the agent which acts by nature, and
the manner of actualization of the possible act is not the same for both
agents, i.e. so far as the need for a new determinant is concerned. Further, is
this division into two agents complete, or does demonstration lead to an agent
which resembles neither the natural agent nor the voluntary agent of human
experience?
All these are multifarious and difficult questions which need, each of them, a special examination, both in themselves and in regard to the opinions the ancients held about them. To treat what is in reality a plurality of questions as one problem is one of the well known seven sophisms, and a mistake in one of these principles becomes a great error by the end of the examination of reality.
Ghazali
says:
There are two objections to this. The first objection is to say: why do you deny the theory of those who say that the world has been created by an eternal will which has decreed its existence in the time in which it exists; that its non-existence lasts until the moment it ceases and that its existence begins from the moment it begins; that its existence was not willed before and therefore did not happen, and that at the exact moment it began it was willed by an eternal will and therefore began? What is the objection to this theory and what is absurd in it?
I say:
This
argument is sophistical: although it is not allowable for him to admit the
possibility of the actual effect being delayed after the actual cause, and in a
voluntary agent, after the decision to act, he regards it as possible that the
effect should be delayed after the will of the agent. It is possible that the
effect should be delayed after the will of the agent, but its being delayed
after the actual cause is impossible, and equally impossible is its being
delayed after a voluntary agent’s decision to act. The difficulty is thus
unchanged, for he must of necessity draw one of these two conclusions: either
that the act of the agent does not imply in him a change which itself would
need an external principle of change, or that there are changes which arise by
themselves, without the necessity of an agent in whom they occur and who causes
them, and that therefore there are changes possible in the Eternal without an
agent who causes them. And his adversaries insist on these two very points: ( 1
) that the act of the agent necessarily implies a change and that each change has a principle which
causes it; (2) that the Eternal cannot change in any way. But all this is
difficult to prove.
The Ash’arites are forced to assume either a first agent or a first act of this agent, for they cannot admit that the disposition of the agent, relative to the effect, when he acts is the same as his disposition, when he does not act. This implies therefore a new disposition or a new relation, and this necessarily either in the agent, or in the effect, or in both? But in this case, if we posit as a principle that for each new disposition there is an agent, this new disposition in the first agent will either need another agent, and then this first agent was not the first and was not on his own account sufficient for the act but needed another, or the agent of the disposition which is the condition of the agent’s act will be identical with the agent of the act. Then this act which we regarded as being the first act arising out of him will not be the first, but his act producing the disposition which is the condition of the effect will be anterior to the act producing the effect. This, you see, is a necessary consequence, unless one allows that new dispositions may arise in the agents without a cause. But this is absurd, unless one believes that there are things which happen at haphazard and by themselves, a theory of the old philosophers who denied the agent,; the falsehood of which is self-evident.
In Ghazali’s objection there is a confusion. For our expressions ‘eternal will’ and ‘temporal will’ are equivocal, indeed contrary. For the empirical will is a faculty which possesses the possibility of doing equally one of two contraries and then of receiving equally one of the two contraries willed. For the will is the desire of the agent towards action. When the agent acts, the desire ceases and the thing willed happens, and this desire and this act are equally related to both the contraries. But when one says: ‘There is a Wilier who wills eternally one of two contraries in Himself’, the definition of the will is abandoned, for we have transferred its nature from the possible to the necessary. If it is objected that in an eternal will the will does not cease through the presence of the object willed, for as an eternal will has no beginning there is no moment in it which is specially determined for the realization of the object willed, we answer: this is not obvious, unless we say that demonstrative proof leads to the existence of an agent endowed with a power which is neither voluntary nor natural, which, however, the Divine Law calls ‘will’, in the same way as demonstrative proof leads to middle terms between things which seemed at first sight to be contrary, without being really so, as when we speak of an existence which is neither inside nor outside the world.
Ghazali
answers, on behalf of the philosophers:
The philosophers say: This is clearly impossible, for everything that happens is necessitated and has its cause, and as it is impossible that there should be an effect without a necessitating principle and a cause, so it is impossible that there should exist a cause of which the effect is delayed, when all the conditions of its necessitating, its causes and elements are completely fulfilled. On the contrary, the existence of the effect, when the cause is realized with all its conditions, is necessary, and its delay is just as impossible as an effect without cause. Before the existence of the world there existed a Wilier, a will, and its relation to the thing willed. No new wilier arose, nor a new will, nor a new relation to the will-for all this is change; how then could a new object of will arise, and what prevented its arising before? The condition of the new production did not distinguish itself from the condition of the non-production in any way, in any mode, in any relation-on the contrary, everything remained as it was before. At one moment the object of will did not exist, everything remained as it was before, and then the object of will existed. Is not this a perfectly absurd theory?
I say:
This
is perfectly clear, except for one who denies one of the premisses we have laid
down previously. But Ghazali passes from this
proof to an example based upon convention,’ and through this he confuses this
defence of the philosophers.
Ghazali says:
This kind of impossibility is found not only in the necessary and essential cause and effect but also in the accidental and conventional. If a man pronounces the formula of divorce against his wife without the divorce becoming irrevocable immediately, one does not imagine that it will become so later. For he made the formula through convention and usage a cause of the judgement, and we do not believe that the effect can be delayed, except when the divorce depends on an ulterior event, e.g. on the arrival of tomorrow or on someone’s entering the house, for then the divorce does not take place at once, but only when tomorrow arrives or someone enters the house; in this case the man made the formula a cause only in conjunction with an ulterior event. But as this event, the coming of tomorrow and someone’s entering the house, is not yet actual, the effect is delayed until this future event is realized. The effect only takes place when a new event, i.e. entering the house or the arrival of tomorrow, has actually happened. Even if a man wanted to delay the effect after the formula, without making it dependent on an ulterior event, this would be regarded as impossible, although it is he himself who lays down the convention and fixes its modalities. If thus in conventional matters such a delay is incomprehensible and inadmissible, how can we admit it in essential, rational, and necessary causal relations? In respect of our conduct and our voluntary actions, there is a delay in actual volition only when there is some obstacle. When there is actual volition and actual power and the obstacles are eliminated, a delay in the object willed is inadmissible.; A delay in the object willed is imaginable only in decision, for decision is not sufficient for the existence of the act; the decision to write does not produce the writing, if it is not, as a new fact, accompanied by an act of volition, i.e. an impulse in the man which presents itself at the moment of the act. If there is thus an analogy between the eternal Will and our will to act, a delay of the object willed is inadmissible, unless through an obstacle, and an antecedent existence of the volition is equally inadmissible, for I cannot will to get up tomorrow except by way of decision. If, however, the eternal Will is analogous to our decision, it does not suffice to produce the thing decided upon, but the act of creation must be accompanied by a new act of volition, and this brings us again to the idea of a change. But then we have the same difficulty all over again. Why does this impulse or volition or will or whatever you choose to call it happen just now and not before? There remain, then, only these alternatives: either something happening without a cause, or an infinite regress. This is the upshot of the discussion: There is a cause the conditions of which are all completely fulfilled, but notwithstanding this the effect is delayed and is not realized during a period to the beginning of which imagination cannot attain and for which thousands of years would mean no diminution; then suddenly, without the addition of any new fact, and without the realization of any new condition, this effect comes into existence and is produced. And this is absurd.
I say:
This
example of divorce based on convention seems to strengthen the argument of the
philosophers, but in reality it weakens it. For it enables the Ash’arites to
say: In the same way as the actual divorce is delayed after the formula of
divorce till the moment when the condition of someone’s entering the house, or
any other, is fulfilled, so the realization of the world can be delayed after
God’s act of creation until the condition is fulfilled on which this
realization depends, i.e. the moment when God willed it. But conventional
things do not behave like rational. The Literalists, comparing these
conventional things to rational, say: This divorce is not binding and does not
become effective through the realization of the condition which is posterior to
the pronouncement of the divorce by the divorcer, since it would be a divorce
which became effective without connexion with the act of the divorcer. But in
this matter there is no relation between the concept drawn from the nature of
things and that which is artificial and conventional.
Then
Ghazali says, on behalf of the Ash’arites:
The answer is: Do you recognize the impossibility of connecting the eternal Will with the temporal production of anything, through the necessity of intuitive thought or through a logical deduction, or-to use your own logical terminology-do you recognize the clash between these two concepts through a middle term or without a middle term? If you claim a middle term-and this is the deductive method-you will have to produce it, and if you assert that you know this through the necessity of thought, why do your adversaries not share this intuition with you? For the party which believes in the creation of the world in time through an eternal Will includes so many persons that no country can contain them and no number enumerate them, and they certainly do not contradict the logically minded out of obstinacy, while knowing better in their hearts. A proof according to the rules of logic must be produced to show this impossibility, as in all your arguments up till now there is only a presumption of impossibility and a comparison with our decision and our will; and this is false, for the eternal Will does not resemble temporal volitions, and a pure presumption of impossibility will not suffice without proof.
I say:
This
argument is one of those which have only a very feeble persuasive power. It
amounts to saying that one who claims the impossibility of delay in an effect,
when its cause with all its conditions is realized, must assert that he knows
this either by a syllogism or from first principles; if through a syllogism, he
must produce it-but there is none; if from first principles, it must be known
to all, adversaries and others alike. But this argument is mistaken, for it is
not a condition of objective truth that it should be known to all. That
anything should be held by all does not imply anything more than its being a
common notion, just as the existence of a common notion does not imply
objective truth.
Ghazali answers on behalf of the Ash’arites:
If it is said, ‘We know by the necessity of thought that, when all its conditions are fulfilled, a cause without effect is inadmissible and that to admit it is an affront to the necessity of thought,’ we answer: what is the difference between you and your adversaries, when they say to you, ‘We know by the necessity of thought the impossibility of a theory which affirms that one single being knows all the universals, without this knowledge forming a plurality in its essence or adding anything to it, and without this plurality of things known implying a plurality in the knowledge’? For this is your theory of God, which according to us and our science is quite absurd. You, however, say there is no analogy between eternal and temporal knowledge. Some of you acknowledge the impossibility involved, and say that God knows only Himself and that He is the knower, the knowledge and the known, and that the three are one. One might object: The unity of the knowledge, the knower, and the known is clearly an impossibility, for to suppose the Creator of the world ignorant of His own work is necessarily absurd, and the Eternal-who is far too high to be reached by your words and the words of any heretics-could, if He knows only Himself, never know His work.
I
say
This amounts to saying that the theologians do not gratuitously and without proof deny the admitted impossibility of a delay between the effect and its cause, but base themselves on an argument which leads them to believe in the temporal creation of the world, and that they therefore act in the same way as the philosophers, who only deny the well-known necessary plurality of knowledge and known, so far as it concerns their unity in God, because of a demonstration which, according to them, leads them to their theory about Him. And that this is still more true of those philosophers who deny it to be necessary that God should know His own work, affirming that He knows only Himself. This assertion belongs to the class of assertions whose contrary is equally false., For there exists no proof which refutes anything that is evidently true, and universally acknowledged. Anything that can be refuted by a demonstrative proof is only supposed to be true, not really true.] Therefore, if it is absolutely and evidently true that knowledge and known form a plurality, both in the visible and in the invisible world, we can be sure that the philosophers cannot have a proof of this unity in God; but if the theory of the plurality of knowledge and known is only a supposition, then it is possible for the philosophers to have a proof. Equally, if it is absolutely true that the effect of a cause cannot be delayed after the causation and the Ash’arites claim that they can advance a proof to deny it, then we can be absolutely sure that they cannot have such a proof. If there is a controversy about questions like this, the final criterion rests with the sound understanding’ which does not base itself on prejudice and passion, when it probes according to the signs and rules by which truth and mere opinion are logically distinguished. Likewise, if two people dispute about a sentence and one says that it is poetry, the other that it is prose, the final judgment rests with the ‘sound understanding’ which can distinguish poetry from prose, and with the science of prosody. And as, in the case of metre, the denial of him who denies it does not interfere with its perception by him who perceives it, so the denial of a truth by a contradictor does not trouble the conviction of the men to whom it is evident.
This
whole argument is extremely inept and weak, and Ghazali
ought not to have filled his book with such talk if he intended to convince the
learned.
And
drawing consequences which are irrelevant and beside the point, Ghazali goes on to say:
But the consequences of this argument cannot be overcome. And we say to them: How will you refute your adversaries, when they say the eternity of the world is impossible, for it implies an infinite number and an infinity of unifies for the spherical revolutions, although they can be divided by six, by four, and by two.’ For the sphere of the sun revolves in one year, the sphere of Saturn in thirty years, and so Saturn’s revolution is a thirtieth and Jupiter’s revolution-for Jupiter revolves in twelve years-a twelfth of the sun’s revolution. But the number of revolutions of Saturn has the same infinity as the revolutions of the sun, although they are in a proportion of one to thirty and even the infinity of the sphere of the fixed stars which turns round once in thirty-six thousand years is the same as the daily revolution which the sun performs in twenty-four hours. If now your adversary says that this is plainly impossible, in what does your argument differ from his? And suppose it is asked: Are the numbers of these revolutions even or uneven or both even and uneven or neither even nor uneven? If you answer, both even and uneven, or neither even nor uneven, you say what is evidently absurd. If, however, you say ‘even’ or ‘uneven’, even and uneven become uneven and even by the addition of one unit and how could infinity be one unit short? You must, therefore, draw the conclusion that they are neither even nor uneven.
I say:
This
too is a sophistical argument. It amounts to saying: In the same way as you
are unable to refute our argument for the creation of the world in time,
that if it were eternal, its revolutions would be neither even nor uneven, so we
cannot refute your theory that the effect of an agent whose conditions
to act are always fulfilled cannot be delayed. This argument aims only at
creating and establishing a ; doubt, which is one of the sophist’s objectives.
But
you, reader of this book, you have already heard the arguments of the
philosophers to establish the eternity of the world and the refutation of the
Ash’arites. Now hear the proofs of the Ash’arites for their refutation and hear
the arguments of the philosophers to refute those proofs in the wording of Ghazali!
[Here, in the Arabic text, the last
passage of Ghazali, which previously was given
only in an abbreviated form, is repeated in full.]
I say:
This
is in brief that, if you imagine two circular movements in one and the same finite
time and imagine then a limited part of these movements in one and the same
finite time, the proportion between the parts of these two circular movements
and between their wholes will be the same. For instance, if the circular
movement of Saturn in t the period which we call a year is a thirtieth of the
circular movement of the sun in this period, and you imagine the whole of the
circular movements of the sun in proportion to the whole of the circular
movements of Saturn in one and the same period, necessarily the proportion
between their wholes and between their parts will be the same. If, however,
there is no proportion between two movements in their totality, because they
are both potential, i.e. they have neither beginning nor end but there exists a
proportion between the parts, because they are both actual, then the proportion
between the wholes is not necessarily the same as the proportion between the
parts-although many think so, basing their proof on this prejudice -for
there is no proportion between two magnitudes or quantities which are both
taken to be infinite. When, therefore, the ancients believed that, for
instance, the totality of the movements of the sun and of Saturn had neither
beginning nor end, there could be no proportion between them, for this would
have implied the finitude of both these totalities, just as this is implied for
the parts of both. This is self-evident. Our adversaries believe that,
when a proportion of more and less exists between parts, this proportion holds
good also for the totalities, but this is only binding when the totalities are
finite. For where there is no end there is neither ‘more’ nor ‘less’. The
admission in such a case of the proportion of more and less brings with it
another absurd consequence, namely that one infinite could be greater than
another. This is only absurd when one supposes two things actually infinite,
for then a proportion does exist between them. When, however, one imagines
things potentially infinite, there exists no proportion at all. This is the
right answer to this question, not what Ghazali
says in the name of the philosophers.
And
through this are solved all the difficulties which beset our adversaries on
this question, of which the greatest is that which they habitually formulate in
this way: If the movements in the past are infinite, then no movement in the
actual present can take place, unless an infinite number of preceding movements
is terminated., This is true, and acknowledged by the philosophers, once
granted that the anterior movement is the condition for the posterior
movement’s taking place, i.e. once granted that the existence of one single
movement implies an infinite number of causes. But no philosopher allows the
existence of an infinite number of causes, as accepted by the materialists, for
this would imply the existence of an effect without cause and a motion without
mover. But when the existence of an eternal prime mover had been proved, whose
act cannot be posterior to his being, it followed that there could as little be
a beginning for his act as for his being; otherwise his act would be possible,
not necessary, and he would not be a first principle.’ The acts of an agent who
has no beginning have a beginning as little as his existence, and therefore it
follows necessarily that no preceding act of his is the condition for the
existence of a later, for neither of them is an agent by itself and their
sequence is accidental. An accidental infinite, not an essential infinite, is
admitted by the philosophers; nay, this type of infinite is in fact a necessary
consequence of the existence of an eternal first principle., And this is not
only true for successive or continuous movements and the like, but even where
the earlier is regarded as the cause of the later, for instance the man who
engenders a man like himself. For it is necessary that the series of temporal
productions of one individual man by another should lead upwards to an eternal
agent, for whom there is no beginning either of his existence or of his
production of man out of man. The production of one man by another ad infinitum is accidental, whereas the relation of before and after in it
is essential. The agent who has no beginning either for his existence or for
those acts of his which he performs without an instrument, has no first
instrument either to perform those acts of his without beginning which by their
nature need an instrument .
But
since the theologians mistook the accidental for the essential, they denied
this eternal agent; the solution of their problem was difficult and they
believed this proof to be stringent. But this theory of the philosophers is
clear, and their first master Aristotle has explained that, if motion were
produced by motion, or element by element, motion and element could not exists For
this type of infinite the philosophers admit neither a beginning nor an end,
and therefore one can never say of anything in this series that it has ended or
has begun, not even in the past, for everything that has an end must have begun
and what does not begin does not end. This can also be understood from the fact
that beginning and end are correlatives. Therefore one who affirms that there
is no end of the celestial revolutions in the future cannot logically ascribe a
beginning to them, for what has a beginning has an end and what has no end has
no beginning, and the same relation exists between first and last; i.e. what
has a first term has also a last term, and what has no first term has no last
term, and there is in reality neither end nor beginning for any part of a
series that has no last term, and what has no beginning for any of its parts
has no end for any of them either. When, therefore, the theologians ask the
philosophers if the movements which precede the present one are ended, their
answer is negative, for their assumption that they have no beginning implies
their endlessness. The opinion of the theologians that the philosophers admit
their end is erroneous, for they do not admit an end for what has no
beginning.’ It will be clear to you that neither the arguments of the
theologians for the temporal creation of the world of which Ghazali speaks, nor the arguments of the philosophers
which he includes and describes in his book, suffice to reach absolute evidence
or afford stringent proof. And this is what we have tried to show in this book.
The best answer one can give to him who asks where in the past is the starting-point
of His acts, is: The starting-point of His acts is at the starting-point
of His existence; for neither of them has a beginning.
And
here is the passage of Ghazali in which he sets
forth the defence of the philosophers against the argument built on the
difference in speed of the celestial spheres, and his refutation of their
argument.
Ghazali says:
If one says, ‘The error in your argument consists in your considering those circular movements as an aggregate of units, but those movements have no real existence, for the past is no more and the future not yet; “aggregate” means units existing in the present, but in this case there is no existence.’
Then
he says to refute this:
We answer: Number can be divided into even and uneven; there is no third possibility, whether for the numbered permanent reality, or for the numbered passing event. Therefore whatever number we imagine, we must believe it to be even or uneven, whether we regard it as existent or non-existent; and if the thing numbered vanishes from existence, our judgement of its being even or uneven does not vanish or change.
I say:
This is the end of his argument. But this argument-that the numbered thing must be judged as even or uneven, whether it exists or not-is only valid so far as it concerns external things or things in the soul that have a beginning and an end. For of the number which exists only potentially, i.e. which has neither beginning nor end, it cannot truly be said that it is even or uneven, or that it begins or ends; it happens neither in the past nor in the future, for what exists potentially falls under the law of non-existence. This is what the philosophers meant when they said that the circular movements of the past and the future are non-existent. The upshot of this question is: Everything that is called a limited aggregate with a beginning and an end is so called either because it has a beginning and end in the world exterior to the soul, or because it is inside, not outside, the soul. Every totality, actual and limited in the past, whether inside or outside the soul, is necessarily either even or uneven. But an unlimited aggregate existing outside the soul cannot be other than limited so far as it is represented in the soul, for the soul cannot represent unlimited existence. Therefore also this unlimited aggregate, as being limited in the soul, can be called even or uneven; in so far, however, as it exists outside the soul, it can be called neither even nor uneven. Equally, past aggregates which are considered to exist potentially outside the soul, i.e. which have no beginning, cannot be called even or uneven unless they are looked upon as actual, i.e. as having beginning and end. No motion possesses totality or forms an aggregate, i.e. is provided with a beginning or an end, except in so far as it is in the soul, as is the case with time.’ And it follows from the nature of circular movement that it is neither even nor uneven except as represented in the soul. The cause of this mistake is that it was believed that, when something possesses a certain quality in the soul, it must possess this quality also outside the soul, and, since anything that has happened in the past can only be represented in the soul as finite, it was thought that everything that has happened in the past must also be finite outside the soul. And as the circular movements of the future are regarded by the imagination as infinite, for it represents them as a sequence of part after part, Plato and the Ash’arites believed that they might be infinite, but this is simply a judgement based on imagination, not on proof. Therefore those who believe-as many theologians have done-that, if the world is supposed to have begun, it must have an end, are truer to their principles and show more consistency.
Ghazali says after this:
And we say moreover to the philosophers: According to your principles it is not absurd that there should be actual units, qualitatively differentiated, which are infinite in number; I am thinking of human souls, separated through death from their bodies. These are therefore realities that can neither be called even nor uneven. How will you refute the man who affirms that this is necessarily absurd in the same way as you claim the connexion between an eternal will and a temporal creation to be necessarily absurd? This theory about souls is that which Avicenna accented. and it is perhaps Aristotle’s.
I say:
This
argument is extremely weak. It says, in brief, ‘You philosophers need not
refute our assertion that what is a logical necessity for you is not necessary,
as you consider things possible which your adversaries consider impossible by
the necessity of thought. That is to say, just as you consider things possible
which your adversaries consider impossible, so you consider things necessary
which your adversaries do not consider so. And you cannot bring a criterion for
judging the two claims.’ It has already been shown in the science of logic that
this is a weak rhetorical or sophistical kind of argument., The answer is that
what we claim to be necessarily true is objectively true, whereas what you
claim as necessarily absurd is not as you claim it to be. For this there is no
other criterion than immediate intuitive apprehension, just as, when one man
claims that a line is rhythmical and another denies it, the criterion is the
intuition of the sound understanding.
As
for the thesis of a numerical plurality of immaterial souls, this is not a
theory acknowledged by the philosophers, for they regard matter as the cause of
numerical plurality and form as the cause of congruity in numerical plurality.
And that there should be a numerical plurality without matter, having one
unique form, is impossible. For in its description one individual can only be
distinguished from another accidentally, as there is often another individual
who participates in this descriptions but only through their matter do
individuals differ in reality. And also this: the impossibility of an actual
infinite is an acknowledged axiom in philosophical theory, equally valid for
material and immaterial things. We do not know of any one who makes a
distinction here between the spatial and the non-spatial, with the single
exception of Avicenna. I do not know of any other philosopher who affirms this,
it does not correspond with any of their principles and it makes no sense, for
the philosophers deny the existence of an actual infinite equally for material
and for immaterial things, as it would imply that one infinite could be greater
than another. Perhaps Avicenna wanted only to satisfy the masses, telling them
what they were accustomed to hear about the soul. But this theory is far from
satisfactory. For if there were an actual infinite and it were divided in two,
the part would equal the whole; e.g. if there were a line or a number actually
infinite in both directions and it were divided in two, both the parts and the
whole would be actually infinite; and this is absurd. All this is simply the
consequence of the admission of an actual and not potential infinite.
Ghazali
says:
If it is said, ‘The truth lies with Plato’s theory of one eternal soul which is only divided in bodies and returns after its separation from them to its original unity’, we answer: This theory is still worse, more objectionable and more apt to be regarded as contrary to the necessity of thought. For we say that the soul of Zaid is either identical with the soul of Amr or different from it; but their identity would mean something absurd, for everyone is conscious of his own identity and knows that he is not another, and, were they identical, their knowledge, which is an essential quality of their souls and enters into all the relations into which their souls enter, would be identical too. If you say their soul is unique and only divided through its association with bodies, we answer that the division of a unity which has no measurable volume is absurd by the necessity of thought. And how could the one become two, and indeed a thousand, and then return to its unity? This can be understood of things which have volume and quantity, like the water of the sea which is distributed into brooks and rivers and flows then back again into the sea, but how can that which has no quantity be divided? We seek to show by all this that the philosophers cannot shake the conviction of their adversaries that the eternal Will is connected with temporal creation, except by claiming its absurdity by the necessity of thought, and that therefore they are in no way different from the theologians who make the same claim against the philosophical doctrines opposed to theirs. And out of this there is no issue.
I say:
Zaid and Amr are numerically different, but identical in form. If, for example, the soul of Zaid were numerically different from the soul of Amr in the way Zaid is numerically different from Amr, the soul of Zaid and the soul of Amr would be numerically two, but one in their form, and the soul would possess another soul. The necessary conclusion is therefore that the soul of Zaid and the soul of Amr are identical in their form. An identical form inheres in a numerical, i.e. a divisible, multiplicity, only through the multiplicity of matter. If then the soul does not die when the body dies, or if it possesses an immortal element, it must, when it has left the bodies, form a numerical unity. But this is not the place to go deeper into this subject.
His argument against Plato is sophistical. It says in short that the soul of Zaid is either identical with the soul of Amr or different from it; but that the soul of Zaid is not identical with the soul of Amr and that therefore it is different from it. But ‘different’ is an equivocal term, and ‘identity’ too is predicated of a number of things which are also called ‘different’. The souls of Zaid and Amr are one in one sense and many in another; we might say, one in relation to their form, many in relation to their substratum. His remark that division can only be imagined of the quantitative is partially false; it is true of essential division, but not of accidental division, i.e. of those things which can be divided, because they exist in the essentially divisible. The essentially divisible is, for example, body; accidental division is, for instance, the division of whiteness, when the bodies in which it is present are divided, and in this way the forms and the soul are accidentally divisible, i.e. through the division of the substrate. The soul is closely similar to light: light is divided by the division of illuminated bodies, and is unified when the bodies are annihilated, and this same relation holds between soul and bodies. To advance such sophistical arguments is dishonest, for it may be supposed that he is not a man to have overlooked the points mentioned. What he said, he said only to flatter the masses of his times, but how far removed is such an attitude from the character of those who seek to set forth the truth! But perhaps the man may be forgiven on account of the time and place in which he lived; and indeed he only proceeded in his books in a tentative way.
And as these arguments carry no evidence whatsoever, Ghazali says:
We want to show by all this that the philosophers cannot shake the conviction of their adversaries that the eternal Will is connected with temporal creation, by claiming its absurdity by the necessity of thought, and that therefore they do not distinguish themselves from the theologians, who make the same claim against the philosophical doctrines opposed to theirs. And out of this there is no issue.
I say:
When someone denies a truth of which it is absolutely certain that it is such-and-such, there exists no argument by which we can come to an understanding with him; for every argument is based on known premisses about which both adversaries agree. When each point advanced is denied by the adversary, discussion with him becomes impossible, but such people stand outside the pale of humanity and have to be educated. But for him who denies an evident truth, t because of a difficulty which presents itself to him there is a remedy, i.e. the solution of this difficulty. He who does not understand evident truth, because he is lacking in intelligence, cannot be taught anything, nor can he be educated. It is like trying to make the blind imagine colours or know their existence.
Ghazali
says:
The philosophers may object: This argument (that the present has been preceded by an infinite past) can be turned against you, for God before the creation of the world was able to create it, say, one year or two years before He did, and there is no limit to His power; but He seemed to have patience and did not create. Then He created. Now, the duration of His inactivity is either finite or infinite. If you say finite, the existence of the Creator becomes finite; if you say infinite, a duration in which there is an infinite number of possibilities receives its termination. We answer: Duration and time are, according to us, created, but we shall explain the real answer to this question when we reply to the second proof of the philosophers.
I say:
Most people who accept a temporal creation of the world believe time to have been created with it. Therefore his assertion that the duration of His inactivity was either limited or unlimited is untrue. For what has no beginning does not finish or end. And the opponent does not admit that the inactivity has any duration at all. What one has to ask them about the consequences of their theory is: Is it possible, when the creation of time is admitted, that the term of its beginning may lie beyond the real time in which we live? If they answer that it is not possible, they posit a limited extension beyond which the Creator cannot pass, and this is, in their view, shocking and absurd. If, however, they concede that its possible beginning may lie beyond the moment of its created term, it may further be asked if there may not lie another term beyond this second. If they answer in the affirmative-and they cannot do otherwise-it will be said: Then we shall have here a possible creation of an infinite number of durations, and you will be forced to admit-according to your argument about the spherical revolutions-that their termination is a condition for the real age which exists since them. If you say what is infinite does not finish, the arguments you use about the spherical revolutions against your opponents your opponents will use against you on the subject of the possibility of created durations. If it is objected that the difference between those two cases is that these infinite possibilities belong to extensions which do not become actual, whereas the spherical revolutions do become actual, the answer is that the possibilities of things belong to their necessary accidents and that it does not make any difference, according to the philosophers, if they precede these things or are simultaneous with them, for of necessity they are the dispositions of things. If, then, it is impossible that before the existence of the present spherical revolution there should have been infinite spherical revolutions, the existence of infinite possible revolutions is equally impossible. If one wants to avoid these consequences, one can say that the age of the world is a definite quantity and cannot be longer or shorter than it is, in conformity with the philosophical doctrine about the size of the world. Therefore these arguments are not stringent, and the safest way for him who accepts the temporal creation of the world is to regard time as of a definite extension and not to admit a possibility which precedes the possible; and to regard also the spatial extension of the world as finite. Only, spatial extension forms a simultaneous whole; not so time.
Ghazali expounds a certain kind of argument
attributed to the philosophers on this subject against the theologians when
they denied that the impossibility of delay in the Creator’s act after His
existence is known by primitive intuition:
How will you defend yourselves, theologians, against the philosophers, when they drop this argument, based on the necessity of thought, and prove the eternity of the world in this way, saying that times are equivalent so far as the possibility that the Divine Will should attach itself to them is concerned, for what differentiates a given time from an earlier or a later time? And it is not absurd to believe that the earlier or the later might be chosen when on the contrary you theologians say about white, black, movement, and rest that the white is realized through the eternal Will although its substrate accepts equally black and white. Why, then, does the eternal Will attach itself to the white rather than to the black, and what differentiates one of the two possibles from the other for connexion with the eternal Will? But we philosophers know by the necessity of thought that one thing does not distinguish itself from a similar except by a differentiating principle, for if not, it would be possible that the world should come into existence, having the possibility both of existing and of not existing, and that the side of existence, although it has the same possibility as the side of non-existence, should be differentiated without a differentiating principle. If you answer that the Will of God is the differentiating principle, then one has to inquire what differentiates the Will, i.e. the reason why it has been differentiated in such or such way. And if you answer: One does not inquire after the motives of the Eternal, well, let the world then be eternal, and let us not inquire after its Creator and its cause, since one does not inquire after the motives of the Eternal! If it is regarded as possible that the Eternal should differentiate one of the two possibles by chance, it will be an extreme absurdity to say that the world is differentiated in differentiated forms which might just as well be otherwise, and one might then say that this has happened by chance in the same way as you say that the Divine Will has differentiated one time rather than another or one form rather than another by chance. If you say that such a question is irrelevant, because it refers to anything God can will or decide, we answer that this question is quite relevant, for it concerns any time and is pertinent for our opponents to any decision God takes.
We answer: The world exists, in the way it exists, in its time, with its qualities, and in its space, by the Divine Will and will is a quality which has the faculty of differentiating one thing from another,’ and if it had not this faculty, power in itself would suffice But, since power is equally related to two contraries’ and a differentiating principle is needed to differentiate one thing from a similar, it is said that the Eternal possesses besides His power a quality which can differentiate between two similars. And to ask why will differentiates one of two similars is like asking why knowledge must comprehend the knowable, and the answer is that ‘knowledge’ is the term for a quality which has just this nature. And in the same way, ‘will’ is the term for a quality the nature or rather the essence of which is to differentiate one thing from another.
The philosophers may object: The assumption of a quality the nature of which is to differentiate one thing from a similar one is something incomprehensible, nay even contradictory, for ‘similar’ means not to be differentiated, and ‘differentiated’ means not similar. And it must not be believed that two blacks in two substrates are similar in every way, since the one is in one place and the other in another, and this causes a distinction; nor are two blacks at two times in one substrate absolutely similar, since they are separated in time, and how could they therefore be similar in every way? When we say of two blacks that they are similar, we mean that they are similar in blackness, in their special relation to it-not absolutely. Certainly, if the substrate and the time were one without any distinction, one could not speak any more of two blacks or of any duality at all. This proves that the term ‘Divine Will’ is derived from our will, and one does not imagine that through our will two similar things can be differentiated.’ On the contrary, if someone who is thirsty has before him two cups of water, similar in everything in respect to his aim, it will not be possible for him to take either of them. No, he can only take the one he thinks more beautiful or lighter or nearer to his right hand, if he is right-handed, or act from some such reason, hidden or known. Without this the differentiation of the one from the other cannot be imagined.
I say:
The
summary of what Ghazali relates in this section
of the proofs of the philosophers for the impossibility of a temporal
proceeding from an eternal agent is that in God there cannot be a will. The
philosophers could only arrive at this argument after granting to their
opponents that all opposites-opposites in time,b like anterior and
posterior, as well as those in quality, like white and black-are
equivalent in relation to the eternal Will. And also non-existence and
existence are, according to the theologians, equivalent in relation to the
Divine Will. And having granted their opponents this premiss, although they did
not acknowledge its truth, they said to them: It is of the nature of will that
it cannot give preponderance to one thing rather than to a similar one, except
through a differentiating principle and a cause which only exist in one of
these two similar things; if not, one of the two would happen by chance-and
the philosophers argued for the sake of discussion, as if they had conceded
that, if the Eternal had a will, a temporal could proceed from an eternal. As
the theologians were unable to give a satisfactory answer, they took refuge in
the theory that the eternal Will is a quality the nature of which is to
differentiate between two similar things, without there being for God a
differentiating principle which inclines Him to one of two similar acts; that
the eternal Will is thus a quality like warmth which gives heat or like
knowledge which comprehends the knowable. But their opponents, the philosophers,
answered: It is impossible that this should happen, for two similar things are
equivalent for the wilier, and his action can only attach itself to the one
rather than to the other through their being dissimilar, i.e. through one’s
having a quality the other has not. When, however, they are similar in every
way and when for God there is no differentiating principle at all, His will
will attach itself to both of them indifferently and, when this is the case-His
will being the cause of His act-the act will not attach itself to the one
rather than to the other, it will attach itself either to the two contrary
actions simultaneously or to neither of them at all, and both cases are absurd.
The philosophers, therefore, began their argument, as if they had it granted to
them that all things were equivalent in relation to the First Agent, and they
forced them to admit that there must be for God a differentiating principle
which precedes Him, which is absurd. When the theologians answered that will is
a quality the nature of which is to differentiate the similar from the similar,
in so far as it is similar, the philosophers objected that this is not
understood or meant by the idea of will. They therefore appear to reject the
principle which they granted them in the beginning.’ This is in short the
content of this section. It waves the argument from the original question to
the problem of the will; to shift one’s ground, however, is an act of
sophistry.
Ghazali answers in defence of the theological
doctrine of the Divine Will:
There are two objections: First, as to your affirmation that you cannot imagine this, do you know it by the necessity of thought or through deduction? You can claim neither the one nor the other. Your comparison with our will is a bad analogy, which resembles that employed on the question of God’s knowledge. Now God’s knowledge is different from ours in several ways which we acknowledge. Therefore it is not absurd to admit a difference in the will. Your affirmation is like saying that an essence existing neither outside nor inside the world, neither continuous with the world nor separated from it, cannot be understood, because we cannot understand this according to our human measure; the right answer is that it is the fault of your imagination, for rational proof has led the learned to accept its truth. How, then, will you refute those who say that rational proof has led to establishing in God a quality the nature of which is to differentiate between two similar things? And, if the word ‘will’ does not apply, call it by another name, for let us not quibble about words! We only use the term ‘will’ by permission of the Divine Law. It may be objected that by its conventional meaning ‘will’ designates that which has desire, and God has no desire, but we are concerned here with a question not of words but of fact. Besides, we do not even with respect to our human will concede that this cannot be imagined. Suppose two similar dates in front of a man who has a strong desire for them, but who is unable to take them both. Surely he will take one of them through a quality in him the nature of which is to differentiate between two similar things. All the distinguishing qualities you have mentioned, like beauty or nearness or facility in taking, we can assume to be absent, but still the possibility of the taking remains. You can choose between two answers: either you merely say that an equivalence in respect to his desire cannot be imagined-but this is a silly answer, for to assume it is indeed possible or you say that if an equivalence is assumed, the man will remain for ever hungry and perplexed, looking at the dates without taking one of them, and without a power to choose or to will, distinct from his desire. And this again is one of those absurdities which are recognized by the necessity of thought. Everyone, therefore, who studies, in the human and the divine, the real working of the act of choice, must necessarily admit a quality the nature of which is to differentiate between two similar things.
I say:
This
objection can be summarized in two parts: In the first Ghazali
concedes that the human will is such that it is unable to differentiate one
thing from a similar one, in so far as it is similar, but that a rational proof
forces us to accept the existence of such a quality in the First Agent. To
believe that such a quality cannot exist would be like believing that there
cannot exist a being who is neither inside nor outside the world. According to
this reasoning, will, which is attributed to the First Agent and to man, is
predicated in an equivocal way, like knowledge and other qualities which exist
in the Eternal in a different way from that in which they exist in the
temporal, and it is only through the prescription of the Divine Law that we
speak of the Divine Will. It is clear that this objection cannot have anything
more than a dialectical value. For a proof that could demonstrate the existence
of such a quality, i.e. a principle determining the existence of one thing
rather than that of a similar, would have to assume things willed that are
similar; things willed are, however, not similar, but on the contrary opposite,
for all opposites can be reduced to the opposition of being and not being,
which is the extreme form of opposition; and opposition is the contrary of
similarity. The assumption of the theologians that the things to which the will
attaches itself are similar is a false one, and we shall speak of it later. If
they say: we affirm only that they are similar in relation to the First Wilier,
who in His holiness is too exalted to possess desires, and it is through
desires that two similar things are actually differentiated, we answer: as to
the desires whose realization contributes to the perfection of the essence of
the wilier, as happens with our desires, through which our will attaches itself
to the things willed-those desires are impossible in God, for the will
which acts in this way is a longing for perfection when there is an
imperfection in the essence of the wilier; but as to the desires which belong
to the essence of the things willed, nothing new comes to the wilier from their
realization. It comes exclusively to the thing willed, for instance, when a
thing passes into existence from non-existence, for it cannot be doubted
that existence is better for it than non-existence. It is in this second
way that the Primal Will is related to the existing things, for it chooses for
them eternally the better of two opposites, and this essentially and primally.
This is the first part of the objection contained in this argument.
In
the second part he no longer concedes that this quality cannot exist in the
human will, but tries to prove that there is also in us, in the face of similar
things, a will which distinguishes one from the other; of this he gives
examples. For instance, it is assumed that in front of a man there are two
dates, similar in every way, and it is supposed that he cannot take them both
at the same time. It is supposed that no special attraction need be imagined
for him in either of them, and that nevertheless he will of necessity
distinguish one of them by taking it. But this is an error. For, when one
supposes such a thing, and a wilier whom necessity prompts to eat or to take
the date, then it is by no means a matter of distinguishing between two similar
things when, in this condition, he takes one of the two dates. It is nothing
but the admission of an equivalence of two similar things; for whichever of the
two dates he may take, his aim will be attained and his desire satisfied. His
will attaches itself therefore merely to the distinction between the fact of
taking one of them and the fact of leaving them altogether; it attaches itself
by no means to the act of taking one definite date and distinguishing this act
from the act of leaving the other (that is to say, when it is assumed that the
desires for the two are equal); he does not prefer the act of taking the one to
the act of taking the other, but he prefers the act of taking one of the two,
whichever it may be, and he gives a preference to the act of taking over the
act of leaving.’ This is self-evident. For distinguishing one from the
other means giving a preference to the one over the other, and one cannot give
a preponderance to one of two similar things in so far as it is similar to the
other-although in their existence as individuals they are not similar
since each of two individuals is different from the other by reason of a
quality exclusive to it. If, therefore, we assume that the will attaches itself
to that special character of one of them, then it can be imagined that the will
attaches to the.-one rather than the other because of the element of
difference existing in both. But then the will does not attach itself to two
similar objects, in so far as they are similar. This is, in short, the meaning
of Ghazali’s first objection. Then he gives his
second objection against those who deny the existence of a quality,
distinguishing two similar objects from one another.
Ghazali
says:
The second objection is that we say: You in your system also are unable to do without a principle differentiating between two equals, for the world exists in virtue of a cause which has produced it in its peculiar shape out of a number of possible distinct shapes which are equivalent; why, then, has this cause differentiated some of them? If to distinguish two similar things is impossible, it is irrelevant whether this concerns the act of God, natural causality, or the logical necessity of ideas. Perhaps you will say: the universal order of the world could not be different from what it is; if the world were smaller or bigger than it actually is, this order would not be perfect, and the same may be asserted of the number of spheres and of stars. And perhaps you will say: The big differs from the small and the many from the few, in so far as they are the object of the will, and therefore they are not similar but different; but human power is too feeble to perceive the modes of Divine Wisdom in its determination of the measures and qualities of things; only in some of them can His wisdom be perceived, as in the obliquity of the ecliptic in relation to the equator, and in the wise contrivance of the apogee and the eccentric sphere.’ In most cases, however, the secret is not revealed, but the differences are known, and it is not impossible that a thing should be distinguished from another, because the order of the world depends on it; but certainly the times are absolutely indifferent in relation to the world’s possibility and its order, and it cannot be claimed that, if the world were created one moment later or earlier, this order could not be imagined; and this indifference is known by the necessity of thought.-But then we answer: Although we can employ the same reasoning against your argument in the matter of different times, for it might be said that God created the world at the time most propitious for its creation, we shall not limit ourselves to this refutation, but shall assume, according to your own principle, a differentiation in two points about which there can be no disagreement: (1) the difference in the direction of spherical movement; (2) the definite place of the poles in relation to the ecliptic in spherical movement. The proof of the statement relating to the poles is that heaven is a globe, moving on two poles, as on two immovable points, whereas the globe of heaven is homogeneous and simple, especially the highest sphere, the ninth, which possesses no stars at all, and these two spheres move on two poles, the north and the south. We now say: of all the opposite points, which are infinite, according to you philosophers, there is no pair one could not imagine as poles. Why then have the two points of the north and south pole been fixed upon as poles and as immovable; and why does the ecliptic not pass through these two poles, so that the poles would become the opposite points of the ecliptic? And if wisdom is shown in the size and shape of heaven, what then distinguishes the place of the poles from others, so that they are fixed upon to serve as poles, to the exclusion of all the other parts and points? And yet all the points are similar, and all parts of the globe are equivalent. And to this there is no answer.
One might say: Perhaps the spot in which the point of the poles is, is distinguished from other points by a special quality, in relation to its being the place of the poles and to its being at rest, for it does not seem to change its place or space or position or whatever one wishes to call it; and all the other spots of the sphere by turning change their position in relation to the earth and the other spheres and only the poles are at rest; perhaps this spot was more apt to be at rest than the others. We answer: If you say so, you explain the fact through a natural differentiation of the parts of the first sphere; the sphere, then, ceases to be homogeneous, and this is in contradiction with your principle, for one of the proofs by which you prove the necessity of the globular shape of heaven, is that its nature is simple, homogeneous, and without differentiation, and the simplest shape is the globe; for the quadrangle and the hexagon and other figures demand a salience and a differentiation of the angles,’ and this happens only when its simple nature is added to. But although this supposition of yours is in contradiction with your own theory, it does not break the strength of your opponents’ argument; the question about this special quality still holds good, namely, can those other parts accept this quality or not? If the answer is in the affirmative, why then is this quality limited to a few only of those homogeneous parts? If the answer is negative, we reply: the other parts, in so far as they constitute bodies, receiving the form of bodies, are homogeneous of necessity, and there is no justification for attributing this special quality to this spot exclusively on account of its being a part of a body and a part of heaven, for the other parts of heaven participate in this qualification. Therefore its differentiation must rest on a decision by God, or on a quality whose nature consists in differentiating between two similars. Therefore, just as among philosophers the theory is upheld that all times are equivalent in regard to the creation of the world, their opponents are justified in claiming that the parts of heaven are equivalent for the reception of the quality through which stability in position becomes more appropriate than a change of position. And out of this there is no issue.
I say:
This
means in brief that the philosophers must acknowledge that there is a quality
in the Creator of the world which differentiates between two similars, for it
seems that the world might have had another shape and another quantity than it
actually has, for it might have been bigger or smaller. Those different possibilities
are, therefore, equivalent in regard to the determination of the existence of
the world. On the other hand, if the philosophers say that the world can have
only one special shape, the special quantity of its bodies and the special
number of them it actually has, and that this equivalence of possibilities can
only be imagined in relation to the times of temporal creation-since for
God no moment is more suitable than another for its creation-they may be
told that it is possible to answer this by saying that the creation of the
world happened at its most propitious moment. But we, the theologians say, want
to show the philosophers two equivalent things of which they cannot affirm that
there exists any difference between them; the first is the particular direction
of the spherical movement and the second the particular position of the poles,
relative to the spheres; for any pair whatever of opposite points, united by a
line which passes through the centre of the sphere, might constitute the poles.
But the differentiation of these two points, exclusive of all other points
which might just as well be the poles of this identical sphere cannot happen
except by a quality differentiating between two similar objects. If the
philosophers assert that it is not true that any other place on the sphere
might be the seat for these poles, they will be told: such an assertion implies
that the parts of the spheres are not homogeneous and yet you have often said
that the sphere is of a simple nature and therefore has a simple form, viz. the
spherical. And again, if the philosophers affirm that there are spots on the
sphere which are not homogeneous, it will be asked how these spots came to be
of a heterogeneous nature; is it because they are a body or because they are a
celestial body? But the absence of homogeneity cannot be explained in this way.
Therefore-Ghazali says just as among
philosophers the theory is upheld that all times are equivalent in regard to
the creation of the world, the theologians are justified in claiming that the
parts of heaven are equivalent in regard to their serving as poles, and that
the poles do not seem differentiated from the other points through a special
position or through their being in an immovable place, exclusive of all other
places.
This
then in short is the objection; it is, however, a rhetorical one, for many
things which by demonstration can be found to be necessary seem at first sight
merely possible.’ The philosophers’ answer is that they assert that they have
proved that the world is composed of five bodies: a body neither heavy nor
light, i.e. the revolving spherical body of heaven and four other bodies, two
of which are earth, absolutely heavy, which is the centre of the revolving
spherical body, and fire, absolutely light, which is seated in the extremity of
the revolving sphere; nearest to earth is water, which is heavy relatively to
air, light relatively to earth; next to water comes air, which is light
relatively to water, heavy relatively to fire. The reason why earth is absolutely
heavy is that it is farthest away from the circular movement, and therefore it
is the fixed centre of the revolving body; the reason why fire is absolutely
light is that it is nearest to the revolving sphere; the intermediate bodies
are both heavy and light, because they are in the middle between the two
extremes, i.e. the farthest point and the nearest. If there were not a
revolving body, surely there would be neither heavy nor light by nature, and
neither high nor low by nature, and this whether absolutely or relatively; and
the bodies would not differ by nature in the way in which, for instance, earth
moves by nature to its specific place and fire moves by nature to another
place, and equally so the intermediary bodies. And the world is only finite,
because of the spherical body, and this because of the essential and natural
finiteness of the spherical body, as one single plane circumscribes it.’
Rectilinear bodies are not essentially finite, as they allow of an increase and
decrease; they are only finite because they are in the middle of a body that
admits neither increase nor decrease, and is therefore essentially finite. And,
therefore, the body circumscribing the world cannot but be spherical, as
otherwise the bodies would either have to end in other bodies, and we should
have an infinite regress, or they would end in empty space, and the
impossibility of both suppositions has been demonstrated. He who understands
this knows that every possible world imaginable can only consist of these bodies,
and that bodies have to be either circular-and then they are neither
heavy nor light-or rectilinear-and then they are either heavy or
light, i.e. either fire or earth or the intermediate bodies; that these bodies
have to be either revolving, or surrounded by a revolving periphery, for each
body either moves from, towards, or round the centre; that by the movements of
the heavenly bodies to the right and to the left all bodies are constituted and
all that is produced from opposites is generated; and that through these
movements the individuals of these four bodies never cease being in a continual
production and corruption. Indeed, if a single one of these movements should
cease, the order and proportion of this universe would disappear, for it is
clear that this order must necessarily depend on the actual number of these
movements-for if this were smaller or greater, either the order would be
disturbed, or there would be another order-and that the number of these
movements is as it is, either through its necessity for the existence of this
sublunary world, or because it is the best .
Do
not ask here for a proof for all this, but if you are interested in science,
look for its proof, where you can find it. Here, however, listen to theories
which are more convincing than those of the theologians and which, even if they
do not bring you complete proof, will give your mind an inclination to lead you
to proof through scientific speculation. You should imagine that each heavenly
sphere is a living being, in so far as it possesses a body of a definite
measure and shape and moves itself in definite directions, not at random.
Anything of this nature is necessarily a living being; i.e. when we see a body
of a definite quality and quantity move itself in space, in a definite
direction, not at random, through its own power, not through an exterior cause,
and move in opposite directions at the same time, we are absolutely sure that
it is a living being, and we said only ‘not through an exterior cause’ because
iron moves towards a magnet when the magnet is brought to it from the outside-and
besides, iron moves to a magnet from any direction whatever., The heavenly
bodies, therefore, possess places which are poles by nature, and these bodies
cannot have their poles in other places, just as earthly animals have
particular organs in particular parts of their bodies for particular actions,
and cannot have them in other places, e.g. the organs of locomotion, which are
located in definite parts. The poles represent the organs of locomotion in
animals of spherical form, and the only difference in this respect between
spherical and non-spherical animals is that in the latter these organs
differ in both shape and power, whereas in the former they only differ in
power. For this reason it has been thought on first sight that they do not
differ at all, and that the poles could be in any two points on the sphere. And
just as it would be ridiculous to say that a certain movement in a certain
species of earthly animal could be in any part whatever of its body, or in that
part where it is in another species, because this movement has been localized
in each species in the place where it conforms most to its nature, or in the
only place where this animal can perform the movement, so it stands with the
differentiation in the heavenly bodies for the place of their poles. For the
heavenly bodies are not one species and numerically many, but they form a
plurality in species, like the plurality of different individuals of animals
where there is only one individual in the species.
Exactly
the same answer can be given to the question why the heavens move in different
directions: that, because they are animals, they must move in definite
directions, like right and left, before and behind, which are directions
determined by the movements of animals, and the only difference between the
movements of earthly animals and those of heavenly bodies is that in the
different animals these movements are different in shape and in power, whereas
in the heavenly animals they only differ in power. And it is for this reason
that Aristotle thinks that heaven possesses the directions of right and left,
before and behind, high and low. The diversity of the heavenly bodies in the
direction of their movements rests on their diversity of species, and the fact
that this difference in the directions of their movements forms the specific
differentia of their species is something proper to them. Imagine the first
heaven as one identical animal whose nature obliges it-either by
necessity or because it is for the best-to move with all its parts in one
movement from east to west. The other spheres are obliged by their nature to
have the opposite movement. The direction which the body of the universe is
compelled to follow through its nature is the best one, because its body is the
best of bodies and the best among the moving bodies must also have the best
direction. All this is explained here in this tentative way, but is proved
apodictically in its proper place. This is also the manifest sense of the
Divine Words, ‘There is no changing the words of God’, and ‘There is no
altering the creation of God’. If you want to be an educated man, proceeding by
proof, you should look for the proof of this in its proper place.
Now
if you have understood all this, it will not be difficult for you to see the
faults in Ghazali’s arguments here about the
equivalence of the two opposite movements in relation to each heavenly body and
to the sublunary world. On first thoughts it might be imagined that the movement
from east to west might also belong to other spheres besides the first, and
that the first sphere might equally well move from west to east. You might as
well say that the crab could be imagined as having the same direction of
movement as man. But, as a matter of fact, such a thought will not occur to you
about men and crabs, because of their difference in shape, whereas it might
occur to you about the heavenly spheres, since they agree in shape. He who
contemplates a product of art does not perceive its wisdom if he does not
perceive the wisdom of the intention embodied in it, and the effect intended.
And if he does not understand its wisdom, he may well imagine that this object
might have any form, any quantity, any configuration of its parts, and any composition
whatever. This is the case with the theologians in regard to the body of the
heavens, but all such opinions are superficial. He who has such beliefs about
products of art understands neither the work nor the artist, and this holds
also in respect of the works of God’s creation. Understand this principle, and
do not judge the works of God’s creation hastily and superficially-so
that you may not become one of those about whom the Qur’an says: ‘Say, shall we
inform you of those who lose most by their works, those who erred in their
endeavour after the life of this world and who think they are doing good
deeds?’ May God make us perspicacious and lift from us the veils of ignorance;
indeed He is the bounteous, the generous! To contemplate the various actions of
the heavenly bodies is like contemplating the kingdom of heaven, which Abraham
contemplated, according to the words of the Qur’an: ‘Thus did we show Abraham
the kingdom of heaven and of the earth, that he should be of those who are
sure.’ And let us now relate Ghazali’s argument
about the movements.
Ghazali
says:
The second point in this argument concerns the special direction of the movement of the spheres which move partially from east to west, partially in the opposite direction, whereas the equivalence of the directions in relation to their cause is exactly the same as the equivalence of the times. If it is said: If the universe revolved in only one direction, there would never be a difference in the configuration of the stars, and such relations of the stars as their being in trine, in sextile, and in conjunction would, never arise, but the universe would remain in one unique position without any change; the difference of these relations, however, is the principle of all production in the world-we answer: Our argument does not concern the difference in direction of movement; no, we concede that the highest sphere moves from east to west and the spheres beneath it in the opposite direction, but everything that happens in this way would happen equally if the reverse took place, i.e. if the highest sphere moved from west to east and the lower spheres in the opposite direction. For all the same differences in configuration would arise just as well. Granted that these movements are circular and in opposite directions, both directions are equivalent; why then is the one distinguished from the other, which is similar to it?’ If it is said: as the two directions are opposed and contrary, how can they be similar?-we answer: this is like saying ‘since before and after are opposed in the existing world, how could it be claimed that they are equivalent?’ Still, it is asserted by you philosophers that the equivalence of times, so far as the possibility of their realization and any purpose one might imagine in their realization is concerned, is an evident fact. Now, we regard it as equally evident that spaces, positions, situations, and directions are equivalent so far as concerns their receiving movement and any purpose that might be connected with it. If therefore the philosophers are allowed to claim that notwithstanding this equivalence they are different, their opponents are fully justified in claiming the same in regard to the times.
I say:
From
what I have said previously, the speciousness of this argument and the way in
which it has to be answered will not be obscure to you. All this is the work of
one who does not understand the exalted natures of the heavenly bodies and
their acts of wisdom for the sake of which they have been created, and who
compares God’s knowledge with the knowledge of ignorant man.
Ghazali
says:
If it is said: as the two directions are opposed and contrary, how can they be similar?-we answer: this is like saying ‘since before and after in the existing world are opposed, how could it be claimed that they are equivalent?’ Still, it is asserted by you philosophers that the equivalence of times so far as the possibility of their realization, and any purpose one might imagine in their realization is concerned, is an evident fact. Now, we regard it as equally evident that spaces, positions, situations, and directions are equivalent so far as concerns their receiving the movement and any purpose that might be connected with it.
I say:
The
falsehood of this is self-evident. Even if one should admit that the
possibilities of man’s existence and non-existence are equivalent in the
matter out of which he has been created, and that this is a proof for the
existence of a determining principle which prefers his existence to his non-existence,
still it cannot be imagined that the possibilities of seeing and not seeing are
equivalent in the eye. Thus no one can claim that the opposite directions are
equivalent, although he may claim that the substratum for both is indifferent,
and that therefore out of both directions similar actions result. And the same
holds good for before and after: they are not equivalent, in so far as this
event is earlier and that event later; they can only be claimed to be equivalent
so far as their possibility of existence is concerned. But the whole assumption
is wrong: for essential opposites also need essentially opposite substrata and
a unique substratum giving rise to opposite acts at one and the same time is an
impossibility. The philosophers do not believe that the possibilities of a
thing’s existence and of its non-existence are equivalent at one and the
same time; no, the time of the possibility of its existence is different from
the time of the possibility of its non-existence, time for them is the
condition for the production of what is produced, and for the corruption of
what perishes. If the time for the possibility of the existence of a thing and
the time for the possibility of its non-existence were the same, that is
to say in its proximate matter, its existence would be vitiated, because of the
possibility of its non-existence, and the possibility of its existence
and of its non-existence would be dependent only on the agent, not on the
substratum.
Thus
he who tries to prove the existence of an agent in this way gives only
persuasive, dialectical arguments, not apodictic proof. It is believed that
Farabi and Avicenna followed this line to establish that every act must have an
agent, but it is not a proof of the ancient philosophers, and both of them
merely took it over from the theologians of our religion. In relation, however,
to the temporal creation of the world-for him who believes in it-before
and after cannot even be imagined, for before and after in time can only be
imagined in relation to the present moment, and as, according to the
theologians, there was before the creation of the world no time, how could
there be imagined something preceding the moment when the world was created? A
definite moment cannot be assigned for the creation of the world, for either
time did not exist before it, or there was an infinite time, and in neither
case could a definite time be fixed to which the Divine could attach itself.
Therefore it would be more suitable to call this book ‘Incoherence’ without
qualification rather than ‘The Incoherence of the Philosophers’, for the only
profit it gives the reader is to make him incoherent.
Ghazali
says:
If, therefore, the philosophers are allowed to claim that, notwithstanding this equivalence, they are different, their opponents are fully justified in claiming the same in regard to times.
I say:
He
wants to say: If the philosophers are justified in claiming a difference in the
direction of movement, the theologians have the right to assert a difference in
times, notwithstanding their belief in their equivalence. This is only a verbal
argument, and does not refer to the facts themselves, even if one admits an
analogy between the opposite directions and the different times, but this is often
objected to, because there is no analogy between this difference in times and
directions. Our adversary, however, is forced to admit that there is an analogy
between them, because they are both claimed to be different, and both to be
equivalent! These, therefore, are one and all only dialectical arguments.
Ghazali says:
The second objection against the basis of their argument is that the philosophers are told: ‘You regard the creation of a temporal being by an eternal as impossible, but you have to acknowledge it too, for there are new events happening in the world and they have causes. It is absurd to think that these events lead to other events ad infinitum, and no intelligent person can believe such a thing. If such a thing were possible, you need not acknowledge a creator and establish a necessary being on whom possible existences depend. If, however, there is a limit for those events in which their sequence ends, this limit will be the eternal and then indubitably you too acknowledge the principle that a temporal can proceed from an eternal being.’
I say:
If
the philosophers had introduced the eternal being into reality from the side of
the temporal by this kind of argument, i.e. if they had admitted that the
temporal, in so far as temporal, proceeds from an eternal being, there would be
no possibility of their avoiding the difficulty in this problem. But you must
understand that the philosophers permit the existence of a temporal which comes
out of a temporal being ad infinitum in
an accidental way, when this is repeated in a limited and finite matter-when,
for instance, the corruption of one of two things becomes the necessary
condition for the existence of the other. For instance, according to the
philosophers it is necessary that man should be produced from man on condition
that the anterior man perishes so as to become the matter for the production of
a third. For instance, we must imagine two men of whom the first produces the
second from the matter of a man who perishes; when the second becomes a man
himself, the first perishes, then the second man produces a third man out of
the matter of the first, and then the second perishes and the third produces
out of his matter a fourth, and so we can imagine in two matters an activity
continuing ad infinitum, without any
impossibility arising. And this happens as long as the agent lasts, for if this
agent has neither beginning nor end for his existence, the activity has neither
beginning nor end for its existence, as it has been explained before. And in
the same way you may imagine this happening in them in the past: When a man
exists, there must before him have been a man who produced him and a man who
perished, and before this second man a man who produced him and a man who
perished, for everything that is produced in this way is, when it depends on an
eternal agent, of a circular nature in which no actual totality can be reached.
If, on the other hand, a man were produced from another man out of infinite
matters, or there were an infinite addition of them, there would be an
impossibility, for then there could arise an infinite matter and there could be
an infinite whole. For if a finite whole existed to which things were added ad
infinitum without any corruption
taking place in it, an infinite whole could come into existence, as Aristotle
proved in his Physics. For this reason the ancients introduce an eternal
absolutely unchanging being, having in mind not temporal beings, proceeding
from him in so far as they are temporal, but beings proceeding from him as being
eternal generically, and they hold that this infinite series is the necessary
consequence of an eternal agent, for the temporal needs for its own existence
only a temporal cause. Now there are two reasons why the ancients introduce the
existence of an eternal numerically unique being which does not suffer any
change. The first is that they discovered that this revolving being is eternal,
for they discovered that the present individual is produced through the
corruption of its predecessor and that the corruption of this previous
individual implies the production of the one that follows it, and that it is
necessary that this everlasting change should proceed from an eternal mover and
an eternal moved body, which does not change in its substance, but which
changes only in place so far as concerns its parts, and approaches certain of
the transitory things and recedes from certain of them, and this is the cause
of the corruption of one half of them and the production of the other half. And
this heavenly body is the being that changes in place only, not in any of the
other kinds of change, and is through its temporal activities the cause of all
things temporal; and because of the continuity of its activities which have
neither beginning nor end, it proceeds from a cause which has neither beginning
nor end. The second reason why they introduce an eternal being absolutely
without body and matter is that they found that all the kinds of movement
depend on spatial movement, and that spatial movement depends on a being moved
essentially by a prime mover, absolutely unmoved, both essentially and
accidentally, for otherwise there would exist at the same time an infinite
number of moved movers, and this is impossible. And it is necessary that this
first mover should be eternal, or else it would not be the first. Every
movement, therefore, depends on this mover and its setting in motion
essentially, not accidentally. And this mover exists simultaneously with each
thing moved, at the time of its motion, for a mover existing before the thing
moved-such as a man producing a man-sets only in motion
accidentally, not essentially; but the mover who is the condition of man’s
existence from the beginning of his production till its end, or rather from the
beginning of his existence till its end, is the prime mover. And likewise his
existence is the condition for the existence of all beings and the preservation-
of heaven and earth and all that is between them. All this is not proved here
apodictically, but only in the way we follow here and which is in any case more
plausible for an impartial reader than the arguments of our opponents.
If
this is clear to you, you certainly are in no need of the subterfuge by which Ghazali in his argument against the philosophers
tries to conciliate them with their adversaries in this matter; indeed these
artifices will not do, for if you have not understood how the philosophers
introduce an eternal being into reality, you have not understood how they
settle the difficulty of the rise of the temporal out of the eternal; they do
that, as we said, either through the medium of a being eternal in its essence
but generable and corruptible in its particular movements, not, however, in its
universal circular movement, or through the medium of what is generically
eternal-i.e. has neither beginning nor end-in its acts.
Ghazali answers in the name of the philosophers:
The philosophers may say, ‘we do not consider it impossible that any temporal being, whatever it may be, should proceed from an eternal being, but we regard it as impossible that the first temporal should proceed from the eternal, as the mode of its procession does not differ from that which precedes it, either in a greater inclination towards existence or through the presence of some particular time, or through an instrument, condition, nature, accident, or any cause whatever which might produce a new mode. If this therefore is not the first temporal, it will be possible that it should proceed from the eternal, when another thing proceeds from it, because of the disposition of the receiving substratum, or because the time was propitious or for any other reason.
Having
given this reply on the part of the philosophers, Ghazali
answers it:
This question about the actualization of the disposition, whether of the time and of any new condition which arises in it, still holds good, and we must either come to an infinite regress or arrive at an eternal being out of which a first temporal being proceeds.
I say:
This question is the same question all over again as he asked the philosophers first,’ and this is the same kind of conclusion as he made them draw then, namely that a temporal proceeds from an eternal, and having given as their answer something which does not correspond with the question, i.e. that it is possible that a temporal being should proceed from the Eternal without there being a first temporal being, he turns the same question against them again. The correct answer to this question was given above: the temporal proceeds from the First Eternal, not in so far as it is temporal but in so far as it is eternal, i.e. through being eternal generically, though temporal in its parts. For according to the philosophers an eternal being out of which a temporal being proceeds essentially’ is not the First Eternal, but its acts, according to them, depend on the First Eternal; i.e. the actualization of the condition for activity of the eternal, which is not the First Eternal, depends on the First Eternal in the same way as the temporal products depend on the First Eternal and this is a dependence based on the universal, not on individuals.
After
this Ghazali introduces an answer of the
philosophers, in one of the forms in which this theory can be represented,
which amounts to this: A temporal being proceeding from an eternal can only be
represented by means of a circular movement which resembles the eternal by not
having beginning or end and which resembles the temporal in so far as each part
of it is transient, so that this movement through the generation of its parts
is the principle of temporal things, and through the eternity of its totality
the activity of the eternal.
Then
Ghazali argues against this view, according to
which in the opinion of the philosophers the temporal proceeds from the First
Eternal, and says to them:
Is this circular movement temporal or eternal? If it is eternal, how does it become the principle for temporal things? And if it is temporal, it will need another temporal being and we shall have an infinite regress. And when you say that it partially resembles the eternal, partially the temporal, for it resembles the eternal in so far as it is permanent and the temporal in so far as it arises anew, we answer: Is it the principle of temporal things, because of its permanence, or because of its arising anew? In the former case, how can a temporal proceed from something because of its permanence? And in the latter case, what arises anew will need a cause for its arising anew, and we have an infinite regress.
I say:
This argument is sophistical. The temporal does not proceed
from it in so far as it is eternal, but in so far as it is temporal; it does
not need, however, for its arising anew a cause arising anew, for its arising
anew is not a new fact, but is an eternal act, i.e. an act without
o beginning
or end. Therefore its agent must be an eternal agent, for an eternal act has an
eternal agent, and a temporal act a temporal agent. Only through the eternal
element in it can it be understood that movement has neither beginning nor end,
and this is meant by its permanence, for movement itself is not permanent, but
changing.
And since Ghazali knew this, he said:
In order to elude this consequence the philosophers have a kind of artifice which we will expose briefly.
Ghazali says:
They assert that he who affirms that the world is posterior to God and God prior to the world cannot mean anything but that He is prior not temporally but essentially like the natural priority of one to two, although they can exist together in temporal existence, or like the priority of cause to effect, for instance the priority of the movement of a man to the movement of his shadow which follows him, or the movement of the hand to the movement of the ring, or the movement of the hand in the water to the movement of the water, for all these things are simultaneous, but the one is cause, the other effect, for it is said that the shadow moves through the movement of the man and the water through the hand in the water, and the reverse is not said although they are simultaneous. If this is what you mean by saying that God is prior to the world, then it follows that they must both either be temporal or eternal, for it is absurd that the one should be temporal and the other eternal. If it is meant that God is prior to the world and to time, not essentially, but temporally, then there was, before the existence of the world and of time, a time in which the world was non-existent, since non-existence preceded the world and God preceded it during a long duration which had a final term but no initial one, and then there was before time an infinite time, which is self-contradictory. Therefore the assertion that time had a beginning is absurd. And if time-which is the expression of the measure of movement -is eternal, movement must be eternal. And the necessity of the eternity of movement implies the necessity of the eternity of the thing in motion, through the duration of which time endures.
I say:
The
mode of their reasoning which he reproduces does not constitute a proof. It
amounts to saying that the Creator, if He is prior to the world, must either be
prior not in time, but in causation, like the priority of a man to his shadow,
or prior in time, like a builder to a wall. If He is prior in the same way as
the man is prior to his shadow, and if the Creator is eternal, then the world
too is eternal. But if He is prior in time, then He must precede the world by a
time which has no beginning, and time will be eternal, for if there is a time
before the actual, its starting-point cannot be imagined. And if time is
eternal, movement too is eternal, for time cannot be understood without motion.
And if motion is eternal, the thing in motion will be eternal, and its mover
will necessarily be eternal too. But this proof is unsound, for it is not of
the nature of the Creator to be in time, whereas it belongs to the nature of
the world to be so; and for this very reason it is not true that He is either
simultaneous with it or prior to it in time or in causation.
Ghazali
says
The objection to this is: Time is generated and created, and before it there was no time at all. The meaning of our words that God is prior to the world and to time is: He existed without the world and without time, then He existed and with Him there was the world and there was time. And the meaning of our words that He existed without the world is: the existence of the essence of the Creator and the non-existence of the essence of the world, and nothing else. And the meaning of our words that He existed and with Him there was the world is: the existence of the two essences, and nothing else. And the meaning of priority: the uniqueness of His existence, and nothing else. And the world is like a singular person; if we should say, for instance: God existed without Jesus, then He existed with Jesus-these words contain nothing but, first, the existence of an essence and the non-existence of an essence, then, the existence of two essences, and there is no need to assume here a third essence, namely time, although imagination cannot desist from assuming it. But we should not heed the errors of the imagination.
I say:
These
words are erroneous and mistaken, for we have already proved that there are two
kinds of existence: one in the nature of which there is motion and which cannot
be separated from time; the other in the nature of which there is no motion and
which is eternal and cannot be described in terms of time. The first is known
by the senses and by reason; the existence of the second-in the nature of
which there is neither motion nor change-is known by proof to everyone
who acknowledges that each motion needs a mover and each effect a cause, and
that the causes which move each other do not regress infinitely, but end in a
first cause which is absolutely unmoved. And it has also been established that
the entity in the nature of which there is no movement is the cause of the
entity in the nature of which there is movement. And it has been proved also that
the entity in the nature of which there is motion cannot be separated from
time, and that the entity in the nature of which there is no movement is
entirely free from time. Therefore the priority of the one entity over the
other is based neither on a priority in time, nor on the priority of that kind
of cause and effect, which belongs to the nature of things in motion, like the
priority of a man to his shadow. For this reason anyone who compares the
priority of the unmoved being to the thing in motion to the priority existing
between two things in motion is in error; since it is only true of each one in
pairs of moving things that, when it is brought in relation to the other, it is
either simultaneous with it or prior or posterior in time to it. It is the
later philosophers of Islam who made this mistake, since they enjoyed but
slight comprehension of the doctrine of the ancients. So the priority of this
one being to the other is the priority of the unchanging timeless existence to
the changing existence which is in time, and this is an altogether different
type of priority. It is therefore not true of these existences that they are
simultaneous, or that the one precedes the other, and Ghazali’s
observation that the priority of the Creator to the world is not a temporal
priority is true. But the posteriority of the world to the Creator, since He
does not precede the world in time, can only be understood as the posteriority
of effect to cause,’ for posteriority and priority are opposites which are
necessarily in one genus, as has been shown in the sciences.’ Since therefore
this priority is not in time, the posteriority also cannot be in time, and we
have the same difficulty all over again: how can the effect be delayed after
the cause when the conditions of acting are fulfilled? The philosophers,
however, since they do not recognize a beginning in the totality of this
existence in moti/n, are not touched by this difficulty, and it is possible for
them to indicate in what way the temporal beings proceed from the eternal. One
of their proofs that existence in motion has no beginning, and that in its
totality it does not start, is that, when it is assumed to start, it is assumed
to exist before its existence, for to start is a movement, and movement is of
necessity in the thing in motion, equally whether the movement is regarded as
taking place in time or at an instants Another proof is that everything that
becomes has the potentiality of becoming before it actually becomes, although
the theologians deny this (a discussion with them on this point will follow);
now potentiality is a necessary attribute of being in motion, and it follows
necessarily that, if it were assumed to become, it would exist before its
existence. What we have here are only dialectical arguments; they have,
however, a much greater plausibility than what the theologians advance.
As for Ghazali’s words:
If we should say, for instance, that God existed without Jesus, and then He existed with Jesus, these words contain nothing but, first, the existence of an essence and the non-existence of an essence, then, the existence of two essences, and there is no need to assume here a third essence, namely time.
I say:
This
is true, provided that Jesus’ posteriority is not regarded as an essential
temporal posteriority, but, if there is a posteriority, it is an accidental
posteriority, for time precedes this posterior entity, i.e. it is a necessity
of Jesus’ existence that time should precede Him and that His existence should
have begun, but the world is not subject to such a necessity, except in so far
as it is a part of a moving existence beyond which time extends in two
directions,’ as happens to Jesus and other transitory individuals.z Nothing of
this is proved here; here it is simply explained that the objection is not
valid. In addition, what he says afterwards of the proofs of the philosophers
is untrue.
Answering
in the name of the philosophers, Ghazali says:
One might say that our expression ‘God existed without the world’ means a third thing, besides the existence of one being and the non-existence of another, because, if we should suppose that in the future God should exist without the world, there would be in the future the existence of one being and the non-existence of another, still it would not be right to say ‘God existed without the world’, but we should say ‘God will exist without the world’, for only of the past do we say ‘God existed without the world’; and between the words ‘existed’ and ‘will exist’ there is a difference, for they cannot replace each other. And if we try to find out where the difference between the two sentences lies, it certainly does not lie in the words ‘existence of one being’ and ‘non-existence of another being’, but in a third entity, for if we say of the non-existence of the world in the future ‘God was without the world’, it will be objected: this is wrong, for ‘was’ refers only to the past. This shows therefore that the word ‘was’ comprises a third entity, namely the past, and the past by itself is time, and through another existent it is movement, for movement passes only through the passing of time. And so it follows necessarily that, before the world, a time finished which terminated in the existence of the world.
I say:
In
this in brief he shows that when it is said ‘such-and-such was
without such-and-such’ and then ‘such-and-such was with
such-and-such’ a third entity is understood, namely time. The word
‘was’ shows this, because of the difference in the meaning of this concept in
the past and in the future, for if we assume the existence of one thing with
the non-existence of another in the past, we say ‘such a thing existed
without such a thing’, but when we assume the non-existence of the one
with the existence of the other in the future, we say ‘such a thing will exist
without such a thing’, and the change in meaning implies that there is here a
third entity. If in our expression ‘such-and-such existed without
such-and-such’ the word ‘existed’ did not signify an entity, the
word ‘existed’ would not differ from ‘will exist’. All this is self-evident,
but it is only unquestionable in relation to the priority and posteriority of
things which are by nature in time. Concerning the timeless the word ‘was’ and
the like indicate in such a proposition nothing but the copula between
predicate and subject, when we say, for example, ‘God was indulgent and
compassionate’;’ and the same holds when either predicate or subject is
timeless, e.g. when we say ‘God was without the world, then God was with the
world’. Therefore for such existents the time-relation to which he refers
does not hold. This relation is, however, unquestionably real when we compare
the non-existence of the world with its existence, for if the world is in
time, the non-existence of the world as to be in time too. And since the
non-existence and the existence of the world cannot be in one and the
same time, the non-existence must precede; the non-existence must
be prior and the world posterior to it, for priority and posteriority in the
moving can only be understood in this relation to time. The only flaw in this
argument is to assume this relation between God and the world. Only in this
point is the argument which Ghazali relates
faulty and does it fail to constitute a proof.
Then
Ghazali gives the theologians’ objection to
this argument of the philosophers:’
The primitive meaning of the two words is the existence of one thing and the non-existence of another. The third element which is the connexion between the two words is a necessary relation to us. The proof is that, if we should suppose a destruction of the world in the future and afterwards a second existence for us, we should then say ‘God was without the world’, and this would be true, whether we meant its original non-existence or the second non-existence, its destruction after its existence. And a sign that this is a subjective relation is that the future can become past and can be indicated by the word ‘past’.’ All this is the consequence of the inability of our imagination to imagine the beginning of a thing without something preceding it, and this ‘before’ of which the imagination cannot rid itself is regarded as a really existing thing, namely time. This resembles the inability of the imagination to admit a limited body, e.g. overhead, without anything beyond its surface, so that it is imagined that behind the world there is a space either occupied or empty; and when it is said there is above the surface of the world no beyond and no farther extension, this is beyond the grasp of the imagination. Likewise, when it is said that there is no real anterior to the existence of the world, the imagination refuses to believe it. But the imagination may be called false in allowing above the world an empty space which is an infinite extension by our saying to it: empty space cannot be understood by itself, for extension is the necessary attribute of a body whose sides comprise space;’ a finite body implies the finiteness of extension, which is its attribute and the limitation of occupied space; empty space is unintelligible, therefore there is neither empty nor occupied space behind the world, although the imagination cannot admit this. And in the same way as it is said that spatial extension is an attribute of body, temporal extension is an attribute of motion, for time is the extension of movement just as the space between the sides of a body is the extension of space. And just as the proof that the sides of a body are finite prevents the admission of a spatial extension behind the world, so the proof of the finite character of movement in both directions prevents the supposition of a temporal extension behind the world, although the imagination, subject to its illusion and supposition, admits it and does not hold back from it. There is no difference between temporal extension, which is apprehended as divided through the relation of before and after, and spatial extension, which is apprehended as divided through the relation of high and low. If it is therefore permissible to admit a highest point above which there is nothing, it is equally permissible to admit a beginning, not preceded by anything real, except through an illusion similar to that which permits a beyond for the highest space. This is a legitimate consequence; notice it carefully, as the philosophers themselves agreed that behind the world there is neither empty nor occupied space.
I say:
There
are two parts to this objection; the first is that, when we imagine the past
and the future, i.e. the prior and the posterior, they are two things existing
in relation to our imagination, because we can imagine a future event as
becoming past and a past event as having been future. But if this is so, past
and future are not real things in themselves and do not possess existence
outside the soul; they are only constructs of the soul. And when movement is
annihilated, the relation and measure of time will not have sense any more.
The
answer is that the necessary connexion of movement and time is real and time is
something the soul constructs in movement, but neither movement nor time is
annihilated: they are only abolished in those things which are not subject to
motion, but in the existence of moving things or in their possible existence
time inheres necessarily. For there are only two kinds of being, those that are
subject to motion and those that are not, and the one kind cannot be converted
into the other, for otherwise a conversion of the necessary into the possible
would become possible. For if movement were impossible and then afterwards
occurred, the nature of things which arc not subject to motion would have
changed into the nature of things subject to motion, and this is impossible.
This is a consequence of the fact that motion inheres necessarily in a
substratum. If movement were possible before the existence of the world, the
things which are subject to movement would be necessarily in time, for movement
is only possible in what is subject to rest,’ not in absolute non-existence,
for in absolute non-existence there is no possibility whatever, or one would
have to admit that absolute non-existence could be converted into
existence. Therefore, the non-existence or privation which necessarily
precedes the occurrence of a thing has to be connected with a substratum, and
will be disconnected from it when the substratum actually receives this
occurrence, as happens with all contraries. For instance, when a warm thing
becomes cold, the essence of warmth does not change into coldness; it is only
the receptacle and the substratum of warmth that exchange their warmth for
coldness.
The
second part of this objection-and it is the most important of these
objections-is sophistical and malicious. It amounts to saying that to
imagine something before the beginning of this first movement (which is not
preceded by any moving body) is like the illusion that the end of the world,
for example, its highest part, ends necessarily either in another body or in
empty space, for extension is a necessary attribute of body, as time is a
necessary attribute of movement. And if it is impossible that there should be
an infinite body, it is impossible that there should be an infinite extension,
and, if it is impossible that there should be infinite extension, it is
impossible that every body should end in another body or in something which has
the potentiality of extension, i.e. for instance, emptiness, and that this
should continue without end. And the same applies to movement which has time as
a necessary attribute, for if it is impossible that there should be infinite
past movements and there exists therefore a first movement with a finite
initial term, it is impossible that there should exist a ‘before’ before it,
for, if so, there would be another movement before the first.
This
objection is, as we said, malicious, and belongs to the class of sophistical
substitutions-you will recognize what I mean if you have read the book On sophistic refutations. In other
words, Ghazali treats the quantity which has no
position and does not form a totality, i.e. time and motion, as the quantity
which possesses position and totality, i.e. body. He makes the impossibility of
endlessness in the latter a proof of its impossibility in the former, and he
deals with the act of the soul when it imagines an increase in the one quantity
which is assumed to be actual, i.e. body, as if it concerned both quantities.
This is a manifest error. For to imagine an increase in actual spatial
magnitude, so that it must end in another actual spatial magnitude, is to
imagine something which does not exist in the essence and definition of spatial
magnitude, but to imagine priority and posteriority in a movement that occurs
is to imagine something that belongs to its essence. For a movement can only
occur in time, i.e. time has to pass beyond its beginning. For this reason one
cannot represent a time the initial term of which is not the final term of
another time, for the definition of ‘the instant’ is that it is the end of the
past and the beginning of the future,’ for the instant is the present which
necessarily is the middle between the past and the future, and to represent a
present which is not preceded by a past is absurd. This, however, does not
apply to the point, for the point is the end of the line and exists at the same
time as the line, for the line is at rest. Therefore one can imagine a point
which is the beginning of a line without its being the end of another line, but
the instant cannot exist without the past and tile future, and exists
necessarily after the past and before the future, and what cannot subsist in itself
cannot exist before the existence of the future without being the end of tile
past. The cause of this error is the comparison of the instant with the point.
The proof that each movement which occurs is preceded by time is this:
everything must come to exist out of a privation, and nothing can become in the
instant-of which it can be truly said that its becoming is a vanishing-and
so it must be true that its privation must be in another moment than that in
which it itself exists, and there is time between each pair of instants,
because instant is not continuous with instant, nor point continuous with
point. This has been proved in the sciences. Therefore before the instant in
which the movement occurs there must necessarily be a time, because, when we represent
two instants in reality, there must necessarily be time between them.
And what is said in this objection that ‘higher’ resembles ‘before’ is not true, nor does the instant resemble the point, nor the quantity which possesses position the quantity which does not possess position.’ He who allows the existence of an instant which is not a present, or of a present which is not preceded by a past, denies time and the instant, for he assumes an instant as having the description which we have mentioned, and then assumes a time which has no beginning-which is a self-contradictory assumption. It is, therefore, wrong to ascribe to an act of imagination the fact that there is a prior event for every occurrence, for he who denies priority denies the event in time. The contrary is the case with the man who denies the real character of the high, for he denies the absolutely high and, when he denies the absolutely high, he denies also the absolutely low,’ and when these two are denied, also the heavy and the light are denied’, and the act of the imagination that a body with straight dimensions must end in another body is not false; no, this is a necessary truth, for the body with straight dimensions has the possibility of increasing, and what has this possibility is not limited by nature. Therefore the body with straight surfaces must end in the circumscribing circular body, since this is the perfect body which is liable neither to increase nor to decrease. Therefore when the mind seeks to imagine that the circular body must end in another body, it imagines the impossible. These are all matters of which the theologians and those who do not start their inquiry in the proper scientific order are unaware.
Further,
the relation between time and motion is not the same as that between spatial
limit and spatial magnitude, for the spatial limit is an attribute of spatial
magnitude, in so far as it inheres in it, in the way that the accident inheres
in its substratum and is individualized by the individuality of its substratum
and is indicated by pointing at its substratum and by its being in the place in
which its substratum is. But this is not the case with the necessary relation
between time and motion. For the dependence of time on motion is much like the
dependence of number on the thing numbered: just as number does not become
individualized through tire individuation of the thing numbered, nor pluralized
through its plurality, so it stands with the relation between time and
movement. Time, therefore, is unique for all movement and for each thing
moving, and exists everywhere, so that if we should suppose people confined
from youth in a cave in the earth, still we should be sure that they would
perceive time, even if they did not perceive any of the movements which are perceived
in the world. Aristotle therefore thought that the existence of movements in
time is much like the existence of the things numbered in numbers for number is
not pluralized through the plurality of the things numbered, nor is it
localized through the individuation of the places numbered. He thought,
therefore, that its specific quality was to mesaure the movements and to
measure the existence of moving things, in so far as they are moving, as number
counts the individual moving things, and therefore Aristotle says in his
definition of time that it is the number of movement according to the relations
of anterior and posterior.’ Therefore, just as the supposition that a thing
numbered occurs does not imply that number comes into existence, but it is a necessary
condition for the occurrence of a thing numbered that number should exist
before it, so the occurrence of movement implies that there was time before it.
If time occurred with the occurrence of any individual movement whatever, time
would only be perceived with that individual movement. This will make you
understand how different the nature of time is from the nature of spatial
magnitude.
Ghazali answers on behalf of the philosophers:
It may be said: This comparisons is lame, for there is neither above nor below in the world; for the world is spherical, and in the sphere there is neither above nor below; if the one direction is called above, because it is overhead, and the other below, because it is under foot, this name is always determined in relation to you, and the direction which is below in relation to you is above in relation to another, if you imagine him standing on the other side of the terrestrial globe with the sole of his foot opposite the sole of your foot. Yes, these parts of heaven which you reckon above during the day are identical with what is below during the night, and what is below the earth comes again above the earth through the daily revolution. But it cannot be imagined that the beginning of the world becomes its end. If we imagined a stick with one thick and one thin end and we agreed to call the part nearest the thin end ‘above’ and the other ‘below’, there would not arise from this an essential differentiation in the parts of the world; it would simply be that different names would have been applied to the shape of the stick, so that if we substituted the one name for the other, there would be an exchange of names, but the world itself would remain unchanged. So ‘above’ and ‘below’ are a mere relation to you without any differentiation in the parts and places of the world. The non-existence, however, preceding the world and the initial term of its existence are essential realities, a substitution or a change of which cannot be imagined. Nor can it be imagined that the non-existence which is supposed to occur at the disappearance of the world and which follows the world can become the non-existence preceding it. The initial and final terms of the world’s existence are permanent essential terms, in which no change can be imagined through the change of the subjective relation to them, in contrast with ‘above’ and ‘below’. Therefore we philosophers, indeed, are justified in saying that in the world there is neither ‘above’ nor ‘below’, but you theologians have not the right to assert that the existence of the world has neither a ‘before’ nor an ‘after’.
And when the existence of ‘before’ and ‘after’ is proved, time cannot mean anything but what is apprehended through the anterior and the posterior.
I say:
This
answer given in the name of the philosophers is extremely unsound. It amounts
to saying that ‘above’ and ‘below’ are relative to us and that therefore
imagination can treat them as an infinite sequence, but that the sequence of
‘before’ and ‘after’ does not rest on imagination-for there is here no
subjective relation-but is a ~ purely rational concept. This means that
the order of above and below in a thing may be reversed in imagination, but
that the privation before an event and the privation after an event, its before
and its after, are not interchangeable for imagination. But by giving this
answer the problem is not solved, for the philosophers think that i there
exists a natural above; to which light things move and a natural below to which
heavy things move, or else the heavy and the light would be relative and exist
by convention, and they hold that in imagination the limit of a body, having by
nature its place above, may end either in occupied or in empty space. And this
argument is in- valid as a
justification of the philosophers for two reasons. First, that the philosophers
assume an absolute above and an absolute below, but no absolute beginning and
no absolute end; secondly that their opponents may object that it is not the
fact of their being relative that causes the imagination to regard the sequence
of low and high as an infinite series, but that this happens to the imagination
because it observes that every spatial magnitude is continuous with another
spatial magnitude, just as any event is preceded by another event. n Therefore Ghazali transfers the question from the words ‘above’
and ‘below’ to ‘inside’ and ‘outside’s and he says in his answer to the
philosophers:
There is no real difference in the words ‘above’ and ‘below’, and therefore there is no sense in defining them, but we will apply ourselves rather to the words ‘inside’ and ‘outside’. We say: The world has an inside and an outside; and we ask: Is there outside the world an occupied or empty space? The philosophers will answer: There is outside the world neither occupied nor empty space, and if you mean by ‘outside’ its extreme surface, then there is an outside, but if you mean anything else, there is no outside. Therefore if they ask us theologians if there is anything before the existence of the world, we say: If you mean by it the beginning, i.e. its initial term, then there is a before, just as there is an outside to the world according to your explanation that that is its ultimate limit and its final plane, but if you mean anything else, then there is not, in analogy with your answer.
If you say: A beginning of existence, without anything preceding it, cannot be understood, we say: A limit of a body existing without anything outside it cannot be understood.’ If you say: Its exterior is its furthest plane and nothing else, we say: Its before is the beginning of its existence, nothing else. The conclusion is that we say: We affirm that God has an existence without the world’s existing, and this assumption again does not force us to accept anything else. That to assume more rests on the act of imagination is proved by the fact that imagination acts in the same way in regard to time as in regard to place, for although our opponents believe in the eternity of the world, their imagination is willing to suppose it created; whereas we, who believe in its creation, are often allowed by our imagination to regard it as eternal. So much as far as body is concerned; but to revert to time, our opponents do not regard a time without a beginning as possible, and yet in opposition to this belief their imagination can represent it as a possible assumption, although time cannot be represented by the imagination in the way that body is represented, for neither the champion nor the opponent of the finitude of body can imagine a body not surrounded by empty or occupied space; the imagination simply refuses to accept it. Therefore one should say: a clear thinker pays no attention to the imagination when he cannot deny the finitude of body by proof, nor does he give attention to the imagination when he cannot deny the beginning of an existence without anything preceding it, which the imagination cannot grasp. For the imagination, as it is only accustomed to a body limited by another body or by air, represents emptiness in this way, although emptiness, being imperceptible, cannot be occupied by anything. Likewise the imagination, being only accustomed to an event occurring after another event, fears to suppose an event not preceded by another event which is terminated. And this is the reason of the error.
I say:
Through
this transference, by his comparing the time-limit with the spatial limit
in his argument against the philosophers, this argument becomes invalid and we
have already shown the error through which it is specious and the sophistical
character of the argument, and we need not repeat ourselves.
Ghazali says:
The philosophers have a second way of forcing their opponents to admit the eternity of time. They say: You do not doubt that God was able to create the world one year, a hundred years, a thousand years, and so ad infinitum, before He created it and that those possibilities are different in magnitude and number. Therefore it is necessary to admit before the existence of the world a measurable extension, one part of which can be longer than another part, and therefore it is necessary that something should have existed before the existence of the world. If you say the word ‘years’ cannot be applied before the creation and revolution of heaven, let us drop the word ‘years’ and let us give another turn to our argument and say: If we suppose that from the beginning of the world till now the sphere of the world has performed, for instance, a thousand revolutions, was God able to create a second world before it, which, for example, would have performed eleven hundred revolutions up to now? If you deny it, it would mean that the Eternal had passed from impotence to power or the world from impossibility to possibility, but if you accept it, and you cannot but accept it, it may be asked if God was able to create a third world which would have performed twelve hundred revolutions up to now and you will have to admit this. We philosophers say: Then, could the world which we called by the order of our supposition the third, although as a matter of fact it is the first, have been created at the same time as the world we called the second, so that the former would have performed twelve hundred revolutions and the latter eleven hundred revolutions, it being understood that both, in revolving, complete the same distance at the same speed? If you were to admit this, you would be admitting something absurd, for it would be absurd that in that case the number of the two revolutions, having the same speed and finishing at the same moment, should be different. But, if you answer that it is impossible that the third world which has up to now performed twelve hundred revolutions could have been created at the same time as the second world which has up to now performed eleven hundred revolutions, and that on the contrary it must have been created the same number of years earlier than the second, as the second has been created before the first-we call it first, as it comes first in order, when in imagination we proceed from our time to it-then there exists a quantity of possibility double that of another possibility, and there is doubtless another possibility which doubles the whole of the others. These measurable quantitative possibilities, of which some are longer than others by a definite measure, have no other reality than time, and those measurable quantities are not an attribute of the essence of God, who is too exalted to possess measure,’ nor an attribute of the non-existence of the world, for non-existence is nothing and therefore cannot be measured with different measures. Still, quantity is an attribute which demands a substratum, and this is nothing other than movement, and quantity is nothing but the time which measures movement. Therefore also for you theologians there existed before the world a substratum of differentiated quantity, namely time, and according to you time existed before the world.’
I say:
The
summary of this argument is that, when we imagine a movement, we find with it
an extension which measures it, as if it were its measurement, while
reciprocally the movement measures the extension, and we find that we can
assume in this measure and this extension a movement longer than the first
supposed movement, and we affirm through the corresponding and congruous units
of this extension that the one movement is longer than the other.’ If therefore
for you theologians the world has a certain extension from its beginning till
now-let us suppose, for instance, a thousand years and since God
according to you is able to create before this world another world, we may
suppose that the extension He can give it will be longer than the extension of
the first world by a certain definite quantity, and that He can likewise create
a third world before this second and that the existence of each of them must be
preceded by an extension through which its
existence can be measured. If this is true, and there is an infinite regress of
this possibility of anterior worlds, there is an extension which precedes all
these worlds. And this extension which measures all of them cannot be absolute
nonexistence, for non-existence cannot measure; it has, therefore, to be
a quantity, for what measures a quantity has to be quantity itself, and the
measuring quantity is that which we call time. And it is clear that this must
precede in existence anything we imagine to occur, just as the measure must
precede the measured in existence. If this extension which is time were to
occur at the occurrence of the first movement, then it would have to be
preceded by an extension which could measure
it, in which it could occur, and which could be like its measurement. And
in the same way any world which could be imagined would have to be preceded by
an extension which measures it. Therefore this extension has no beginning, for
if it had a beginning it would have to have an extension which measured it, for
each event which begins has an extension which
measures it and which we call
time.
This is the
most suitable exposition of this argument, and this is the method by which
Avicenna proves infinite time, but there is a difficulty in understanding it,
because of the problem that each possible has one extension and each extension
is connected with its own possible and this forms a point of discussion;’ or
one must concede that the possibilities prior to the world are of the same
nature as the possible inside the world, i.e. as it is of the nature of this
possible inside the world that time inheres in it, so also with the possible
which is prior to the world. This is clear concerning the possible inside the
world, and therefore the existence of time may be imagined from it.
Ghazali says:
The objection is that all this is the work of imagination, and the most convenient way of refuting it is to compare time with place; therefore we say: Was it not in God’s power to create the highest sphere in its heaven a cubit higher than He has created it? If the answer is negative, this is to deny God’s power, and if the answer is affirmative, we ask: And by two cubits and by three cubits and so on ad infinitum? Now we affirm that this amounts to admitting behind the world a spatial extension which has measure and quantity, as a thing which is bigger by two or three cubits than another occupies a space bigger by two or three cubits, and by reason of this there is behind the world a quantity which demands a substratum and this is a body or empty space. Therefore, there is behind the world empty or occupied space. And how can you answer this? And likewise we may ask, whether God was not able to create the sphere of the world smaller than He has created it by a cubit or two cubits? And is there no difference between those two magnitudes in regard to the occupied space taken away from them and the space they still occupy, for the occupied space withdrawn is bigger when two cubits are taken away than when one cubit is taken away? And therefore empty space has measure. But emptiness is nothing; how can it have measure? And our answer is: ‘It belongs to the illusion of imagination to suppose possibilities in time before the existence of the world’, just as your answer is: ‘It belongs to the illusion of imagination to suppose possibilities in space behind the existence of the world.’ There is no difference between those two points of view.’
I say:
This
consequence is true against the theory which regards an infinite increase in
the size of the world as possible, for it follows from this theory that a
finite thing proceeds from God which is preceded by infinite quantitative
possibilities. And if this is allowed for possibility in space, it must also be
allowed in regard to the possibility in time, and we should have a time limited
in both directions, although it would be preceded by infinite temporal
possibilities. The answer is, however, that to imagine the world to be bigger
or smaller does not conform to truth but is impossible. But the impossibility
of this does not imply that to imagine the possibility of a world before this
world is to imagine an impossibility, except in case the nature of the possible
were already realized and there existed before the existence of the world only
two natures, the nature of the necessary and the nature of the impossible? But
it is evident that the judgement of reason concerning the being of these three
natures is eternal, like its judgement concerning the necessary and the
impossible.
This
objection, however, does not touch the philosophers, because they hold that the
world could not be smaller or bigger than it is,
If
it were possible that a spatial magnitude could infinitely increase, then the existence
of a spatial magnitude without end would be possible and a spatial magnitude,
actually infinite, would exist, and this is impossible and Aristotle has
already shown the impossibility of this.’ But against the man who believes in
this possibility, because the contrary would imply a denial of God’s power,
this argument is valid, for this spatial possibility is just as much a purely
rational concept as the possibility of temporal anteriority according to the
philosophers. Therefore, he who believes in the temporal creation of the world
and affirms that all body is in space, is bound to admit that before the
creation of the world there was space, either occupied by body, in which the
production of the world could occur, or empty, for it is necessary that space
should precede what is produced.’ The man who denies empty space and affirms
the finiteness of body-like certain later Ash’arites who, however,
separated themselves from the principles of the theologians; but I have not
read it in their books and it was told to me by some who studied their
doctrines-cannot admit the temporal production of the world. If the fact
of this extension which measures movement and which stands in relation to it as
its measurement were indeed the work of an illusion-like the
representation of a world bigger or smaller than it really is-time would
not exist, for time is nothing but what the mind perceives of this extension
which measures movement. And if it is self-evident that time exists, then
the act of the mind must necessarily be a veracious one, embodying reason, not
one embodying illusion.
Ghazali says:
It has been objected: we declare that what is not possible is what cannot be done and increase or decrease in the size of the world is impossible, and therefore could not be brought about .
I
say
This
is the answer to the objection of the Ash’arites that to admit that God could
not have made the world bigger or smaller is to charge Him with impotence, but
they have thereby compromised themselves, for impotence is not inability to do
the impossible, but inability to do what can be done.
Ghazali, opposing this, says:
This excuse is invalid for three reasons: The first is that it is an affront to reason, for when reason regards it as possible that the world might be bigger or smaller than it is by a cubit, this is not the same as regarding it as possible to identify black with white and existence with non-existence; impossibility lies in affirming the negative and the positive at the same time, and all impossibilities amount to this. This is indeed a silly and faulty assertion.’
I say:
This statement is, as he says, an affront to reason, but only to the reason of him who judges superficially; it is not an affront to true reason, for a statement about its being possible or not’ requires a proof. And therefore he is right when he declares that this is not impossible in the way in which the assumption that black might be white is impossible, for the impossibility of the latter is self-evident. The statement, however, that the world could not be smaller or larger than it is is not self-evident. And although all impossibilities can be reduced to self-evident impossibilities, this reduction can take place in two ways. The first is that the impossibility is self-evident; the second is that there follows sooner or later from its supposition an impossibility of the same character as that of self-evident impossibilities.’ For instance, if it is assumed that the world might be larger or smaller than it is, it follows that outside it there would be occupied or empty space. And from the supposition that there is outside it occupied or empty space, some of the greatest impossibilities follow: from empty space the existence of mere extension existing by itself; from occupied space a body moving either upward or downward or in a circle which therefore must be part of another world. Now it has been proved in the science of physics that the existence of another world at the same time as this is an impossibility and the most unlikely consequence would be that the world should have empty space: for any world must needs have four elements and a spherical body revolving round them. He who wants to ascertain this should look up the places where its exposition is demanded-this, of course, after having fulfilled the preliminary conditions necessary for the student to understand strict proof .
Then
Ghazali mentions the second reason:
If the world is in the state it is, without the possibility of being larger or smaller than it is, then its existence, as it is, is necessary, not possible. But the necessary needs no cause. So say, then, as the materialists do that you deny the creator and that you deny the cause of causes! But this is not your doctrine.
I say:
To
this the answer which, Avicenna gives in accordance with his doctrine is quite
appropriate.’ According to him necessity of existence is of two kinds: the
necessary, existent by itself, and the necessary, existent through another. But
my answer on this question is still more to the point: things necessary in this
sense need not have an agent or a maker; take, for example, a saw which is used
to saw wood-it is a tool having a certain determined quantity, quality,
and matter, that is, it is not possible for it to be of another material than
iron and it could not have any other shape than that of a saw or any other
measure than the measure of a saw. Still nobody would say that the saw has a
necessity of being= See, therefore, how crude this mistake is! If one were to
take away the necessity from the quantities, qualities, and matters of things
produced by art, in the way the Ash’arites imagine this to happen concerning
the created in relation to the creator, the wisdom which lies in the creator and
the created would have been withdrawn, any agent could be an artificer and any
cause in existence a creator. But all this is a denial of reason and wisdom.
Ghazali says:
The third reason is that this faulty argument authorizes its opponent to oppose it by a similar one, and we may say: The existence of the world was not possible before its existence, for indeed possibility-according to your theory-is coextensive with existence, neither more nor less. If you say: ‘But then the eternal has passed from impotence to power’, we answer:
‘No, for the existence was not possible and therefore could not be brought about and the impossibility of a thing’s happening that could not happen does not indicate impotence.’ If you say: ‘How can a thing which is impossible become possible?’ We answer: ‘But why should it be impossible that a thing should be impossible at one moment and possible at another?’ If you say: ‘The times are similar,’ the answer is: ‘But so are the measures, and why should one measure be possible and another, bigger or smaller by the width of a nail, impossible?’ And if the latter assumption is not impossible, the former is not impossible either.’ And this is the way to oppose them.
But the true answer is that their supposition of possibilities makes no sense whatever. We concede only that God is eternal and powerful, and that His action never fails, even if He should wish it. And there is nothing in this power that demands the assumption of a temporal extension, unless imagination, confusing God’s power with other things, connects it with time.
I say:
The
summary of this is that the Ash’arites say to the philosophers: this question
whether the world could be larger or smaller is impossible according to us; it
has sense only for the man who believes in a priority of possibility in
relation to the actualization of a thing, i.e. the realization of the possible.
We, the Ash’arites, however, say: ‘Possibility occurs together with the
actuality as it is, without adding or subtracting anything.’
Now
my answer is that he who denies the possibility of the possible before its
existence denies the necessary, for the possible is the contrary of the
impossible without there existing a middle term, and, if a thing is not
possible before its existence, then it is necessarily impossible.’ Now to posit
the impossible as existing is an impossible falsehood, but to posit the
possible as existing is a possible, not an impossible, falsehood.’ Their
assertion that possibility and actuality exist together is a falsehood, for possibility
and actuality are contradictory, and do not exist together in one and the same
moment. The necessary consequence for them is that possibility exists neither
at the same time as the actuality nor before it. The true consequence for the
Ash’arites in this discussion is not that the eternal passes from impotence to
power, for he who cannot do an impossible act is not called impotent, but that
a thing can pass from the nature of the i impossible to the nature of
existence, and this is like the changing of the necessary into the possible. To
posit a thing, however, as impossible at one time and possible at another does
not cut it off from the nature of the possible, for this is the general
character of the possible; the existence of anything possible, for instance, is
impossible at the moment when its contrary exists in its substratum. If the
opponent concedes that a thing impossible at one time is possible at another,
then he has conceded that this thing is of the nature of the absolutely
possible’ and that it has not the nature of the impossible. If it is assumed
that the world was impossible for an infinite time before its production, the
consequence is that, when it was produced, it changed over from impossibility
to possibility. This question is not the problem with which we are concerned
here, but as we have said before, the transference from one problem to another
is an act of sophistry.
And
as to his words:
But the true answer is that their supposition of possibilities makes no sense whatever. We concede only that God is eternal and powerful and that His action never fails, even if He should wish it. And there is nothing in this power that demands the assumption of a temporal extension, unless imagination confusing God’s power with other things connects with it time.
I say:
Even
if there were nothing in this supposition-as he says-that implies
the eternity of time, there is something in it that demands that the
possibility of the occurrence of the world and equally of time should be
eternal. And this is that God never ceases to have power for action, and that
it is impossible that anything should prevent His act from being eternally
connected with His existence; and perhaps the opposite of this statement
indicates the impossibility better still, namely, that He should have no power
at one time but power at another, and that He could be called powerful only at
definite limited times, although He is ark eternal and perpetual being. And
then we have the old question again whether the world may be either eternal or
temporal, or whether the world cannot be eternal, or whether the world cannot
be temporal, or whether the world may be temporal but certainly cannot be
eternal, and whether, if the world is temporal, it can be a first act or not.
And if reason has no power to pronounce for one of these opposite propositions,
let us go back to tradition, but do not then regard this question as a rational
one! We say that the First Cause cannot omit the best act and perform an
inferior, because this would be an imperfection; but can there be a greater
imperfection than to assume the act of the Eternal as finite and limited, like
the act of a temporal product, although a limited act can only be imagined of a
limited agent, not of the eternal agent whose existence and action are
unlimited? .All this, as you see, cannot be unknown to the man who has even the
slightest understanding of the rational. And how can it be thought that the
present act proceeding from the Eternal cannot be preceded by another act, and
again by another, and so in our thinking infinitely, like the infinite
continuation of His existence? For it is a necessary consequence that the act
of Him whose existence time cannot measure nor comprehend in either direction
cannot be comprehended in time nor measured by a limited duration. For there is
no being whose act is delayed after its existence, except when there is an
impediment which prevents its existence from attaining its perfection,’ or, in
voluntary beings, when there is an obstruction in the execution of their
choice. He, therefore, who assumes that from the Eternal there proceeds only a
temporal act presumes that His act is constrained in a certain way and in this
way therefore does not depend on His choice.
Ghazali says:
They insist on saying: The existence of the world is possible before its existence, as it is absurd that it should be impossible and then become possible; this possibility has no beginning, it is eternally unchangeable and the existence of the world remains eternally possible, for at no time whatever can the existence of the world be described as impossible; and if the possibility never ceases, the possible, in conformity with the possibility, never ceases either; and the meaning of the sentence, that the existence of the world is possible, is that the existence of the world is not impossible; and since its existence is eternally possible, it is never impossible, for if it were ever impossible, it would not be true that the existence of the world is eternally possible; and if it were not true that the existence of the world is eternally possible, it would not be true that its possibility never ceases; and if it were not true that its possibility never ceases, it would be true that its possibility had begun; and if it were true that its possibility had begun, its existence before this beginning would not be possible and that would lead to the assumption of a time when the world was not possible and God had no power over it.
I say:
He
who concedes that the world before its existence was of a never-ceasing
possibility must admit that the world is eternal, for the assumption that what
is eternally possible is eternally existent implies no absurdity. What can
possibly exist eternally must necessarily exist eternally, for what can receive
eternity cannot become corruptible, except if it were possible that the
corruptible could become eternal. Therefore Aristotle has said that the
possibility in the eternal beings is necessary.’
Ghazali says:
The objection is that it is said that the temporal becoming of the world never ceased to be possible, and certainly there is no time at which its becoming could not be imagined. But although it could be at any time, it did not become at any time whatever, for reality does not conform to possibility, but differs from it. You yourself hold, for instance, in the matter of place, that the world could be bigger than it is or that the creation of an infinite series of bodies above the world is possible, and that there is no limit to the possibilities of increase in the size of the world, but still the actual existence of absolutely infinite occupied space and of any infinite and limitless being is impossible. What is said to be possible is an actual body of a limited surface, but the exact size of this body, whether it is larger or smaller, is not specified. In the same way, what is possible is the coming into existence of the world in time, but the exact time of its coming into existence whether earlier or later, is not specified. The principle of its having come into being is specified and this is the possible, nothing else.’
I say:
The man who assumes that before the existence of the world there was one unique, never-ceasing possibility must concede that the world is eternal. The man who affirms, like Ghazali in his answer, that before the world there was an infinite number of possibilities of worlds, has certainly to admit that before this world there was another world and before this second world a third, and so on ad infinitum, as is the case with human beings, and especially when it is assumed that the perishing of the earlier is the necessary condition for the existence of the later. For instance, if God had the power to create another world before this, and before this second world yet another, the series must continue infinitely, or else we should arrive at a world before which no other world could have been created (however, the theologians do not affirm this nor use it as a proof for the temporal production of the world). Although the assumption that before this world there might be an infinite number of others does not seem an impossible one, it appears after closer examination to be absurd, for it would follow from it that the universe had the nature of an individual person in this transitory world, so that its procession from the First Principle would be like the procession of the individual person from Him-that is to say, through an eternal moving body and an eternal motion. But then this world would be part of another world, like the transient beings in this world, and then necessarily either we end finally in a world individually eternal or we have an infinite series. And if we have to bring this series to a standstill, it is more appropriate to arrest it at this world, by regarding it as eternally unique.
Ghazali says:
The fourth proof is that they say everything that becomes is preceded by the matter which is in it, for what becomes cannot be free from matter.’ For this reason matter never becomes; what becomes is only the form, the accidents and the qualities which add themselves to matters The proof is that the existence of each thing that becomes must, before its becoming, either be possible, impossible, or necessary: it cannot be impossible, for the essentially impossible will never exist; it cannot be necessary, for the essentially necessary will never be in a state of non-existence, and therefore it is the essentially possible.’ Therefore, the thing which becomes has before its becoming the possibility of becoming, but the possibility of becoming is an attribute which needs a relation and has no subsistence in itself.’ It needs, therefore, a substratum with which it can be connected, and there is no substratum except matter, and it becomes connected with it in the way in which we say this matter receives warmth and coldness, or black and white, or movement and rest, i.e. it is possible that these qualities and these changes occur in it and therefore possibility is an attribute of matter. Matter does not possess other matter, and cannot become; for, if it did, the possibility of its existence would precede its existence, and possibility would subsist by itself without being related to anything else, whereas it is a relative attribute which cannot be understood as subsisting by itself. And it cannot be said that the meaning of possibility amounts to what can be done and what the Eternal had the power to do, because we know only that a thing can be done, because it is possible, and we say ‘this can be done because it is possible and cannot be done because it is not possible’; and if ‘this is possible’ meant ‘this can be done’, to say ‘this can be done because it is possible’ would mean ‘this is possible because it is possible’, and this is a circular definition; and this shows that ‘this is possible’ is a first judgement in the mind, evident in itself, which makes the second judgement ‘that it can be done’ intelligible. It cannot be said, either, that to be possible refers to the knowledge of the Eternal, for knowledge depends on a thing known, whereas possibility is undoubtedly an object of knowledge, not knowledge; further, it is a relative attribute, and needs something to which it can be related, and this can only be matter, and everything that becomes is preceded by matter.
I say:
The
summary of this is that everything that becomes is possible before it becomes,
and that possibility needs something for its subsistence, namely, the
substratum which receives that which is possible. For it must not be believed
that the possibility of the recipient is the same as the possibility of the
agent. It is a different thing to say about Zaid, the agent, that he can do
something and to say about the patient that it can have something done to it.
Thus the possibility of the patient is a necessary condition for the
possibility of the agent, for the agent which cannot act is not possible but
impossible. Since it is impossible that the possibility prior to the thing’s
becoming should be absolutely without substratum, or that the agent should be
its substratum or the thing possible-for the thing possible loses its
possibility, when it becomes actual-there only remains as a vehicle for
possibility the recipient of the possible, i.e. matter. Matter, in so far as it
is matter, does not become; for if it did it would need other matter and we
should have an infinite regress. Matter only becomes in so far as it is
combined with form. Everything that comes into being comes into being from something
else, and this must either give rise to an infinite regress and lead directly
to infinite matter which is impossible, even if we assume an eternal mover, for
there is no actual infinite; or the forms must be interchangeable in the
ingenerable and incorruptible substratum, eternally and in rotation.’ There
must, therefore, be an eternal movement which produces this interchange in the
eternally transitory things. And therefore it is clear that the generation of
the one in each pair of generated beings is the corruption of the other;
otherwise a thing could come into being from nothing, for the meaning of
‘becoming’ is the alteration of a thing and its change, from what it has
potentially, into actuality. It is not possible that the privation itself should
change into the existent, and it is not the privation of which it is said that
it has become. There exists, therefore, a substratum for the contrary forms,
and it is in this substratum that the forms interchange.
Ghazali says:
The objection is that the possibility of which they speak is a judgement of the intellect, and anything whose existence the intellect supposes, provided no obstacle presents itself to the supposition, we call possible and, if there is such an obstacle, we call it impossible and, if we suppose that it cannot be supposed not to be, we call it necessary. These are rational judgements which need no real existent which they might qualify. There are three proofs of this. The first is: If possibility needed an existent to which it could be related, and of which it could be said that it is its possibility, impossibility also would need an existent of which it might be said that it is its impossibility; but impossibility has no real existence, and there is no matter in which it occurs and to which it could be related.
I say:
That
possibility demands an existing matter is clear, for all true intellectual
concepts need a thing outside the soul, for truth, as it has been defined, is
the agreement of what is in the soul with what is outside the soul.’ And when
we say that something is possible, we cannot but understand that it needs
something in which this possibility can be. As regards his proof that the
possible is not dependent on an existent, because the impossible is not
dependent on an existent, this is sophistical. Indeed the impossible demands a
substratum just as much as the possible does, and this is clear from the fact
that the impossible is the opposite of the possible and opposite contraries
undoubtedly require a substratum. For impossibility is the negation of
possibility, and, if possibility needs a substratum, impossibility which is the
negation of this possibility requires a substratum too, e.g. we say that the
existence of empty space is impossible, because the existence of independent
dimensions outside or inside natural bodies is impossible, or that the presence
of opposites at the same time in the same substratum is impossible, or that the
equivalence of one to two is impossible, i.e. in reality. All this is self-evident,
and it is not necessary to consider the errors here committed.
Ghazali says:
The second proof is that the intellect decides that black and white are possible before they exist.’ If this possibility were related to the body in which they inhere, so that it might be said that the meaning is that this body can be black and white, then white would not be possible by itself and possibility would be related only to the body. But we affirm, as concerns the judgement about black in itself, as to whether it is possible, necessary, or impossible, that we, without doubt, will say that it is possible. And this shows that the intellect in order to decide whether something is possible need not admit an existing thing to which the possibility can be related.
I
say
This
is a sophism. For the possible is predicated of the recipient and of the
inherent quality. In so far as it is predicated of the substratum, its opposite
is the impossible, and in so far as it is predicated of the inherent, its
opposite is the necessary.’ Thus the possible which is described as being the
opposite of the impossible is not that which abandons its possibility so far as
it is actualized, when it becomes actual, because this latter loses its
possibility in the actualizing process.’ This latter possible is only described
by possibility in so far as it is in potency, and the vehicle of this potency
is the substratum which changes from existence in potency into existence in
actuality.’ This is evident from the definition of the possible that it is the
nonexistence which is in readiness to exist or not to exists This possible non-existent
is possible neither in so far as it is non-existent nor in so far as it
is actually existent. It is only possible in so far as it is in potency, and
for this reason the Mu’tazilites affirm that the nonexistent is a kind of
entity. For non-existence is the opposite of existence, and each of the
two is succeeded by the other, and when the non-existence of a thing
disappears it is followed by its existence, and when its existence disappears
it is succeeded by its non-existence. As non-existence by itself
cannot change into existence, and existence
by
itself cannot change into non-existence, there must be a third entity
which is the recipient for both of them, and that is what is described by
‘possibility’ and ‘becoming’ and ‘change from the quality of non-existence
to the quality of existence’. For non-existence itself is not described
by ‘becoming’ or ‘change’; nor is the thing that has become actual described in
this way, for what becomes loses the quality of becoming, change, and
possibility when it has become actual. Therefore there must necessarily be
something that can be described by ‘becoming’ and ‘change’ and ‘transition from
nonexistence to existence’, as happens in the passage of opposites into
opposites; that is to say, there must be a substratum for them in which they
can interchange-with this one difference, however, that this substratum
exists in the interchange of all the accidents in actuality, whereas in the
substance it exists in potency.’
And
we cannot think of regarding what is described by ‘possibility’ and ‘change’ as
identical with the actual, i.e. which belongs to the becoming in so far as it
is actual, for the former again vanishes and the latter must necessarily be a
part of the product. Therefore there must necessarily be a substratum which is
the recipient for the possibility and which is the vehicle of the change and
the becoming, and it is this of which it is said that it becomes, and alters,
and changes from non-existence into existence. Nor can we think of making
this substratum of the nature of the actualized, for if this were the case the
existent would not become, for what becomes comes into being from the non-existent
not from the existent.’ Both philosophers and Mu’tazilites agree about the
existence of this entity; only the philosophers are of the opinion that it
cannot be exempt from a form actually existent, i.e. that it cannot be free
from existence, like the transition, for example, from sperma to blood and the
transition from blood to the members of the embryo. The reason is that if it
were exempt from existence it would have an existence of its own, and if it had
an existence of its own, becoming could not come from it. This entity is called
by the philosophers ‘lyle’, and it is the cause of generation and corruption.
And according to the philosophers an existent which is free from Kyle is neither generable nor
corruptible.
Ghazali says:
The third proof is that the souls of men, according to the philosophers, are substances which subsist by themselves’ without being in a body or in matter or impressed on matters they had a beginning in time, according to the theory of Avicenna and the acknowledged philosophers, they had possibility before their beginning, but they have neither essence nor matter’ and their possibility is a relative attribute, dependent neither on God’s power nor on the Agent;’ but on what then is it dependent? The difficulties are therefore turned against them themselves.
I say:
I
do not know any philosopher who said that the soul has a beginning in the true
sense of the word and is thereafter everlasting except -as Ghazali relates-Avicenna. All other
philosophers agree that in their temporal existence they are related to and
connected with the bodily possibilities, which receive this connexion like the
possibilities which subsist in mirrors for their connexion with the rays of the
suns According to the philosophers this possibility is not of the nature of the
generable and corruptible forms, but of a kind to which, according to them,
demonstrative proof leads, and the vehicle of this possibility is of another
nature than the nature of the Kyle. He
alone can grasp their theories in these matters who has read their books and
fulfilled the conditions there laid down by them, and has besides a sound
understanding and a learned master. That Ghazali
should touch on such questions in this way is not worthy of such a man, but
there are only these alternatives: either he knew these matters in their true
nature, and sets them out here wrongly, which is wicked; or he did not
understand their real nature and touched on problems he had not grasped, which
is the act of an ignoramus. However, he stands too high in our eyes for either
of these qualifications. But even the best horse will stumble’ and it was a
stumble of Ghazali’s that he brought out this
book. But perhaps he was forced to do so by the conditions of his time and his
situation.
Ghazali says, speaking on behalf of the
philosophers:
It may be said: To reduce possibility to a judgement of the intellect is absurd, for the meaning of ‘judgement of the intellect’ is nothing but the knowledge of possibility, and possibility is an object of knowledge, not knowledge itself; knowledge, on the contrary, comprises possibility and follows it and depends on it as it is, and if knowledge vanished the object of knowledge would not, but the disappearance of the object of knowledge would imply the disappearance of knowledge. For knowledge and the object-known are two things, the former dependent on the latter, and if we supposed rational beings to turn away from possibility and neglect it, we should say: ‘It is not possibility that is annulled, for the possibilities subsist by themselves, but it is simply that minds neglect them or that minds and rational beings have disappeared; but possibility remains, without any doubt.’ And the three proofs are not valid, for impossibility requires an existent to which it can be related, and impossibility means identifying two opposites, and if the substratum were white it could not become black as long as the white existed, and therefore we need a substratum, qualified by the quality during the inherence of which its opposite is spoken of as impossible in this substratum, and therefore impossibility is a relative attribute subsistent in a substratum and related to it. And where the necessary is concerned it is evident that it is related to necessary existence.
As concerns the second proof, that black is in itself possible, this is a mistake, for if it is taken, abstracted from the substratum in which it inheres, it is impossible, not possible; it only becomes possible when it can become a form in a body; the body is then in readiness for the interchange, and the interchange is possible for the body; but in itself black has no individuality, so as to be characterizable by possibility.
As concerns the third proof about the soul, it is eternal for one school of philosophers, and is only possible in the attaching of itself to bodies, and therefore against those philosophers the argument does not apply= But for those who admit that the soul comes into existence-and one school of philosophers has believed that it is impressed on matter and follows its temperament, as is indicated by Galen in certain passages-it comes into existence in matter and its possibility is related to its matter.’ And according to the theory of those who admit that it comes into existence, although it is not impressed on matter-which means that it is possible for the rational soul to direct matter-the possibility prior to the becoming is relative to matter , and although the soul is not impressed on matter, it is attached to it, for it is its directing principle and uses it as an instrument, and in this way its possibility is relative to matters
I
say
What
he says in this section is true, as will be clear to you from our explanation
of the nature of the possible.
Then
Ghazali, objecting to the philosophers, says:
And the answer is: To reduce possibility, necessity, and impossibility to rational concepts is correct, and as for the assertion that the concepts of reason form its knowledge, and knowledge implies a thing known, let them be answered: it cannot be said that receptivity of colour and animality and the other concepts, which are fixed in the mind according to the philosophers-and this is what constitutes the sciences-have no objects ; still these objects have no real existence in the external world, and the philosophers arc certainly right in saying that universals exist only in the mind, not in the external world, and that in the external world there arc only particular individuals, which arc apprehended by the senses, not by reason; and yet these individuals arc the reason why the mind abstracts from them a concept separated from its rational matter; therefore receptivity of colour is a concept, separate in the mind from blackness and whiteness, although in reality a colour which is neither black nor white nor of another colour cannot be imagined,’ and receptivity of colour is fixed in the mind without any specification-now, in the same way, it can be said that possibility is a form which exists in minds, not in the exterior world, and if this is not impossible for other concepts,, there is no impossibility in what we have said.
I say:
This
argument is sophistical because possibility is a universal which has
individuals outside the mind like all the other universals, and knowledge is
not knowledge of the universal concept, but it is a knowledge of individuals in
a universal way which the mind attains in the case of the individuals, when it
abstracts from them one common nature which is distributed among the different
matters. The nature, therefore, of the universal is not identical with the
nature of the things of which it is a universal. Ghazali
is here in error, for he assumes that the nature of possibility is the nature
of the universal, without there being individuals on which this universal, i.e.
the universal concept of possibility, depends. The universal, however, is not
the object of knowledge; on the contrary through it the things become known,
although it exists potentially in the nature of the things known;’ otherwise
its apprehension of the individuals, in so far as they are universals, would be
false. This apprehension would indeed be false if the nature of the object
known were essentially individual, not accidentally individual, whereas the
opposite is the case: it is accidentally individual, essentially universal.
Therefore if the mind did not apprehend the individuals in so far as they are
universal, it would be in error and make false judgements about them. But if it
abstracts those natures which subsist in the individual things from their
matter, and makes them universal, then it is possible that it judges them
rightly; otherwise it would confuse those natures, of which the possible is
one.
The
theory of the philosophers that universals exist only in the mind, not in the
external world, only means that the universals exist actually only in the mind,
and not in the external world, not that they do not exist at all in the
external world, for the meaning is that they exist potentially, not actually in
the external world; indeed, if they did not exist at all in the outside world
they would be false. Since universals exist outside the mind in potency and
possibilities exist outside the soul in potency, the nature of universals in
regard
to
this resembles that of possibilities. And for this reason Ghazali tried to deceive people by a sophism, for he
compared possibility to the universals because of their both being potentially
in reality, and then he assumed that the philosophers assert that universals do
not exist at all outside the soul; from which he deduced that possibility does
not exist outside the soul. What an ugly and crude sophism!
Ghazali says:
As regards their assertion that, if it were assumed that rational beings had vanished or had neglected possibility, possibility itself would not have disappeared, we answer: ‘If it were assumed that they had vanished, would not the universal concepts, i.e. the genera and species, have disappeared too?’ and if they agree to this, this can only mean that universals are only concepts in the mind; but this is exactly what we say about possibility, and there is no difference between the two cases; if they, however, affirm that they are permanent in the knowledge of God,’ the same may be said about possibility, and the argument is valid, and our aim of showing the contradiction in this theory has been attained.
I say:
This
argument shows his foolishness and proneness to contradiction. The most
plausible form in which it might be expressed would be to base it on two
premisses: the first, that the evident proposition that possibility is
partially individual, namely, outside the soul, partially universal, namely,
the universal concept of the individual possibles, is not true; and the second,
that it was said that the nature of the individual possibles outside the soul
is identical with the nature of the universal of possibility in the mind; and
in this case the possible would have neither a universal nor an individual
nature, or else the nature of the individual would have to be identical with
that of the universal. All this is presumptuous, and how should it be else, for
in a way the universal has an existence outside the soul.
Ghazali says:
And as regards their subterfuge where the impossible is concerned, that it is related to the matter qualified by its opposite, as it cannot take the place of its opposite this cannot be the case with every impossible, for that God should have a rival is impossible, but there is no matter to which this impossibility could be related. If they say the impossibility of God’s having a rival, means that the solitude of God in His essence and His uniqueness are necessary and that this solitude is proper to Him, we answer: This is not necessary, for the world exists with Him, and He is therefore not solitary. And if they say that His solitude so far as a rival is concerned is necessary, and that the opposite of the necessary is the impossible, and that the impossible is related to Him, we answer: In this case the solitude of God in regard to the world is different from His solitude in regard to His equal and in this case His solitude in regard to His rival is necessary, and in regard to the created world not necessary.’
I say:
All
this is vain talk, for it cannot be doubted that the judgments of the mind have
value only in regard to the nature of things outside the soul. If there were outside
the soul nothing possible or impossible, the judgment of the mind that things
are possible or impossible would be of as much value as no judgment at all, and
there would be no difference between reason and illusion. And that there should
be a rival to God is just as impossible in reality as God’s existence is i
necessary in reality. But there is no sense in wasting more words on this
question.
Ghazali says:
The subterfuge concerning the becoming of the souls is worthless too, for they have individual essences and a possibility prior to their becoming, and at that time there is nothing with which they could be brought into relation. Their argument contends that it is possible for matter that the souls direct it is a remote relation and, if this satisfies you, you might as well say that the possibility of the souls becoming lies in the power of Him who can on His own authority produce them, for the souls are then related to the Agent-although they are not impressed on Him-in the same way as to the body, on which they are not impressed either. And since the imprint is made neither on the one substrate nor on the other, there is no difference between the relation to the agent and that to the patient.
I say:
He
wants to force those who assume the possibility of the soul’s becoming without
there being an imprint in matter to concede that the possibility in the
recipient is like the possibility in the agent, because the act proceeds from
the agent and therefore these two possibilities are similar. But this is a
shocking supposition, for, according to it, the soul would come to the body as
if it directed it from the outside, as the artisan directs his product, and the
soul would not be a form in the body, just as the artisan is not a form in his
product. The answer is that it is not impossible that there should be amongst i
the entelechies which conduct themselves like formsb something that is separate
from its substratum as the steersman is from his ships and the artisan from his
tool, and if the body is like the instrument of the
soul,
the soul is a separate form, and then the possibility which is in the
instrument is not like the possibility which is in the agent; no, the
instrument is in both conditions, the possibility which is in the patient and
the possibility which is in the agent, and therefore the instruments are the
mover and the moved, and in so far as they are the mover, there is in them the
possibility which is in the agent, and in so far as they are moved, the
possibility which is in the recipient.’ But the supposition that the soul is a
separate entity does not force them into the admission that the possibility
which is in the recipient is identical= with the possibility which is in the
agent. Besides, the possibility which according to the philosophers is in the
agent is not only a rational judgement, but refers to something outside the
soul. Therefore his argument does not gain by assimilating one of these two
possibilities to the other. And since Ghazali
knew that all these arguments have no other effect than to bring doubts and
perplexity to those who cannot solve them-which is an act of wicked
sophists, he says:
And if it is said you have taken good care in all your objections to oppose the difficulties by other difficulties, but nothing of what you yourself have adduced is free from difficulty, we answer: the objections do show the falsity of an argument, no doubt, and certain aspects of the problem are solved in stating the opposite view and its foundation. We have not committed ourselves to anything more than to upsetting their theories, and to showing the faults in the consequence of their proofs so as to demonstrate their incoherence. We do not seek to attack from any definite point of view, and we shall not transgress the aim of this book, nor give full proofs for the temporal production of the world, for our intention is merely to refute their alleged knowledge of its eternity. But after finishing this book we shall, if it pleases God, devote a work to establishing the doctrine of truth, and we call it ‘The Golden Mean in Dogmatic Beliefs’,’ in which we shall be engaged in building up, as in this book we have been in destroying.
I say:
To
oppose difficulty with difficulty does not bring about destruction, but only perplexity
and doubts in him who acts in this way, for why should he think one of the two
conflicting theories reasonable and the opposite one vain? Most of the
arguments with which this man Ghazali opposes
the philosophers are doubts which arise when certain parts of the doctrine of
the philosophers come into conflict with others, and when those differences are
compared with each other; but this is an imperfect refutation. A perfect
refutation would be one that succeeded in showing the futility of their system
according to the facts themselves, not such a one as, for instance, his
assumption that it is permissible for the opponents of the philosophers to
claim that possibility is a mental concept in the same way as the philosophers
claim this for the universal. For if the truth of this comparison between the
two were conceded, it would not follow that it was untrue that possibility was
a concept dependent on reality, but only either that the universal existed in
the mind only was not true, or that possibility existed in the mind only was
not true. Indeed, it would have been necessary for him to begin by establishing
the truth, before starting to perplex and confuse his readers, for they might
die before they could get hold of that book, or he might have died himself
before writing it. But this book has not yet come into my hands’ and perhaps he
never composed it, and he only says that he does not base this present book on
any doctrine, in order that it should not be thought that he based it on that
of the Ash’arites. It appears from the books ascribed to him that in
metaphysics he recurs to the philosophers. And of all his books this is most
clearly shown and most truly proved in his book called The Niche for Lights.
Ghazali says:
Know that this is part of the first question, for according to the philosophers the existence of the world, having no beginning, does not end either; it is eternal, without a final term. Its disappearance and its corruption cannot be imagined; it never began to exist in the condition in which it exists’ and it will never cease to exist in the condition in which it exists.
Their four arguments which we have mentioned in our discussion of its eternity in the past refer also to its eternity in the future, and the objection is the same without any difference. They say that the world is caused, and that its cause is without beginning or end, and that this applies both to the effect and to the cause, and that, if the cause does not change, the effect cannot change either; upon this they build their proof of the impossibility of its beginning, and the same applies to its ending. This is their first proof.
The second proof is that an eventual annihilation of the world must occur alter its existence, but ‘after’ implies an affirmation of time.
The third proof is that the possibility of its existence does not end, and that therefore its possible existence may conform to the possibility.’ But this argument has no force, for we regard it as impossible that the world should not have begun, but we do not regard it as impossible that it should last eternally, if God should make it last eternally, for it is not necessary that what begins has also an end, although it is necessary for an act to have a beginning and an initial term. Only Abu Hudhail al-Allaf thought that the world must needs have an end, and he said that, as in the past infinite circular movements are impossible, so they are in the future s but this is wrong, for the whole of the future never enters into existence either simultaneously or successively, whereas the whole of the past is there simultaneously but not successively.’ And since it is clear that we do not regard the incorruptibility of the world as impossible from a rational point of view-we regard indeed its incorruptibility and corruptibility as equally possible-we know only through the Divine Law which of the two possibilities will be realized. Therefore let us not try to solve this problem by mere reason!
I say:
His
assertion that the argument of the philosophers for the eternity of the world in
the past applies also to its eternity in the future is true, and equally the
second argument applies to both cases. But his assertion that the third argument
is not equally valid for the future and for the past, that indeed we regard the
becoming of the world in the past as impossible, but that with the exception of
Abu Hudhail al-Allaf, who thought that the eternity of the world was impossible
in either direction, we do not regard its eternity in the future as absolutely
impossible, is not true. For when it was conceded to the philosophers that the
possibility of the world had no beginning and that with this possibility a
condition of extension, which could measure this possibility, was connected in
the same way as this condition of extension is connected with the possible
existent, when it is actualized, and it was also evident that this extension had
no initial term, the philosophers were convinced that time had no initial term,
for this extension is nothing but time, and to call it timeless eternitys is
senseless. And since time is connected with possibility and possibility with
existence in motion, existence in motion has no first term either. And the
assertion of the theologians that everything which existed in the past had a
first term is futile, for the First exists in the past eternally, as it exists
eternally in the future. And their distinction here between the first term and
its acts requires a proof, for the existence of the temporal which occurs in the
past is different from the existence of the eternal which occurs in the past.
For the temporal which has occurred in the past is finite in both directions,
i.e. it has a beginning and an end, but the eternal which has occurred in the
past has neither beginning nor end.’ And therefore, since the philosophers
have not admitted that the circular movement has a beginning, they cannot be
forced to admit that it has an end, for they do not regard its existence in the
past as transitory, and, if some philosopher does regard it as such, he
contradicts himself and therefore the statement is true that everything that has
a beginning has an end. That anything could have a beginning and no end is not
true, unless the possible could be changed into the eternal, for everything that
has a beginning is possible. And that anything could be liable to corruption and
at the same time could be capable of eternity is something incomprehensible’
and stands in need of examination. The ancient philosophers indeed examined this
problem, and Abu Hudhail agrees with the philosophers in saying that whatever
can be generated is corruptible, and he kept strictly to the consequence which
follows from the acceptance of the principle of becoming. As to those who make a
distinction between the past and the future, because what is in the past is
there in its totality, whereas the future never enters into existence in its
totality (for the future enters reality only successively), this is deceptive,
for what is in reality past is that which has entered time and that which has
entered time has time beyond it in both directions and possesses totality. But
that which has never entered the past in the way the temporal enters the past
can only be said in an equivocal way to be in the past; it is infinitely
extended, with the past rather than in the past, and possesses no totality in
itself, although its parts are totalities. And this, if it has no initial term
beginning in the past, is in fact time itself. For each temporal beginning is a
present, and each present is preceded by a past, and both that which exists
commensurable with time, and time commensurable with it, must necessarily be
infinite. Only the parts of time which are limited by time in both directions
can enter the past, in the same way as only the instant which is everchanging
and only the instantaneous motion of a thing in movement in the spatial
magnitude in which it moves can really enter the existence of the moved.’ And
just as we do not say that the past of what never ceased to exist in the past
ever entered existence at an instant-for this would mean that its existence had
a beginning and that time limited it in both directions-so it stands with that
which is simultaneous with time, not in time. For of the circular movements only
those that time limits enter into represented existence,’ but those that are
simultaneous with time do not afterwards enter past existence, just as the
eternally existent does not enter past existence, since no time limits it. And
when one imagines an eternal entity whose acts are not delayed after its
existence-as indeed must be the case with any entity whose existence is
perfect-then, if it is eternal and does not enter past time, it follows
necessarily that its acts also cannot enter past time, for if they did they
would be finite and this eternal existent would be eternally inactive and what
is eternally inactive is necessarily impossible. And it is most appropriate for
an entity, whose existence does not enter time and which is not limited by time,
that its acts should not enter existence either, because there is no difference
between the entity and its acts. If the movements of the celestial bodies and
what follows from them are acts of an eternal entity, the existence of which
does not enter the past, then its acts do not enter past time either. For it is
not permissible to say of anything that is eternal that it has entered past
time, nor that it has ended, for that which has an end has a beginning. For
indeed, our statement that it is eternal means the denial of its entering past
time and of its having had a beginning. He who, assuming that it entered past
time, assumes that it must have a beginning begs the question. It is, therefore,
untrue that what is coexistent with eternal existence, has entered existence,
unless the eternal existence has entered existence by entering past time.
Therefore our statement `everything past must have entered existence’ must be
understood in two ways: first, that which has entered past existence must have
entered existence, and this is a true statement; secondly, that which is past
and is inseparably connected with eternal existence cannot be truly said to have
entered existence, for our expression `entered existence’ is incompatible with
our expression `connected with eternal existence’. And there is here no
difference between act and existence. For he who concedes the existence of an
entity which has an eternal past must concede that there exist acts, too, which
have no beginning in the past. And it by no means follows from the existence of
His acts that they must have entered existence, just as it by no means follows
from the past permanency of His essence that He has ever entered existence. And
all this is perfectly clear, as you see.
Through
this First Existent acts can exist which never began and will never cease, and
if this were impossible for the act, it would be impossible, too, for existence,
for every act is connected with its existent in existence. The theologians,
however, regarded it as impossible that God’s act should be eternal, although
they regarded His existence as eternal, and that is the gravest error. To apply
the expression `production’ for the world’s creation as the Divine Law does
is more appropriate than to use it of temporal production, as the Ash’arites
did,’ for the act, in so far as it is an act, is a product, and eternity is
only represented in this act because this production and the act produced have
neither beginning nor end. And I say that it was therefore difficult for Muslims
to call God eternal and the world eternal, because they understood by
`eternal’ that which has no cause. Still I have seen some of the theologians
tending rather to our opinion.
Ghazali says:
Their fourth proof is similar to the third, for they say that if the world were annihilated the possibility of its existence would remain, as the possible cannot become impossible. This possibility is a relative attribute and according to them everything that becomes needs matter which precedes it and everything that vanishes needs matter from which it can vanish, but the matter and the elements do not vanish, only the forms and accidents vanish which were in them.
I say:
If
it is assumed that the forms succeed each other in one substratum in a circular
way and that the agent of this succession is an eternal one, nothing impossible
follows from this assumption. But if this succession is assumed to take place in
an infinite number of matters or through an infinite number of specifically
different forms, it is impossible, and equally the assumption is impassible that
such a succession could occur without an eternal agent or through a temporal
agent. For if there were an infinite number of matters, an actual infinite would
exist, and this is impossible. It is still more absurd to suppose that this
succession could occur through temporal agents, and therefore from this point of
view it is only true that a man must become from another man, on condition that
the successive series happens in one and the same matter and the perishing of
the curlier men can become the matter of the later. Besides, the existence of
the earlier men is also in some respect the efficient cause and the instrument
for the later-all this, however, in an accidental way, for those men are nothing
but the instrument for the Agent, who does not cease to produce a man by means
of a man and through the matter of a man. The student who does not distinguish
all these points will not be able to free himself from insoluble doubts. Perhaps
God will place you and us among those who have reached the utmost truth
concerning what may and must be taught about God’s infinite acts. What I have
said about all these things is not proved here, but must be examined by the
application of the conditions which the ancients have explained and the rules
which they have established for scientific research. Besides, he who would like
to be one of those who possess the truth should in any question he examines
consult those who hold divergent opinions.’
Ghazali says:
The answer to all this has been given above. I only single out this question because they have two proofs for it.
The first proof is that given by Galen, who says: If the sun, for instance, were liable to annihilation, decay would appear in it over a long period. But observation for thousands of years shows no change in its size and the fact that it has shown no loss of power through such a long time shows that it does not suffer corruption.’ There are two objections to this: The first is that the mode of this proof-that if the sun suffers corruption, it must suffer loss of power, and as the consequence is impossible the antecedent must be impossible too-is what the philosophers call a conjunctive hypothetical proposition,’ and this inference is not conclusive, because its antecedent is not true, unless it is connected with another condition. In other words the falsehood of the consequence of the proposition `if the sun suffers corruption, it must become weaker’ does not imply the falsehood of the antecedent, unless either (z) the antecedent is bound up with the additional condition that, if it suffers corruption through decay, it must do so during a long period, or () it is seriously proved that there is no corruption except through decay. For only then does the falsehood of the consequence imply the falsehood of the antecedent. Now, we do not concede that a thing can only become corrupt through decay; decay is only one form of corruption, for it is not impossible that what is in a state of perfection should suddenly suffer corruption.
I say:
He
says in his objection here to this argument that there is no necessary relation
between antecedent and consequent, because that which suffers corruption need
not become weaker, since it can suffer corruption before it has become weaker.
The conclusion, however, is quite sound, when it is assumed that the corruption
takes place in a natural way, not by violence, and it is assumed besides that
the celestial body is an animal, for all animals super corruption only in a
natural way-they necessarily decay before their corruption. However, our
opponents do not accept these premisses, so far as they concern heaven, without
proof. And therefore Galen’s statement is only of dialectical value. The
safest way to use this argument is to say that, if heaven should suffer
corruption, it would either disintegrate into the elements of which it is
composed or, losing the form it possesses, receive another, as happens with the
four elements when they change into one another. If, however, heaven passed away
into the elements, those elements would have to be part of another world, for it
could not have come into being from the elements contained in this world, since
these elements are infinitely small, compared with its size, something like a
point in relation to a circle.’ Should heaven, however, lose its form and
receive another there would exist a sixth element opposed to all the others,
being neither heaven, nor earth, nor water, nor air, nor fire. And all this is
impossible. And his statement that heaven does not decay ; is only a common
opinion, lacking the force of the immediately evident axioms; and it is
explained in the Posterior Analytics of what kind these premisses area
Ghazali says:
The second objection is that, if it were conceded to Galen that there is no corruption except through decay, how can it be known that decay does not affect the sun? His reliance on observation is impossible, for observations determine the size only by approximation, and if the sun, whose size is said to be approximately a hundred and seventy times that of the earth, decreased, for instance, by the size of mountains the difference would not be perceptible to the senses. Indeed, it is perhaps already in decay, and has decreased up to the present by the size of mountains or more; but perception cannot ascertain this, for its knowledge in the science of optics works only by supposition and approximation. The same takes place with sapphire and gold, which, according to them, are composed out of elements and which are liable to corruption. Still, if you left a sapphire for a hundred years, its decrease would be imperceptible, and perhaps the decrease in the sun during the period in which it has been observed stands in proportion to its size as the decrease of the sapphire to its size in a hundred years. This is imperceptible, and this fact shows that his proof is utterly futile.
We have abstained from bringing many proofs of the same kind as the wise disdain. We have given only this one to serve as an example of what we have omitted, and the have restricted ourselves to the four proofs which demand that their solution should be attempted in the way indicated above.
I say:
If
the sun had decayed and the parts of it which had disintegrated during the
period of its observation were imperceptible because of the size of its body,
still the effect of its decay on bodies in the sublunary world would be
perceptible in a definite degree, for everything that decays does so only
through the corruption and disintegration of its parts, and those parts which
disconnect themselves from the decaying mass must necessarily remain in the
world in their totality or change into
other parts, and in either case an appreciable change must occur in the world,
either in the number or in the character of its parts. And if the size of the
bodies could change, their actions and affections would change too, and if their
actions and affections, and especially those of the heavenly bodies, could
change, changes would arise in the sublunary world. To imagine, therefore, a
dissipation of the heavenly bodies is to admit a disarrangement in the divine
order which, according to the philosopher, prevails in this world. This proof is
not absolutely strict.
Ghazali says:
The philosophers have a second proof of the impossibility of the annihilation of the world. They say: The substance of the world could not be annihilated, because no cause could be imagined for this and the passage from existence to non-existence cannot take place without a cause. This cause must be either the Will of the Eternal, and this is impossible, for if He willed the annihilation of the world after not having willed it, He would have changed; or it must be assumed that God and His Will are in all conditions absolutely the same, although the object of His Will changes from non-existence to existence and then again from existence to non-existence. And the impossibility of which we have spoken in the matter of a temporal existence through an eternal will, holds also for the problem of annihilation. But we shall add here a still greater difficulty, namely, that the object willed is without doubt an act of the wiper, for the act of him who acts after not having acted-even if he does not alter in his own nature-must necessarily exist after having not existed: if he remained absolutely in the state he was in before, his act would not be there. But when the world is annihilated, there is no object for God’s act, and if He does not perform anything (for annihilation is nothing), how could there be an action? Suppose the annihilation of the world needed a new act in God which did not exist before, what could such an act be? Could it be the existence of the world? But this is impossible, since what happens is on the contrary the termination of its existence. Could this act then be the annihilation of the world? But annihilation is nothing at all, and it could therefore not be an act. For even in its slightest intensity an act must be existent, but the annihilation of the world is nothing existent at all; how could it then be said that he who caused it was an agent, or he who effected it its cause?`
The philosophers say that to escape this difficulty the theologians are divided into four sects and that each sect falls into an absurdity.
I say:
He
says here that the philosophers compel the theologians who admit the
annihilation of the world to draw the consequence that from the Eternal, who
produced the world, there proceeds a new act, i.e. the act of annihilation, just
as they compelled them to draw this consequence in regard to His temporal
production. About this problem everything has been said already in our
discussion of temporal production, for the same difficulties as befall the
problem of production apply to annihilation, and there is no sense in repeating
ourselves. But the special difficulty he mentions here is that from the
assumption of the world’s temporal production it follows that the act of the
agent attaches itself to non-existence, so that in fact the agent performs a
non-existing act and this seemed to all the parties too shocking to be
accepted,’ and therefore they took refuge in theories he mentions later. But
this consequence follows necessarily from any theory which affirms that the act
of the agent is connected with absolute creation-that is, the production of
something that did not exist before in potency and was not a possibility which
its agent converted from potency into actuality, a theory which affirms in fact
that the agent created it out of nothing. But for the philosophers the act of
the agent is nothing but the actualizing of what is in potency, and this act is,
according to them, attached to an existent in two ways, either
in production, by converting the thing from its potential existence into
actuality so that its non-existence is terminated, or
in destruction, by converting the thing from its actual existence into
potential existence, so that it passes into a relative non-existence. But he who
does not conceive the act of the agent in this way has to draw the consequence
that the agent’s act is attached to non-existence in both ways, in production
as in destruction; only as this seems clearer in the case of destruction, the
theologians could not defend themselves against their opponents. For it is clear
that for the man who holds the theory of absolute annihilation the agent must
perform something non-existent, for when the agent converts the thing from
existence into absolute non-existence, he directs his first intention to
something non-existent, by contrast with what happens when he converts it from
actual existence into potential existence; for in this conversion the passage
into non-existence is only a secondary fact. The same consequence applies to
production, only here it is not so obvious, for the existence of the thing
implies the annulment of its non-existence, and therefore production is nothing
but the changing of the non-existence of a thing into its existence; but since
this movement is directed towards production, the theologians could say that the
act of the agent is attached solely to production. They could not, however, say
this in regard to destruction, since this movement is directed towards
non-existence. They have, therefore, no right to say that in production the act
of the agent attaches itself only to production, and not to the annulment of
non-existence, for in production the annulment of non-existence is necessary,
and therefore the act of the agent must necessarily be attached to
non-existence. For according to the doctrine of the theologians, the existent
possesses only two conditions: a condition in which it is absolutely
non-existent and a condition in which it is actually existent., The act of the
agent, therefore, attaches itself to it, neither when it is actually existent,
nor when it is non-existent . Thus only the following alternatives remain:
either the act of the agent does not attach itself to it at all, or it attaches
itself to non-existence,’ and non-existence changes itself into existence. He
who conceives the agent in this way must regard the change of nonexistence
itself into existence, and of existence itself into non-existence, as possible,
and must hold that the act of the agent can attach itself to the conversion of
either of these opposites into the other. This is absolutely impossible in
respect to the other opposites, not to speak of non-existence and existence.
The
theologians perceived the agent in the way the weaksighted perceive the shadow
of a thing instead of the thing itself and then mistake the shadow for it. But,
as you see, all these difficulties arise for the man who has not understood that
production is the conversion of a thing from potential into actual existence,
and that destruction is the reverse, i.e. the change from the actual into the
potentials It appears from this that possibility and matter are necessarily
connected with anything becoming, and that what is subsistent in itself can be
neither destroyed nor produced.
The
theory of the Ash’arites mentioned here by Ghazali,
which regards the production of a substance, subsistent in itself, as possible,
but not so its destruction, is an extremely weak one, for the consequences which
apply to destruction apply also to production, only, it was thought, because in
the former case it is more obvious that there was here a real difference. He
then mentions the answers of the different sects to the difficulty which faces
them on the question of annihilation.
Ghazali says:
The Mu’tazilites say: the act proceeding from Him is an existent, i.e. extinction, which He does not create in a substratum; at one and the same moment it annihilates the whole world and disappears by itself, so that it does not stand in need of another extinction and thus of an infinite regress.
And
mentioning this answer to the difficulty, he says:
This is wrong for different reasons. First, extinction is not an intelligible existent, the creation of which can be supposed. Moreover, why, if it is supposed to exist, does it disappear by itself without a cause for its disappearance? Further, why does it annihilate the world? For its creation and inherence in the essence of the world are impossible, since the inherent meets its substratum and exists together with it if only in an instant; if the extinction and existence of the world could meet, extinction would not be in opposition to existence and would not annihilate it’ and, if extinction is created neither in the world nor in a substratum, where could its existence be in order to be opposed to the existence of the world? Another shocking feature in this doctrine is that God cannot annihilate part of the world without annihilating the remainder; indeed He can only create an extinction which annihilates the world in its totality, for if extinction is not in a substratum, it stands in one and the same relation to the totality of the world.
I say:
The
answer is too foolish to merit refutation. Extinction and annihilation are
synonymous, and if God cannot create annihilation,
He
cannot create extinction either. And even if we suppose extinction to be an
existent, it could at most be an accident, but an accident without a substratum
is absurd. And how can one imagine that the non-existent causes non-existence?
All this resembles the talk of the delirious.
Ghazali says:
The second sect, the Karramites, say that the act of God is annihilation, and annihilation signifies an existent which He produces in His essence and through which the world becomes non-existent. In the same way, according to them, existence arises out of the act of creation which He produces in His essence and through which the world becomes existent. Once again, this theory is wrong as it makes the Eternal a substratum for temporal production . Further it is incomprehensible, for creation and likewise annihilation cannot be understood except as an existence, related to will and power, and to establish another entity besides the will and the power and their object, the world, is inconceivable.
I say:
The
Karramites believe that there are here three factors: the agent, the act-which
they call creation-and an object, i.e. that to which the act attaches itself,
and likewise they believe that in the process of annihilation there are three
factors: the annihilator, the act-which they call annihilation-and a
non-existent. They believe that the act inheres in the essence of the agent and
according to them the rise of such a new condition’ in the agent does not
imply that the agent is determined by a temporal cause, for such a condition is
of a relative and proportional type, and a new relation and proportion does not
involve newness in the substratum; only those new events involve a change in the
substratum which change the essence of the substratum, e.g. the changing of a
thing from whiteness to blackness. Their statement, however, that the act
inheres in the essence of the agent is a mistake; it is only a relation which
exists between the agent and the object of the act which, when assigned to the
agent, is called `act’ and when assigned to the object is called `passivity’
Through this assumption the Karramites are not obliged to admit that, as the
Ash’arites believed, the Eternal produces temporal reality’ or that the
Eternal is not eternal, but the consequence which is forced upon them is that
there must be a cause anterior to the Eternal, for, when an agent acts after not
having acted, all the conditions for the existence of his object being fulfilled
at the time he did not act, there must have arisen a new quality in the agent at
the time when he acts, and each new event demands a new causes So there must be
another cause before the first, and so on ad infinitum.
Ghazali says:
The third sect is that of the Ash’arites, who say that
accidents pass away by themselves and cannot be imagined to persist, for if they
persisted they could not, for this very reason, be imagined ever to pass away.b
Substances do not persist by themselves either, but persist by a persistence
added to their existence. And if God had not created persistence, substances
would have become non-existent through the nonexistence of persistence. This too
is wrong, in so far as it denies the evidence of the senses by saying that black
and white do not persist and that their existence is continually renewed; reason
shrinks from this, as it does, too, from the statement that the body renews its
existence at each moment, for reason judges that the hair which is on a man’s
head today is identical with, not similar to, the hair that was there yesterday,
and judges the same about the black and the white.’ There is yet another
difficulty, namely, that when things persist through persistence, God’s
attributes must persist through persistence and this persistence persists
through persistence and so on ad in finitum.
I say:
This
theory of the flux of all existing things is a useless one, although many
ancients held it, and there is no end to the impossibilities it implies. How
could an existent come into existence, when it passes away by itself and
existence passes away through its passing away? If it passed away by itself, it
would have to come into existence by itself, and in this case that by which it
becomes existent would be identical with that by which it passes away and this
is impossible. For existence is the opposite of passing away, and it is not
possible that two opposites should occur in the same thing in one and the same
connexion. Therefore in a pure existent no passing away can be imagined, for if
its existence determined its passing away, it would be non-existent and existent at one and the same moment, and
this is impossible. Further, if the existents persist through the persistence of
an attribute by itself, will this absence of change in them occur through their
existence or through their non-existence? The latter is impossible, so it
follows that they persist because of their existence. If, then, all existents
must persist because they are existent, and non-existence is something that can
supervene upon them, why in Heaven’s name do we need this attribute of
persistence to make them persist? All this resembles a case of mental disorder.
But let us leave this sect, for the absurdity of their theory is too clear to
need refutation.
Ghazali says:
The fourth sect are a group of Ash’arites who say that accidents pass away by themselves, but that substances pass away when God does not create motion or rest or aggregation and disintegration in them, for it is impossible that a body should persist which is neither in motion nor at rest, since in that case it becomes non-existent. The two parties of the Ash’arites incline to the view that annihilation is not an act, but rather a refraining from acting, since they do not understand how non-existence can be an act. All these different theories being false---say the philosophers -it cannot any longer be asserted that the annihilation of the world is possible, even if one were to admit that the world had been produced in time; for although the philosophers concede that the human soul has been produced, they claim the impossibility of its annihilation by means of arguments which are very close to those we have mentioned. For, according to the philosophers, nothing that is self-subsistent and does not inhere in a substratum’ can be imagined as becoming non-existent after its existence, whether it is produced or eternal.’ If one objects against them, that when water is boiled it disappears, they answer that it does not disappear, but is only changed into steam and the steam becomes water again, and its primary matter, i.e. its hyle, the matter in which the form of water inhered, persists when the water has become air, for the hyle only loses the form of water and takes up that of air; the air, having become cold again, condenses into water, but does not receive a new matter, for the matter is common to the elements and only the forms are changed in it.
I say:
He
who affirms that accidents do not persist for two moments, and that their
existence in substances is a condition of the persistence of those substances,
does not know how he contradicts himself, for if the substances are a condition
of the existence of the accidents-since the accidents cannot exist without the
substances in which they inhere-and the accidents are assumed to be a condition
for the existence of the substances, the substances must be necessarily a
condition for their own existence; and it is absurd to say that something is a
condition for its own existence. Further, how could the accidents be such a
condition, since they themselves do not persist for two moments? For, as the
instant is at the same time the end of their privation and the beginning of
their period of existence, the substance mint be destroyed in this instant, for
in this instant there is neither anything of the privative period nor anything
of the existent. If there were in the instant anything of the privative period
or of the existent, it could not be the end of the former and the beginning of
the latter.’ And on the whole, that something which does not persist two
moments should be made a condition for the persistence of something for two
moments is absurd. Indeed, a thing that persists for two moments is more capable
of persisting than one which does not persist for two moments, for the existence
of what does not persist for two moments is at an instant, which is in flux, but
the existence of what persists for two moments is constant, and how can what is
in flux be a condition for the existence of the constant, or how can what is
only specifically persistent be a condition for the persistence of the
individually persistent? This is all senseless talk. One should know that he who
does not admit a Kyle for the corruptible must
regard the existent as simple and as not liable to corruption, for the simple
does not alter and does not exchange its substance for another substance.
Therefore Hippocrates says `if man were made out of one thing alone, he could
not suffer by himself’ ,’ i.e. he could not suffer corruption or change. And
therefore he could not have become either, but would have to be an eternal
existent. What he says here about Avicenna of the difference between the
production and the destruction of the soul is without sense.
Ghazali says, answering the
philosophers:
The answer is: So far as concerns the different sects you have mentioned, although we could defend each of them and could show that your refutation on the basis of your principle is not valid, because your own principles are liable to the same kind of objection, we will not insist on this point, but we will restrict ourselves to one sect and ask: How will you refute the man who claims that creation and annihilation take place through the will of God: if God wills, He creates, and if He wills, He annihilates, and this is the meaning of His being absolutely powerful, and notwithstanding this He does not alter in Himself, but it is only His act that alters? And concerning your objection that, inasmuch as an act must proceed from the agent, it cannot be understood which act can proceed from Him, when He annihilates, we answer: What proceeds from Him is a new fact, and the new fact is non-existence, for there was no non-existence; then it happened as something new, and this is what proceeds from Him. And if you say: Non-existence is nothing, how could it then proceed from Him? we reply: If non-existence is nothing, how could it happen? Indeed, `proceeding from Him’ does not mean anything but that its happening is related to His power. If its happening has an intelligible meaning, why should its relation to His power not be reasonable?
I say:
All
this is sophistical and wrong. The philosophers do not deny that a thing becomes
non-existent when a destroying agent destroys it; they only say that the
destroying act does not attach itself to it, in so far as the thing becomes
non-existent, but in so far as it changes from actual being to potential being,
and non-existence results from this change, and it is in this way that
non-existence is related to the agent. But it does not follow from the fact that
its non-existence occurs after the act of the agent that the agent performs it
primarily and essentially. For when it was conceded to Ghazali
during the discussion of this problem that the non-existence of the corrupting
thing will necessarily occur after the act of the corrupting agent, he drew the
conclusion that its non-existence would follow essentially and primarily from
the act, but this is impossible. For the agent’s act does not attach itself to
its non-existence in so far as it is non-existent, i.e. primarily and
essentially. And therefore , if the perceptible existences were simple, they
could neither be generated nor destroyed except through the act of the agent
being attached to their nonexistence essentially and primarily. But the act of
the agent is only attached to non-existence accidentally and secondarily through
its changing the object from actual existence into another form of existence in
an act followed by non-existence, as from the change of a fire into air there
follows the non-existence of the fire. This is the philosophical theory of
existence and non-existence.
Ghazali says:
And what is the difference between you and the man who denies absolutely that non-existence can occur to accidents and forms, and who says that non-existence is nothing at all and asks how then it could occur and be called an occurrence and a new event? But no doubt non-existence can be represented as occurring to the accidents, and to speak of it as occurring has a sense whether you call it something real or not. And the relation of this occurrence, which has a reasonable sense, to the power of the Omnipotent, also has an intelligible meaning.’
I say:
That
non-existence of this kind occurs is true, and the philosophers admit it,
because it proceeds from the agent according to a second intention and
accidentally; but it does not follow from its proceeding or from its having a
reasonable meaning that it happens essentially or primarily, and the difference
between the philosophers and those who deny the occurrence of non-existence is
that the philosophers do not absolutely deny the occurrence of non-existence,
but only its occurring primarily and essentially through the agent. For the act
of the agent does not attach itself necessarily, primarily, and essentially to
non-existence, and according to the philosophers non-existence happens only
subsequently to the agent’s act in reality. The difficulties ensue only for
those who affirm that the world can be annihilated in an absolute annihilation.
Ghazali says:
Perhaps the philosophers will answer: This difficulty is only acute for those who allow the non-existence of a thing after its existence, for those may be asked what the reality is that occurs. But according to us philosophers the existing thing does not become non-existent, for we understand by the fact that the accidents become non-existent the occurrence of their opposites, which are existing realities, and not the occurrence of mere non-existence which is nothing at all, and how could what is nothing at all be said to occur? For if hair becomes white, it is simply whiteness that occurs, for whiteness is something real; but one cannot say that what occurs is the privation of blackness.’
I say:
This
answer on behalf of the philosophers is mistaken, for the philosophers do not
deny that non-existence occurs and happens through the agent, not, however,
according to a primary intention as would be the consequence for one who assumes
that a thing can change into pure nothingness; no, non-existence, according to
them, occurs when the form of the thing that becomes non-existent disappears,
and the opposite form appears. Therefore the following objection which Ghazali
makes is valid.
Ghazali says:
This is wrong for two reasons. The first is: Does the occurrence of whiteness imply the absence of blackness? If they deny it, this is an affront to reason, and if they admit it, it may be asked: Is what is implied identical with that which implies? To admit this is a contradiction, for a thing does not imply itself, and if they deny it, it may be asked: Has that which is implied an intelligible meaning? If they deny it, we ask, `How do you know, then, that it is implied, for the judgement that it is implied presupposes that it has a sensible meaning?’ If they admit this, we ask; `Is this thing which is implied and has a sensible meaning, i.e. the absence of blackness, eternal or temporal?’ The answer `eternal’ is impossible; if they answer `temporal’, how should what is described as occurring temporally not be clearly understood? And if they answer `neither eternal nor temporal, this is absurd, for if it were said before the occurrence of whiteness that blackness was non-existent, it would be false, whereas afterwards it would be true.’ It occurred, therefore, without any doubt, and this occurrence is perfectly intelligible and must be related to the Omnipotent.
I say:
This
is an occurrence which is perfectly intelligible and must be related to the
Omnipotent, but only accidentally and not essentially, for the act of the agent
does not attach itself to absolute non-existence, nor to the non-existence of
anything, for even the Omnipotent cannot bring it about that existence should
become identical with nonexistence. The man who does not assume matter cannot be
freed from this difficulty, and he will have to admit that the act of the agent
is attached to non-existence primarily and essentially. All this is clear, and
there is no need to say more about it. The philosophers, therefore, say that the
essential principles of transitory things are two: matter and form, and that
there is a third accidental principle, privation, which is a condition of the
occurrence of what becomes, namely as preceding it: if a thing becomes, its
privation disappears, and if it suffers corruption, its privation arises.’
Ghazali says:
The second objection is that according to the philosophers there are accidents which can become non-existent otherwise than through their contrary, for instance, motion has no contrary, and the opposition between motion and rest is, according to the philosophers, only the opposition of possession and non-possession, i.e. the opposition of being and not-being, not the opposition of one being to another being,’ and the meaning of rest is the absence of motion, and, when motion ceases, rest does not supervene as its contrary, but is a pure non-existence.’ The same is the case with those qualities which belong to the class of entelechies, like the impression of the sensible species on the vitreous humour of the eyes and still more the impression of the forms of the intelligibles on the soul; they become existent without the cessation of a contrary, and their non-existence only means the cessation of their existence without the subsequent occurrence of their opposites, and their disappearance is an example of pure nonexistence which arises. The occurrence of such a non-existence is an understandable fact, and that which can be understood as occurring by itself, even if it is not a real entity, can be understood as being related to the power of the Omnipotent. Through this it is clear that, when one imagines an event as occuring through the eternal Will, it is unessential, whether the occurring event is a becoming or a vanishing.
I say:
On the contrary, when non-existence is assumed to proceed from the agent as existence proceeds from it, there is the greatest difference between the two. But when existence is assumed as a primary fact and non-existence as a secondary fact, i.e. when non-existence is assumed to take place through the agent by means of a kind of existence, i.e. when the agent transforms actual existence into potential existence by removing the actuality-which is a quality possessed by the substrate-then it is true. And from this point of view the philosophers do not regard it as impossible that the world should become non-existent in the sense of its changing into another form, b for non-existence is in this case only a subsequent occurrence and a secondary fact. But what they regard as impossible is that a thing should disappear into absolute nothingness, for then the act of the agent would have attached itself to non-existence, primarily and essentially.
Throughout
this discussion Ghazali has mistaken the
accidental for the essential, and forced on the philosophers conclusions which
they themselves regard as impossible. This is in general the character of the
discussion in this book. A more suitable name, therefore, for this book would be
`The Book of Absolute Incoherence’, or `The Incoherence of Ghazali’,
not `The Incoherence of the Philosophers’, and the best name for my book `The
Distinction between Truth and Incoherent Arguments’.’
Ghazali says:
All philosophers, except the materialists, agree that the world has a maker, and that God is the maker and agent of the world and the world is His act and His work. And this is an imposture where their principle is concerned, nay it cannot be imagined that according to the trend of their principle the world is the work of God, and this for three reasons, from the point of view of the agent, from the point of view of the act, and from the point of view of the relation common to act and agent. As concerns the first point, the agent must be willing, choosing, and knowing what he wills to be the agent of what he wills, but according to them God does not will, He has no attribute whatever, and what proceeds from Him proceeds by the compulsion of necessity. The second point is that the world is eternal, but ‘act’ implies production. And the third point is that God is unique, according to their principles, from all points of view, and from one thing-according to their principles-there can only proceed one thing. The world, however, is constituted out of diverse components; how could it therefore proceed from Him?
I say:
Ghazali’s words ‘The
agent must be willing, choosing, and knowing what he wills to be the agent of
what he wills’ are by no means self evident and cannot be accepted as a
definition of the maker of the world without a proof, unless one is justified in
inferring from the empirical to the divine. For we observe in the empirical
world two kinds of agents, one which
performs exclusively one thing and this essentially, for instance warmth
which causes heat and coldness which causes cold; and this kind is called by the
philosophers natural agents. The second kind of agents are those that perform a
certain act at one time and its opposite at another; these, acting only out of
knowledge and deliberation, are called by the philosophers voluntary and
selective agents. But the First Agent cannot be described as having either of
these two actions, in so far as these are ascribed to transitory things by the
philosophers. For he who chooses and wills lacks the things which he wills, and
God cannot lack anything He wills. And he who chooses makes a choice for himself
of the better of two things, but God is in no need of a better condition.
Further, when the willer has reached his object, his will ceases and, generally
speaking, will is a passive quality and a change, but God is exempt from
passivity and change. God is still farther distant from natural action, for the
act of the natural thing is a necessity in its substance, but is not a necessity
in the substance of the willer, and belongs to its entelechy. In addition,
natural action does not proceed from knowledge: it has, however, been proved
that God’s act does proceed from knowledge. The way in which God becomes an
agent and a willer has not become clear in this place, since there is no
counterpart to His will in the empirical world. How is it therefore possible to
assert that an agent can only be understood as acting through deliberation and
choice? For then this definition is indifferently applied to the empirical and
the divine, but the philosophers do not
acknowledge this extension of the definition, so that from their refusal to
acknowledge this definition as applying to the First Agent, it cannot be
inferred that they deny that He acts at all.
This
is, of course, self-evident and not the philosophers are impostors, but he who
speaks in this way, for an impostor is one who seeks to perplex, and does not
look for the truth. He, however, who errs while seeking the truth cannot be
called an impostor, and the philosophers, as a matter of fact, are known to seek
the truth, and therefore they are by no means impostors. There is no difference
between one who says that God wills with a will which does not resemble the
human will, and one who says that God knows through a knowledge which does not
resemble human knowledge; in the same way as the quality of His knowledge cannot
be conceived, so the quality of His will cannot be conceived.
Ghazali
says:
We will now test each of these three reasons at the same time as the illusory arguments which the philosophers give in their defence.
The first reason. We say: ‘Agent’ means someone from whom there proceeds an act with the will to act according to choice and with the knowledge of the object willed. But according to the philosophers the world stands in relation to God as the effect to the cause, in a necessary connexion which God cannot be imagined to sever, and which is like the connexion between the shadow and the man, light and the sun, but this is not an act at all. On the contrary, he who says that the lamp makes the light and the man makes the shadow uses the term vaguely, giving it a sense much wider than its definition, and uses it metaphorically, relying on the fact that there is an analogy between the object originally meant by it and the object to which it is transferred, i.e. the agent is in a general sense a cause, the lamp is the cause of the light, and the sun is the cause of luminosity; but the agent is not called a creative agent from the sole fact that it is a cause, but by its being a cause in a special way, namely that it causes through will and through choice. If, therefore, one said that neither a wall, nor a stone, nor anything inanimate is an agent, and that only animals have actions, this could not be denied and his statement would not be called false. But according to the philosophers a stone has an action, namely falling and heaviness and a centripetal tendency, just as fire has an action, namely heating, and a wall has an action, namely a centripetal tendency and the throwing of a shadow, and, according to them each of these actions proceeds from it as its agent; which is absurd.’
I say:
There are in brief two points here, the first of which is that only those who act from deliberation and choice are regarded as acting causes, and the action of a natural agent producing something else is not counted among acting causes, while the second point is that the philosophers regard the procession of the world from God as the necessary connexion obtaining between shadow and the person, and luminosity and the sun, and the downward rolling in relation to the stone, but that this cannot be called an action because the action can be separated from the agent.
I say:
All
this is false. For the philosophers believe that there are four causes: agent,
matter, form, and end. The agent is what causes some other thing to pass from
potency to actuality and from nonexistence to existence; this actualization
occurs sometimes from deliberation and choice, sometimes by nature, and the
philosophers do not call a person who throws a shadow an agent, except
metaphorically, because the shadow cannot be separated from the man, and by
common consent the agent can be separated from its object, and the philosophers
certainly believe that God is separated’ from the world and according to them
He is not to be classed with this kind of natural cause. Nor is He an agent in
the sense in which any empirical agent, either voluntary or involuntary, is; He
is rather the agent of these causes, drawing forth the Universe from
non-existence to existence and conserving it, and such an act is a more perfect
and glorious one than any performed by the empirical agents. None of these
objections therefore touch them, for they believe that God’s act proceeds from
Him through knowledge, not through any necessity which calls for it, either in
His essence or outside His essence, but through His grace and His bounty. He is
necessarily endowed with will and choice in their highest form, since the
insufficiency which is proper to the empirical willer does not pertain to Him.
And these are the very words of Aristotle in one of his metaphysical treatises:
We were asked how God could bring forth the world out of nothing, and convert it
into something out of nothing, and our answer is this: the Agent must be such
that His capacity must be proportionate to His power and His power proportionate
to His will and His will proportionate to His wisdom, if not, His capacity would
be weaker than His power, His power weaker than His will, and His will weaker
than His wisdom. And if some of His powers were weaker than others, there would
be no difference between His powers and ours, and imperfection would attach to
Him as to us-a very blasphemous theory. But in the opposite case each of these
powers is of the utmost perfection. When He wills He has the power, and when He
has the power He has the capacity and all this with the greatest wisdom. And He
exists, making what He wants out of nothing. And this is only astonishing
through this imperfection which is in us. And Aristotle said also: Everything
that is in this world is only set together through the power which is in it from
God; if this power did not exist in the things, they could not last the
twinkling of an eyes
I
say:
Composite
existence is of two classes; in the one class the composition is something
additional to the existence of the composed, but in the other the composition is
like the existence of matter and form and in these existents the existence
cannot be regarded as anterior to the composition, but on the contrary the
composition is the cause of their existence and anterior to it. If God therefore
is the cause of the composition of the parts of the world, the existence of
which is in their composition, then He is the cause of their existence and
necessarily he who is the cause of the existence of anything whatever is its
agent. This is the way in which according to the philosophers this question must
be understood, if their system is truly explained to the student.
Ghazali
says, speaking on behalf of the philosophers:
The philosophers may say: we call an object anything that has no necessary existence by itself, but exists through another, and we call its cause the agent, and we do not mind whether the cause acts by nature or voluntarily, just as you do not mind whether it acts by means of an instrument or without an instrument, and just as ‘act’ is a genus subdivided into ‘acts which occur by means of an instrument’ and ‘acts which occur without an instrument’, so it is a genus subdivided into ‘acts which occur by nature’ and ‘acts which occur voluntarily’. The proof is that, when we speak of an act which occurs by nature, our words ‘by nature’ are not contradictory to the term ‘act’; the words ‘by nature’ are not used to exclude or contradict the idea of act, but are meant only to explain the specific character of the act, just as, when we speak of an act effected directly without an instrument, there is no contradiction, but only a specification and an explanation. And when we speak of a ‘voluntary act’, there is not a redundancy as in the expression a ‘living being-man’;’ it is only an explanation of its specific character, like the expression, ‘act performed by means of an instrument’. If, however, the word ‘act’ included the idea of will, and will were essential to act, in so far as it is an act, our expression ‘natural act’ would be a contradiction.
I say:
The
answer, in short, has two parts. The first is that everything that is necessary
through another thing is an object of what is necessary by itself,z but this can
be opposed, since that through which the ‘necessary through another’ has its
necessary existence need not be an agent, unless by ‘through which it has its
necessary existence’ is meant that which is really an agent, i.e. that which
brings potency into act. The second part is that the term ‘agent’ seems like
a genus for that which acts by choice and deliberation and for that which acts
by nature; this is true, and is proved by our definition of the term
‘agent’. Only this argument wrongly creates the impression that the
philosophers do not regard the first agent as endowed with will. And this
dichotomy that everything is either of necessary existence by itself or existent
through another is not self-evident.
Ghazali, refuting the philosophers,
says:
This designation is wrong, for we do not call any cause whatsoever an agent, nor any effect an object; for, if this were so, it would be not right to say that the inanimate has no act and that only the living exhibit acts-a statement generally admitted.
I
say:
His assertion that not every cause is called an
agent is true, but his argument that the inanimate is not called an agent is
false, for the denial that the inanimate exhibits acts excludes only the
rational and voluntary act, not act absolutely, for we find that certain
inanimate things have powers to actualize things like themselves; e.g. fire,
which changes anything warm and dry
into another fire like itself, through converting it from what it has in potency
into actuality. Therefore fire cannot make a fire like itself in anything that
has not the potency or that is not in readiness to receive the actuality of
fire. The theologians, however, deny that fire is an agent, and the discussion
of this problem will follow later. Further, nobody doubts that there are in the
bodies of animals powers which make the food a part of the animal feeding itself
and generally direct the body of the animal. If we suppose them withdrawn, the
animal would die, as Galen says. And through this direction we call it alive,
whereas in the absence of these powers we call it dead.
Ghazali goes on:
If the inanimate is called an agent, it is by metaphor, in the same way as it is spoken of metaphorically as tending and willing, since it is said that the stone falls down, because it tends and has an inclination to the centre, but in reality tendency and will can only be imagined in connexion with knowledge and an object desired and these can only be imagined in animals.
I say:
If
by ‘agent’ or ‘tendency’ or ‘willing’ is meant the performance of an
act of a willer, it is a metaphor, but when by these expressions is meant that
it actualizes another’s potency, it is really an agent in the full meaning of
the word.
Ghazali
then says:
When the philosophers say that the term ‘act’ is a genus which is subdivided into ‘natural act’ and ‘voluntary act’, this cannot he conceded; it is as if one were to say that ‘willing’ is a genus which is subdivided into willing accompanied by knowledge of the object willed, and willing without knowledge of the object willed. This is wrong, because will necessarily implies knowledge, and likewise act necessarily implies will.
I say:
The
assertion of the philosophers that ‘agent’ is subdivided into
‘voluntary’ and ‘non-voluntary agent’ is true, but the comparison with a
division of will into rational and irrational is false, because in the
definition of will knowledge is included, so that the division has no sense. But
in the definition of ‘act’ knowledge is not included, because actualization
of another thing is possible without knowing it. This is clear, and therefore
the wise say that God’s word: ‘a wall which wanted to fall to pieces” is a
metaphor.
Ghazali proceeds:
When you affirm that your expression ‘natural act’ is not a contradiction in terms you are wrong; there is as a matter of fact a contradiction when ‘natural act’ is taken in a real sense, only this contradiction is not at once evident to the understanding nor is the incompatibility of nature and act felt acutely, because this expression is employed metaphorically; for since nature is in a certain way a cause and the agent is also a cause, nature is called an agent metaphorically. The expression ‘voluntary act’ is as much redundant as the expression ‘he wills and knows what he wills’.
I say:
This
statement is undoubtedly wrong, for what actualizes another thing, i.e. acts on
it, is not called agent simply by a metaphor, but in reality, for the definition
of ‘agent’ is appropriate to it. The division of ‘agent’ into
‘natural’ and ‘voluntary agent’ is not the division of an equivocal
term, but the division of a genus. Therefore the division of ‘agent’ into
‘natural’ and ‘voluntary agent’ is right, since that which actualizes
another can also be divided into these two classes.
Ghazali says:
However, as it can happen that ‘act’ is used metaphorically and also in its real sense, people have no objection in saying ‘someone acted voluntarily’, meaning that he acted not in a metaphorical sense, but really, in the way in which it is said ‘he spoke with his tongue’, or ‘he saw with his eye’. For, since one is permitted to rise ‘heart’ metaphorically for ‘sight’, and motion of the head or hand for word-for one can say ‘He nodded assent’-it is not wrong to say ‘He spoke with his tongue and he saw with his eye’, in order to exclude any idea of metaphor. This is a delicate point, but let us be careful to heed the place where those stupid people slipped.
I say:
Certainly it is a delicate point that a man with scientific pretensions should give such a bad example and such a false reason to explain the repugnance people seem to have in admitting the division of ‘act’ into ‘natural’ and ‘voluntary act’. No one ever says ‘He saw with his eye, and he saw without his eye’ in the belief that this is a division of sight; we only say ‘He saw with his eye’ to emphasize the fact that real sight is meant, and to exclude the metaphorical sense of ‘sight’. And the intelligent in fact think that for the man who understands immediately that the real meaning is intended, this connecting of sight with the eye is almost senseless. But when one speaks of ‘natural’ and ‘voluntary act’, no intelligent person disagrees that we have here a division of ‘act’. If, however, the expression ‘voluntary act’ were similar to ‘sight with the eye’ the expression ‘natural act’ would be metaphorical. But as a matter of fact the natural agent has an act much more stable than the voluntary agent, for the natural agent’s act is constant-which is not the case with the act of the voluntary agent. And therefore the opponents of the theologians might reverse the argument against them and say that ‘natural act’ is like ‘sight with the eye’ and ‘voluntary act’ is a metaphor-especially according to the doctrine of the Ash’arites, who do not acknowledge a free will in man and a power to exercise an influence on reality. And if this is the case with the agent in the empirical world, how can we know that it is an accurate description of the real Agent in the divine world to say that He acts through knowledge and will?
Ghazali
says, speaking on behalf of the philosophers:
The philosophers may reply: The designation ‘agent’ is known only through language. However, it is clear to the mind that the cause of a thing can be divided into voluntary and non-voluntary cause, and it may be disputed whether or not in both cases the word ‘act’ is used in a proper sense, but it is not possible to deny this since the Arabs say that fire burns, a sword cuts, that snow makes cold, that scammony purges, that bread stills hunger and water thirst, and our expression ‘he beats’ means he performs the act of beating, and ‘it burns’ it performs the act of burning, and ‘he cuts’ he performs the act of cutting; if you say, therefore, that its use is quite metaphorical, you are judging without any evidence.
I say:
I This, in short, is a common-sense argument. The
Arabs indeed call that which exerts
an influence on a thing, even if not voluntary, an agent, in a proper, not in a
metaphorical, sense. This argument, however, is dialectical and of no
importance.
Ghazali
replies to this:
The answer is that all this is said in a metaphorical way and that only a voluntary act is a proper act. The proof is that, if we assume an event which is based on two facts, the one voluntary, the other involuntary, the mind relates the act to the voluntary fact. Language expresses itself in the same way, for if a man were to throw another into a fire and kill him, it is the man who would be called his killer, not the fire. If, however, the term were used in the same sense of the voluntary and the non-voluntary, and it were not that the one was a proper sense, the other a metaphorical, why should the killing be related to the voluntary, by language, usage, and reason, although the fire was the proximate cause of the killing and the man who threw the other into the fire did nothing but bring man and fire together? Since, however, the bringing together is a voluntary act and the influence of the fire non-voluntary, the man is called a killer and the fire only metaphorically so. This proves that the word ‘agent’ is used of one whose act proceeds from his will, and, behold, the philosophers do not regard God as endowed with will and choice.
I
say:
This
is an answer of the wicked who heap fallacy on fallacy. Ghazali is above this, but perhaps the people of his time obliged
him to write this book to safeguard himself against the suspicion of sharing the
philosophers’ view. Certainly nobody attributes the act to its instrument, but
only to its first mover. He who killed a man by fire is in the proper sense the
agent and the fire is the instrument of the killing, but when a man is burned by
a fire, without this fact’s depending on someone’s choice, nobody would say
that the fire burned him metaphorically. The fallacy he employs here is the
wellknown one a dicto secundum quid ad
dictum simpliciter, e.g. to say of a negro, because his teeth are white,
that he is white absolutely. The philosophers do not deny absolutely that God
wills, for He is an agent through knowledge and from knowledge, and He performs
the better of two contrary acts, although both are possible; they only affirm
that He does not will in the way that man wills.
Ghazali says, answering in defence of
the philosophers:
If the philosophers say: We do not mean anything by God’s being an agent but that He is the cause of every existent besides Himself and that the world has its subsistence through Him, and if the Creator did not exist, the existence of the world could not be imagined. And if the Creator should be supposed non-existent, the world would be non-existent too, just as the supposition that the sun was non-existent would imply the non-existence of light. This is what we mean by His being an agent. If our opponents refuse to give this meaning to the word ‘act’, well, we shall not quibble about words.
I
say:
Such
an answer would mean that the philosophers would concede to their opponents that
God is not an agent, but one of those causes without which a thing cannot reach
its perfection; and the answer is wrong, for against them it might be deduced
from it that the First Cause is a principle, as if it were the form of the
Universe, in the way the soul is a principle for the body; no philosopher,
however, affirms this.
Then
Ghazali says, answering the philosophers:
We say: Our aim is to show that such is not the meaning of ‘act’ and ‘work’. These words can mean only that which really proceeds from the will. But you reject the real meaning of ‘act’, although you use this word, which is honoured amongst Muslims. But one’s religion is not perfect when one uses words deprived of their sense. Declare therefore openly that God has no act, so that it becomes clear that your belief is in opposition to the religion of Islam, and do not deceive by saying that God is the maker of the world and that the world is His work, for you use the words, but reject their real sense!
I say:
This
would indeed be a correct conclusion against the philosophers, if they should
really say what Ghazali makes them say. For in
this case they could indeed be forced to admit that the world has neither a
natural nor a voluntary agent, nor that there is another type of agents besides
these two. He does not unmask their imposture by his words, but lie himself
deceives by ascribing to them theories which they do not hold.
Ghazali says:
The second reason for denying that the world is according to the principle of the philosophers an act of God is based on the implication of the notion of an act. ‘Act’ applies to temporal production, but for them the world is eternal and is not produced in time. The meaning of ‘act’ is ‘to convert from not-being into being by producing it’ and this cannot be imagined in the eternal, as what exists already cannot be brought into existence. Therefore ‘act’ implies a temporal product, but according to them the world is eternal; how then could it be God’s act?
I say:
If
the world were by itself eternal and existent (not in so far as it is moved, for
each movement is composed of parts which are produced), then, indeed, the world
would not have an agent at all. But if the meaning of ‘eternal’ is that it
is in everlasting production and that this production has neither beginning nor
end, certainly the term ‘production’ is more truly applied to him who brings
about an everlasting production than to him who procures a limited production.
In this way the world is God’s product and the name ‘production’ is even
more suitable for it than the word ‘eternity’, and the philosophers only
call the world eternal to safeguard themselves against the word ‘product’ in
the sense of ‘a thing produced after a state of nonexistence, from something,
and in time’.
Then Ghazali
says, on behalf of the philosophers:
The philosophers may perhaps say: The meaning of ‘product’ is ‘that which exists after its non-existence’. Let us therefore examine if what proceeds from the agent when He produces, and what is connected with Him, is either pure existence, or pure non-existence, or both together. Now, it is impossible to say that previous non-existence was connected with Him, since the agent cannot exert influence upon non-existence, and it is equally impossible to say ‘both together’, for it is clear that nonexistence is in no way connected with the agent, for non-existence qua non-existence needs no agent at all. It follows therefore that what is connected with Him is connected with Him in so far as it is an existent, that what proceeds from Him is pure existence, and that there is no other relation to Him than that of existence. If existence is regarded as everlasting, then this relation is everlasting, and if this relation is everlasting, then the term to which this relation refers is the most illustrious and the most enduring in influence, because at no moment is non-existence connected with it. Temporal production implies therefore the contradictory statements that it must be connected with an agent, that it cannot be produced, if it is not preceded by non-existence, and that non-existence cannot be connected with the agent.
And if previous non-existence is made a condition of the existent, and it is said that what is connected with the agent is a special existence, not any existence, namely an existence preceded by non-existence, it may be answered that its being preceded by non-existence cannot be an act of an agent or a deed of a maker, for the procession of this existence from its agent cannot be imagined, unless preceded by non-existence; neither, therefore , can the precedence of this non-existence be an act of the agent and connected with him, nor the fact that this existence is preceded by non-existence. Therefore to make non-existence a condition for the act’s becoming an act is to impose as a condition one whereby the agent cannot exert any influence under any condition.’
I say:
This
is an argument put forward on this question by Avicenna from the philosophical
side. It is sophistical, because Avicenna leaves out one of the factors which a
complete division would have to state.
For
he says that the act of the agent must be connected either with an existence or
with a non-existence, previous to it and in so far as it is non-existence, or
with both together, and that it is impossible that it should be connected with
non-existence, for the agent does not bring about non-existence and, therefore,
neither can it effect both together. Therefore the agent can be only connected
with existence, and production is nothing but the connexion of act with
existence, i.e. the act of the agent is only bringing into existence,’ and it
is immaterial whether this existence be preceded by non-existence or not. But
this argument is faulty, because the act of the agent is only connected with
existence in a state of non-existence, i.e. existence in potentiality, and is
not connected with actual existence, in so far as it is actual, nor with
non-existence, in so far as it is non-existent. It is only connected with
imperfect existence in which non-existence inheres. The act of the agent is not
connected with non-existence, because non-existence is not actual; nor is it
connected with existence which is not linked together with non-existence, for
whatever has reached its extreme perfection of existence needs neither causation
nor cause. But existence which is linked up with non-existence only exists as
long as the producer exists. The only way to escape this difficulty is to assume
that the existence of the world has always been and will always be linked
together with non-existence, as is the case with movement, which is always in
need of a mover. And the acknowledged philosophers believe that such is the case
with the celestial world in its relation to the Creator, and a fortiori with the
sublunary world. Here lies the difference between the created and the
artificial, for the artificial product, once produced, is not tied up with
non-existence which would be in need of an agent for the continued sustenance of
the product.’
Ghazali
continues:
And your statement, theologians, that what exists cannot be made to exist, if you mean by it, that its existence does not begin after its nonexistence, is true; but if you mean that it cannot become an effect at the time when it exists, we have shown that it can only become an effect at the time when it exists, not at the time when it does not exist. For a thing only exists when its agent causes it to exist, and the agent only causes it to exist at the time when, proceeding from it, it exists, not when the thing does not exist; and the causation is joined with the existence of the agent and the object, for causation is the relation between cause and effect. Cause, effect, and causation are simultaneous with existence and there is no priority here, and therefore there is causation only for what exists, if by ‘causation’ is meant the relation through which the agent and its object exist. The philosophers say: It is for this reason that we have come to the conclusion that the world, which is the work of God, is without beginning and everlasting, and that never at any moment was God not its agent, for existence is what is joined with the agent and as long as this union lasts existence lasts, and, if this union is ever discontinued, existence ceases. It is by no means what you theologians mean, that if the Creator were supposed to exist no longer, the world could still persist; you, indeed, believe that the same relation prevails as between the builder and the building, for the building persists when the builder has disappeared. But the persistence of the building does not depend on the builder, but on the strength of the structure in its coherence, for if it had not the power of coherence-if it were like water, for example-it would not be supposed to keep the shape which it received through the act of the agent.’
I
say:
Possibly
the world is in such a condition, but in general this argument is not sound. For
it is only true that the causing agent is always connected with the effect , in
so far as the effect actually exists without this actuality’s having any
insufficiency and any potency, if one imagines that the essence of the effect
lies in its being an effect, for then the effect can only be an effect
through the causation of the agent. But if its becoming an effect through a
cause is only an addition to its essence, then it is not necessary that its
existence should cease when the relation between the causing agent and the
effect is interrupted. If, however, it is not an addition, but its essence
consists in this relation of being an effect, then what Avicenna says is true.
However, it is not true of the world, for the world does not exit on account of
this relation, but it exists on account of its substance and the relation is
only accidental to it. Perhaps what Avicenna says is true concerning the forms
of the celestial bodies, in so far as they perceive the separate immaterial
forms; and the philosophers affirm this, because it is proved that there are
immaterial forms whose existence consists in their thinking, whereas knowledge
in this sublunary world only differs from its object because its object inheres
in matter.’
Ghazali, answering the philosophers,
says:
Our answer is that the act is connected with the agent only in so far as it comes into being, but not in so far as it is preceded by non-existence nor in so far as it is merely existent. According to us the act is not connected with the agent for a second moment after its coming to be, for then it exists; it is only connected with it at the time of its coming to be in so far as it comes to be and changes from non-existence into existence. If it is denied the name of becoming, it cannot be thought to be an act nor to be connected with the agent. Your statement, philosophers, that a thing’s coming to be means its being preceded by non-existence, and that its being preceded by non-existence does not belong to the act of the agent and the deed of the producer, is true; but this prior non-existence is a necessary condition for the existent’s being an act of the agent. For existence not preceded by non-existence is everlasting, and cannot be truly said to be an act of the agent. Not all conditions necessary to make an act an act need proceed from the agent’s act; the essence, power, will, and knowledge of the agent are a condition of his being an agent, but do not derive from him. An act can only be imagined as proceeding from an existent, and the existence, will, power, and knowledge of the agent are a condition of his being an agent, although they do not derive from him.’
I
say:
All this is true. The act of the agent is only
connected with the effect, in so far as it is moved, and the movement from
potential to actual being is what is called becoming. And, as Ghazali
says, nonexistence is one of the conditions for the existence of a movement
through a mover. Avicenna’s argument that when it is a condition for the act
of the agent to be connected with the existence, the absence of this connexion
implies that the agent is connected with its opposite, i.e. non-existence, is
not true. But the philosophers affirm that there are existents whose essential
specific differences consist in motion, e.g. the winds and so on; and the
heavens and the sublunary bodies belong to the genus of existents whose
existence lies in their movement, and if this is true, they are eternally in a
continual becoming. And therefore, just as the eternal existent is more truly
existent than the temporal, similarly that which is eternally in becoming is
more truly coming to be than that which comes to be only during a definite time.
And if the substance of the world were not in this condition of continual
movement, the world would not, after its existence, need the Creator, just as a
house after being completed and finished does not need the builder’s
existence, unless that were true which Avicenna tried to prove in the preceding
argument, that the existence of the world consists only in its relation to the
agent; and we have already said that we agree with. him so far as this concerns
the forms of the heavenly bodies.
Therefore the world is during the time of its
existence in need of the presence of its agent for both reasons together,
namely, because the substance of the world is continually in motion and because
its form, through which it has its subsistence and existence, is of the nature
of a relation, not of the nature of a quality, i.e. the shapes and states which
have been enumerated in the chapter on quality. A form which belongs to the
class of quality, and is included in it, is, when it exists and its existence is
finished, in no need of an agent. All this will solve the problem for you, and
will remove from you the perplexity which befalls man through these
contradictory statements.’
Ghazali
says, on behalf of the philosophers:
The philosophers might say: If you acknowledge that it is possible that the act should be simultaneous with the agent and not posterior to it, it follows that if the agent is temporal the act must be temporal, and if the agent is eternal the act must be eternal. But to impose as a condition that the act must be posterior in time to the agent is impossible, for when a man moves his finger in a bowl of water, the water moves at the same time as the finger, neither before nor after, for if the water moved later than the finger, finger and water would have to be in one and the same space before the water disconnected itself, and if the water moved before the finger, the water would be separated from the finger and notwithstanding its anteriority would be an effect of the finger performed for its sake. But if we suppose the finger eternally moving in the water, the movement of the water will be eternal too, and will be, notwithstanding its eternal character, an effect and an object, and the supposition of eternity does not make this impossible. And such is the relation between the world and God.
I say:
This
is true in so far as it concerns the relation of movement and mover, but in
regard to the stable existent or to that which exists without moving or resting
by nature (if there exist such things ) and their relation to their cause, it is
not trues Let us therefore admit this relation between the agent and the world
only in so far as the world is in motion. As for the fact that the act of every
existent must be conjoined with its existence, this is true, unless something
occurs to this existent which lies outside its nature, or one or another
accident occurs to it,b and it is immaterial whether this act be natural or
voluntary. See, therefore, what the Ash’arites did who assumed an eternal
existent, but denied that He acted during His eternal existence, but then,
however, allowed this agent to act eternally in the future, so that the eternal
existence of the Eternal would become divided into two parts, an eternal past
during which He does not act and an eternal future during which He acts! But for
the philosophers all this is confusion and error.
Ghazali
answers the philosophers on the question of priority:
We do not say that the simultaneity of agent and act is impossible, granted that the act is temporal, e.g. the motion of the water, for this happens after its non-being and therefore it can be an act, and it is immaterial whether this act be posterior to the agent or simultaneous with him. It is only an eternal act that we consider impossible, for to call an act that which does not come into being out of not-being is pure metaphor and does not conform to reality. As to the simultaneity of cause and effect, cause and effect can be either both temporal or both eternal, in the way in which it may be said that the eternal knowledge is the cause of the fact that the Eternal is knowing; we are not discussing this, but only what is called an act. For the effect of a cause is not called the act of a cause, except metaphorically. It can only be called an act on condition that it comes into being out of non-being. And if a man thinks he may describe the everlasting Eternal metaphorically as acting on something, what he thinks possible is only the use of a metaphor. And your argument, philosophers-that if we suppose the movement of the water to be eternal and everlasting with the movement of the finger, this does not prevent the movement of the water from being an act-rests on a confusion, for the finger has no act, the agent is simply the man to whom the finger belongs, that is the man who wills the movement; and, if we suppose him to be eternal, then the movement of the finger is his act, because every part of this movement comes out of not-beings and in this sense it is an act. So far as the motion of the water is concerned, we do not say that it occurs through the act of this man-it is simply an act of God. In any case, it is only an act in so far as it has come to be, and if its coming to be is everlasting, it is still an act, because it has come to be.
Then
Ghazali gives the philosophers’ answer:
The philosophers may say: ‘If you acknowledge that the relation of the act to the agent, in so far as this act is an existent, is like the relation of effect and cause and you admit that the causal relation may be everlasting, we affirm that we do not understand anything else by the expression “that the world is an act” than that it is an effect having an everlasting relation to God. Speak of this as an “act” or not just as you please, for do not let us quibble about words when their sense has once been established.’
Ghazali says:
Our answer is that our aim in this question is to show that you philosophers use those venerable names without justification, and that God according to you is not a true agent, nor the world truly His act, and that you apply this word metaphorically-not in its real sense. This has now been shown.
I say:
In
this argument he supposes that the philosophers concede to him that they only
mean by God’s agency that He is the cause of the world, and nothing else, and
that cause and effect are simultaneous. But this would mean that the
philosophers had abandoned their original statement, for the effect follows only
from its cause, in so far as it is a formal or final cause, but does not
necessarily follow from its efficient cause, for the efficient cause frequently
exists without the effect’s existing. Ghazali
acts here like a guardian who tries to extract from his ward the confession
of having done things he did not allow him to do. The philosophers’
theory, indeed, is that the world has an agent acting from eternity and
everlasting, i.e. converting the world eternally from non-being into being. This
question was formerly a point of discussion between Aristotelians and
Platonists. Since Plato believed in a beginning of the world, there could not in
his system be any hesitation in assuming a creative agent for the world. But
since Aristotle supposed the world to be eternal, the Platonists raised
difficulties against him, like the one which occupies us here, and they said
that Aristotle did not seem to admit a creator of the world. If was therefore
necessary for the Aristotelians to defend him with arguments which establish
that Aristotle did indeed believe that the world has a creator and an agent.
This will be fully explained in its proper place.
The
principal idea is that according to the Aristotelians the celestial bodies
subsist through their movement, and that He who bestows this movement is in
reality the agent of this movement and, since the existence of the celestial
bodies only attains its perfection through their being in motion, the giver of
this motion is in fact the agent of the celestial bodies. Further, they prove
that God is the giver of the unity through which the world is united, and the
giver of the unity which is the condition of the existence of the composite;
that is to say, He provides the existence of the parts through which the
composition occurs, because this action of combining is their cause (as is
proved), and such is the relation of the First Principle to the whole world. And
the statement that the act has come to be, is true, for it is movement, and the
expression ‘eternity’ applied to it means only that it has neither a first
nor a last term. Thus the philosophers do not mean by the expression
‘eternal’ that the world is eternal through eternal constituents,s for the
world consists of movement. And since the Ash’arites did not understand this,
it was difficult for them to attribute eternity at the same time to God and to
the world. Therefore the term’ eternal becoming’ is more appropriate to the
world than the term ‘eternity’.
Ghazali
says:
The third reason why it is impossible for the philosophers to admit according to their principle that the world is the act of God is because of a condition which is common to the agent and the act, namely, their assertion that out of the one only one can proceed. Now the First Principle is one in every way, and the world is composed out of different constituents. Therefore according to their principle it cannot be imagined that the world is the act of God.
I say:
If
one accepts this principle, and its consequences, then indeed the answer is
difficult. But this principle has only been put forward by the later
philosophers of Islam.’
Then
Ghazali says, on behalf of the philosophers:
The philosophers may say perhaps: The world in its totality does not proceed from God without a mediator; what proceeds from Him is one single existent, and this is the first of the created principles, namely, abstract intellect, that is a substance subsisting by itself, not possessing any volume, knowing itself and knowing its principle, which in the language of the Divine Law is called ‘angel’. From it there proceeds a third principle, and from the third a fourth, and through this mediation the existent beings come to be many. The differentiation and multiplicity of the act can proceed either from a differentiation in active powers, in the way that we act differently through the power of passion and through the power of anger; or through a differentiation of matters, as the sun whitens a garment which has been washed, blackens the face of man, melts certain substances and hardens others; or through a differentiation of instruments, as one and the same carpenter saws with a saw, cuts with an axe, bores with an awl;’ or this multiplication of the act can proceed through mediation, so that the agent does one act, then this act performs another act, and in this way the act multiplies. All these divisions are impossible in the First Principle, because there is no differentiation nor duality, nor multiplicity in His essence, as will be proved in the proofs of His unity. And there is here neither a differentiation of matters-and the very discussion refers to the first effect, which is, for example, primary matter, nor a differentiation of the instrument, for there is no existent on the same level as God-and the very discussion refers to the coming into existence of the first instrument. The only conclusion possible is that the multiplicity which is in the world proceeds from God through mediation, as has been stated previously.
I say:
This
amounts to saying that from the One, if He is simple, there can proceed only
one. And the act of the agent can only be differentiated and multiplied either
through matters (but there are no matters where He is concerned), or through an
instrument (but there is no instrument with Him). The only conclusion therefore
is that this happens through mediation, so that first the unit proceeds from
Him, and from this unit another, and from this again another, and that it is in
this way that plurality comes into existence.
Then Ghazali
denies this, and says:
We answer: The consequence of this would be that there is nothing in the world composed of units, but that everything that exists is simple and one, and each unit is the effect of a superior unit and the cause of an inferior, till the series ends in an effect which has no further effect, just as the ascending series ends in a cause which has no other cause. But in reality it is not like this, for, according to the philosophers, body is composed of form and Kyle, and through this conjunction there arises one single thing; and man is composed out of body and soul and body does not arise out of soul, nor soul out of body: they exist together through another cause. The sphere, too, is, according to them, like this, for it is a body possessing a soul and the soul does not come to be through the body, nor the body through the soul; no, both proceed from another cause. How do these compounds, then, come into existence? Through one single cause? But then their principle that out of the one only one arises is false. Or through a compound cause? But then the question can be repeated in the case of this cause, till one necessarily arrives at a point where the compound and the simple meet. For the First Principle is simple and the rest are compound, and this can only be imagined through their contact. But wherever this contact takes place, this principle, that out of the one only one proceeds, is false.
I say:
This
consequence, that everything which exists is simple, is a necessary consequence
for the philosophers, if they assume that the First Agent is like a simple agent
in the empirical world. But this consequence is binding only upon the man who
applies this principle universally to everything that exists. But the man who
divides existents into abstract existents and material, sensible existents,
makes the principles to which the sensible existent ascends different from the
principles to which the intelligible existent ascends, for he regards as the
principles of the sensible existents matter and form, and he makes some of these
existents the agents of others, till the heavenly body is reached, and he makes
the intelligible substances ascend to a first principle which is a principle to
them, in one way analogous to a formal cause, in another analogous to a final
cause, and in a third way analogous to an efficient cause. All this has been
proved in the works of the philosophers, and we state
this proposition here only in a general way. Therefore these difficulties
do not touch them. And this is the theory of Aristotle.’
About
this statement-that out of the one only one proceeds-all ancient philosophers
were agreed, when they investigated the first principle of the world in a
dialectical way (they mistook this investigation, however, for a real
demonstration), and they all came to the conclusion that the first principle is
one and the same for everything, and that from the one only one can proceed.
Those two principles having been established, they started to examine where
multiplicity comes from. For they had already come to the conclusion that the
older theory was untenable. This theory held that the first principles are two,
one for the good, one for the bad; for those older philosophers did not think
that the principles of the opposites could be one and the same; they believed
that the most general opposites which comprehend all opposites are the good and
the bad, and held therefore that the first principles must be two. When,
however, after a close examination, it was discovered that all things tend to
one end, and this end is the order which exists in the world, as it exists in an
army through its leader, and as it exists in cities through their government,
they came to the conclusion that the world must have one highest principle; and
this is the sense of the Holy Words ‘If there were in heaven and earth gods
beside God, both would surely have been corrupted’. They believed therefore,
because of the good which is present in everything, that evil occurs only in an
accidental way, like the punishments which good governors of cities ordain; for
they are evils instituted for the sake of the good, not by primary intention.
For there exist amongst good things some that can only exist with an admixture
of evil, for instance, in the being of man who is composed of a rational and an
animal soul. Divine Wisdom has ordained, according to these philosophers, that a
great quantity of the good should exist, although it had to be mixed with a
small quantity of evil, for the existence of much good with a little evil is
preferable to the non-existence of much good because of a little evidence.
Since
therefore these later philosophers were convinced that the first principle must
of necessity be one and unique, and this difficulty about the one occurred, they
gave three answers to this question. Some, like Anaxagoras and his school,
believe that plurality is only introduced through matter,’ some believe that
plurality is introduced through the instruments, and some believe that plurality
comes only through the mediators; and the first who assumed this was Plato. This
is the most convincing answer, for in the case of both the other solutions one
would have to ask again; from where does the plurality come in the matters and
in the instruments? But this difficulty touches anyone
who acknowledges that from the one only one can proceed: he has to
explain how plurality can derive from the one. Nowadays, however, the contrary
of this theory, namely, that out of the one all things proceed by one first
emanation, is generally accepted, and with our contemporaries we need discuss
only this latter statement.
The
objection which Ghazali raises against the
Peripatetics, that, if plurality were introduced through mediators, there could
only arise a plurality of qualitatively undifferentiated agglomerates which
could only form a quantitative plurality, does not touch them. For the
Peripatetics hold that there exists a twofold plurality, the plurality of simple
beings, those beings namely that do not exist in matter, and that some of these
are the causes of others and that they all ascend to one unique cause which is
of their own genus, and is the first being of their genus, and that the
plurality of the heavenly bodies only arises from the plurality of these
principles; and that the plurality of the sublunary world comes only from matter
and form and the heavenly bodies. So the Peripatetics are not touched by this
difficulty. The heavenly bodies are moved primarily through their movers, which
are absolutely immaterial, and the forms of these heavenly bodies are acquired
from these movers and the forms in the sublunary world are acquired from the
heavenly bodies and also from each other, indifferently, whether they are forms
of the elements which are in imperishable prime matters or forms of bodies
composed out of the elements, and, indeed, the composition in this sublunary
world arises out of the heavenly bodies. This is their theory of the order which
exists in the world. The reasons which led the philosophers to this theory
cannot be explained here, since they built it on many principles and
propositions, which are proved in many sciences and through many sciences in a
systematic way. But when the philosophers of our religion, like Farabi and
Avicenna, had once conceded to their opponents that the agent in the divine
world is like the agent in the empirical, and that from the one agent there can
arise but one object (and according to all the First was an absolutely simple
unity), it became difficult for them to explain how plurality could arise from
it. This difficulty compelled them finally to regard the First as different from
the mover of the daily circular movement; they declared that from the First, who
is a simple existent, the mover of the highest sphere proceeds, and from this
mover, since he is of a composite nature, as he is both conscious of himself and
conscious of the First, a duality, the highest sphere, and the mover of the
second sphere, the sphere under the highest can arise. This, however, is a
mistake,’ according to philosophical teaching, for thinker and thought are one
identical thing in human intellect and this is still more true in the case of
the abstract intellects. This does not affect Aristotle’s theory, for the
individual agent in the empirical world, from which there can only proceed one
single act, can only in an equivocal way be compared to the first agent. For the
first agent in the divine world is an absolute agent, while the agent in the
empirical world is a relative agent, and from the absolute agent only an
absolute act which has no special individual object can proceed. And thereby
Aristotle proves that the agent of the human intelligibles is an intellect free
from matter, since this agent thinks all things, and in the same way he proves
that the passive intellect is ingenerable and incorruptible,s because this
intellect also thinks all things.
According
to the system of Aristotle the answer on this point is that everything whose
existence is only effected through a conjunction of parts, like the conjunction
of matter and form, or the conjunction of the elements of the world, receives
its existence as a consequence of this conjunction. The bestower of this
conjunction is, therefore, the bestower of existence. And since everything
conjoined is only conjoined through a unity in it, and this unity through which
it is conjoined must depend on a unity, subsistent by itself, and be related to
it, there must exist a single unity, subsistent by itself, and this unity must
of necessity provide unity through its own essence. This unity is distributed in
the different classes of existing things, according to their natures, and from
this unity, allotted to the individual things, their existence arises; and all
those unities lead upwards to the First Monad, as warmth which exists in all the
individual warm things proceeds from primal warmth, which is fire, and leads
upwards to it? By means of this theory Aristotle connects sensible existence
with intelligible, saying that the world is one and proceeds from one, and that
this Monad is partly the cause of unity, partly the cause of plurality. And
since Aristotle was the first to find this solution, and because of its
difficulty, many of the later philosophers did not understand it, as we have
shown. It is evident, therefore, that there is a unique entity from which a
single power emanates through which all beings exist. And since they are many,
it is necessarily from the Monad, in so far as it is one, that plurality arises
or proceeds or whatever term is to be used. This is the sense of Aristotle’s
theory, a sense very different from that in which those thinkers believe who
affirm that from the one only one can proceed. See therefore how serious this
error proved among the philosophers! You should, therefore, see for youself in
the books of the ancients whether these philosophical theories are proved, not
in the works of Avicenna and others who changed the philosophical doctrine in
its treatment of metaphysics so much that it became mere guessing.
Ghazali
says, on behalf of the philosophers:
It may be said: If the philosophical theory is properly understood, the difficulties disappear. Existents can be divided into what exists in a substratum, like accidents and forms, and what does not exist in a substratum. The latter can be divided again into what serves as a substratum for other things, e.g. bodies, and what does not exist in a substratum, e.g. substances which subsist by themselves. These latter again are divided into those which exert an influence on bodies and which we call souls, and those which exert an influence not on bodies but on souls, and which we call abstract intellects. Existents which inhere in a substratum, like accidents, are temporal and have temporal causes which terminate in a principle, in one way temporal, in another way everlasting, namely, circular movement. But we are not discussing this here. Here we are discussing only those principles which exist by themselves and do not inhere in a substratum, which are of three kinds: (i) bodies, which are the lowest type, (ii) abstract intellects, which are not attached to bodies, either by way of action or by being impressed upon them, which are the highest type, and (iii) souls, which are the intermediate agencies, attached to the bodies in a certain way, namely, through their influence and their action upon them, and which stand midway in dignity; they undergo an influence from the intellects and exert an influence upon the bodies.
Now the number of bodies is ten. There are nine heavens, and the tenth body is the matter which fills the concavity of the sphere of the moon. The nine heavens are animated; they possess bodies and souls, and they have an order in existence which we shall mention here. From the existence of the First Principle there emanates the first intellect-an existent which subsists by itself, immaterial, not impressed on body, conscious of its principle and which we philosophers call First Intellect, but which (for we do not quibble about words) may be called angel, or intellect, or what you will. From its existence there derive three things, an intellect, the soul, and the body of the farthest sphere, i.e. the ninth heaven. Then from the second intellect there derive a third intellect and the soul and the body of the sphere of the fixed stars, then from the third intellect there derive a fourth intellect and the soul and the body of the sphere of Saturn, then from the fourth intellect there derive a fifth intellect and the soul and the body of the sphere of Jupiter, and so on till one arrives at the intellect from which there derive the intellect, the soul and the body of the sphere of the moon, and this last intellect is that which is called the active intellect. Then there follows that which fills the sphere of the moon, namely, the matter which receives generation and corruption from the active intellect and from the natures of the spheres. Then through the action of the movements of the spheres and the stars the matters are mixed in different mixtures from which the minerals, vegetables, and animals arise. It is not necessary that from each intellect another intellect should derive endlessly, for these intellects are of a different kind, and what is valid for the one is not valid for the other. It follows from this that the intellects after the First Principle are ten in number and that there are nine spheres, and the sum of these noble principles after the First Principle is therefore nineteen; and that under each of the primary intellects there are three things, another intellect and a soul and body of a sphere. Therefore there must be in each intellect a triple character, and in the first effect a plurality can only be imagined in this way: (i) it is conscious of its principle, (ii) it is conscious of itself, (iii) it is in itself possible, since the necessity of its existence derives from another. These are three conditions, and the most noble of these three effects must be related to the most noble of these conditions. Therefore the intellect proceeds from the first effect; in so far as the first effect is conscious of its principle; the soul of the sphere proceeds from the first effect, in so far as the first effect is conscious of itself; and the body of the sphere proceeds from the first effect, in so far as by itself the first effect belongs to possible existence. We must still explain why this triple character is found in the first effect, although its principle is only one. We say that from the First Principle only one thing proceeds, namely, the essence of this intellect through which it is conscious of itself. The effect, however, must by itself become conscious of its principle, and this kind of consciousness cannot derive from its cause. Also the effect by itself belongs to possible existence, and i cannot receive this possibility from the First Principle, but possesses it in its own essence. We do indeed regard it as possible that one effect should proceed from the one, although this effect possesses by itself and not through its principle certain necessary qualities, either relative or nonrelative. In this way a plurality arises, and so it becomes the principle of the existence of plurality. Thus the composite can meet the simple, as their meeting must needs take place and cannot take place in any other g manner, and this is the right and reasonable explanation, and it is in this way that this philosophical theory must be understood.
I
say:
All
these are inventions fabricated against the philosophers by Avicenna, Farabi,
and others. But the true theory of the ancient philosophers is that there are
principles which are the celestial bodies, and that the principles of the
celestial bodies, which are immaterial existents, are the movers of those
celestial bodies, and that the celestial bodies move towards them in obedience
to them and out of love for them, to comply with their order to move and to
understand them, and that they are only created with a view to movement. For
when it was found that the principles which move the celestial bodies are
immaterial and incorporeal, there was no way left to them in which they might
move the bodies other than by ordering them to move. And from this the
philosophers concluded that the celestial bodies are rational animals, conscious
of themselves and of their principles, which move them by command. And since it
was established-in the De Anima-that
there is no difference between knowledge and the object of knowledge, except for the latter’s being
in matter, of necessity the
substance of immaterial beings-if there are such -had to be knowledge or
intellect or whatever you wish to call it. And the philosophers knew that these
principles must be immaterial, because they confer on the celestial bodies everlasting
movement in which there is no fatigue or weariness,’ and that anything
which bestows such an everlasting movement must be immaterial, and cannot be a
material power. And indeed the celestial body acquires its permanence only
through these immaterial principles. And the philosophers understood that the
existence of these immaterial principles must be connected with a first
principle amongst them; if not, there could be no order in the world. You can
find these theories in the books of the philosophers and, if you want to make
sure of the truth in these matters, you will have to consult them. It also
becomes clear from the fact that all the spheres have the daily circular
movement, although besides this movement they have, as the philosophers had
ascertained, their own special movements, that He who commands this movement
must be the First Principle, i.e. God, and that He commands the other principles
to order the other movements to the other spheres. Through this heaven and earth
are ruled as a state is ruled by the commands of the supreme monarch, which,
however, are transmitted to all classes of the population by the men he has
appointed for this purpose in the different affairs of the state. As it says in
the Qur’an: ‘And He inspired every Heaven with its bidding.
This heavenly injunction and this obedience are the prototypes of the
injunction and obedience imposed on man because he is a rational animal. What
Avicenna says of the derivation of these principles from each other is a theory
not known amongst the ancients, who merely state that these principles hold
certain positions in relation to the First Principle, and that their existence
is only made real through this relation to the First Principle. As is said in
the Qur’an: ‘There is none amongst us but has his appointed place. It is the
connexion which exists between them which brings it about that some are the
effect of others and that they all depend on the First Principle. By ‘agent’
and ‘object’, ‘creator’ and ‘creature’, in so far as it concerns
this existence nothing more can be understood than just this idea of connexion.
But what we said of this connexion of every existent with the One is something
different from what is meant by ‘agent’ and ‘object’, ‘maker’ and
‘product’ in this sublunary world. If you imagine a ruler who has many men
under his command who again have others under their command, and if you imagine
that those commanded receive their existence only through receiving this command
and through their obedience to this command, and those who are under those
commanded can only exist through those commanded, of necessity the first ruler
will be the one who bestows on all existents the characteristic through which
they become existent, and that which exists through its being commanded will
only exist because of the first ruler. And the philosophers understood that this
is what is meant by the divine laws when they speak of creation, of calling into
existence out of nothing, and of command. This is tire best way to teach people
to understand the philosophical doctrine without tile ignominy attaching to it,
which seems to attach when you listen to the analysis Ghazali
gives of it here. Tire philosophers assert that all this is proved in their
books, and the man who, (raving fulfilled the conditions they impose,’ is able
to study their works will find the truth of what they say---or perhaps its
opposite--and will not understand Aristotle’s theory or Plato’s in any other
sense than that here indicated. And their philosophy is tire highest point human
intelligence can reach. It may be that, Nvlrerr it man discover, these
explanations of philosophical theory, lie will find that they happen not only to
be true but to be generally acknowledged, and teachings which are f;errerally
acceptable are pleasing and delightful to all.
One
of the premisses from which this explanation is deduced is that when one
observes this sublunary world, one finds that what is called ‘living’ and
‘knowing’ moves on its own account in welldefined movements towards
well-defined ends and well-defined acts from which new well-defined acts arise.
For this reason the theologians say that any act can only proceed from a living,
knowing being. When one has found this first premiss, that what moves in
welldefined movements from which arise well-defined and ordered actions is
living and knowing, and one joins to this a second premiss which can be verified
by the senses, that the heavens move on their own account in well-defined
movements from which there follow in the existents under them well-defined acts,
order, and rank through which these existents under them receive their
subsistence, one deduces from this, no doubt, a third principle, namely, that
the heavenly bodies are living beings endowed with perception. That from their
movements there follow well-defined acts from which this sublunary world, its
animals, vegetables, and minerals receive their subsistence and conservation ,
is evident from observation, for, were it not that the sun in its ecliptic
approaches the sublunary world and recedes from it, there would not be the four
seasons, and without tile four seasons there would be no plants and no animals,
and the orderly origination of elements out of each other necessary for the
conservation of their existence would not take place. For instance, when the sun
recedes towards tile south the air in the north becomes cold and rains occur and
tire production of the watery element increases, whereas in tile south tile
production of the airy element becomes greater; whereas in summer, when the sun
approaches our zenith, the opposite takes place. Those actions which the sun
exercises everlastingly through its varying distance from the different
existents which always occupy one and the same place are also found in the moon
and all the stars which have oblique spheres, and they produce tile four seasons
through their circular movements, and the most important of all these movements,
in its necessity for tire existence and conservation of the creation, is tire
highest circular movement which produces day and night. The Venerable Book
refers in several verses to the providential care for man which arises out of
God’s subjection of all tile heavens to His bidding, as, for instance, in tile
Qur’anic verse ‘And the sun and the moon and the stars are subjected to His
bidding’, and wlrcn man observes these acts and this guidance which proceed
necessarily and permanently from tire movcnrcnts of tile stars, and sees how
these stars move in fixed movements, and drat they have well-defined shapes and
move in well-defined directions towards well-defined actions in opposite
motions, he understands that these well-defined acts can only arise from beings
perceptive, living, capable of choice and of willing.
And
he becomes still more convinced of this when he sees that many beings in this
world which have small, despicable, miserable, and insignificant bodies are not
wholly devoid of life, notwithstanding the smallness of’ their size, the
feebleness of their powers, the shortness of their lives, the insignificance of
their bodies; and that divine munificence has bestowed on them life and
perception, through which they direct themselves and conserve their existence.
And he knows with absolute certainty that the heavenly bodies are better fitted
to possess life and perception than the bodies of this sublunary world, because
of the size of their bodies, the magnificence of their existence, and the
multitude of their lights,’ as it says in the Divine Words: ‘Surely the
creation of the heavens and the earth is greater than the creation of man, but
most men know it not. But especially when he notices how they direct the living
beings of this sublunary world, does he understand with absolute certainty that
they are alive, for the living can only be guided by a being leading a more
perfect life. And when man observes these noble, living, rational bodies,
capable of choice, which surround us, and recognizes a third principle, namely,
that they do not need for their own existence the providence with which they
guide the sublunary world, he becomes aware that they are commanded to perform
these movements and to control the animals, vegetables, and minerals of this
sublunary world, and that He who commands them is not one of them and that He is
necessarily incorporeal (for, if not, He would be one of them) and that all
these heavenly bodies control the existents which are under them, but serve Him,
who for His existence is in no need of them. And were it not for this Commander,
they would not give their care everlastingly and continuously to this sublunary
world which they guide willingly, without any advantage to themselves,
especially in this act. They move thus
by way of command and obligation the heavens which repair to them, only in order
to conserve this sublunary world and to uphold its existence. And the Commander
is God (glory be to Him), and all this is the meaning of the Divine Words ‘We
come willingly’.
And
another proof of all this is that, if a man sees a great many people,
distinguished and meritorious, applying themselves to definite acts without a
moment’s interruption, although these acts are not necessary for their own
existence and they do not need them, it is absolutely evident to him that these
acts have been prescribed and ordered to them and that they have a leader who
has obliged them in his everlasting service to act continually for the good of
others. This leader is the highest among them in power and rank and they are, as
it were, his submissive slaves. And this is the meaning to which the Venerable
Book refers in the words: ‘Thus did we show Abraham the kingdom of heaven. and
the earth that he should be of those who are safe. ‘ And when man observes
still another thing, namely, that all the seven planets in their own special
movements are subservient to their universal daily motion and that their own
bodies as parts of the whole are submissive to the universal body, as if they
were all one in fulfilling this service, he knows again with absolute certainty
that each planet has its own commanding principle, supervising it as a deputy of
the first Commander. Just as, in the organization of armies, l where each body
of troops has one commander, called a centurion, each centurion is subordinate
to the one Commander-in-chief of the army, so also in regard to the movements of
the heavenly bodies which the ancients observed. They number somewhat more than
forty, of which seven or eight’-for the ancients disagreed about this
-dominate the others and themselves depend on the first Commander, praise
be to Him! Man acquires this knowledge in this way, whether or not lie knows how
the principle of the creation of these heavenly bodies acts, or what the
connexion is between the existence of these commanders and the first Commander.
In any case lie does not doubt that, if these heavenly bodies existed by
themselves, that is, if they were eternal and had no cause, they might refuse to
serve their own commanders or might not obey them, and the commanders might
refuse to obey the first Commander. But, since it is not possible for them to
behave in this way, the relation between them and the first Commander is
determined by absolute obedience, and this means nothing more than that they
possess this obedience in the essence of their being, not accidentally, as is
the case in the relation between master and servant. Servitude, therefore, is
not something additional to their essence, but these essences subsist through
servitude and this is the meaning of the Divine Words: ‘There is none in the
heavens or the earth but comes to the Merciful as a servant. And their
possession is the kingdom of the heavens and the earth which God showed to
Abraham, as it is expressed in the Devine Words: ‘Thus did we show Abraham the
kingdom of heaven and earth that he should be of those who are safe. Therefore
you will understand that the creation of these bodies and the principle of their
becoming cannot be like the coming to be of the bodies of this sublunary world,
and that the human intellect is too weak to understand how this act works,
although it knows that this act exists. He who tries to compare heavenly with
earthly existence, and believes that the Agent of the divine world acts in the
way in which an agent in this sublunary world works, is utterly thoughtless,
profoundly mistaken, and in complete error.
This
is the extreme limit we can reach in our understanding of the theories of the
ancients about the heavenly bodies, of their proof for the existence of a
Creator for these bodies who is immaterial, and of their statements concerning
the immaterial existents under Him, one of which is the soul. But to believe in
His existence as if He were the cause through which these bodies had been
produced in time, in the way we see the production of the bodies of this
sublunary world, as the theologians desired-this, indeed, is very difficult, and
the premisses they use for its proof do not lead them where they desire. We
shall show this later, when we discuss the different proofs for the existence of
God.
And
since this has been firmly established, we shall now go back to relate and
refute in detail what Ghazali tells of the
philosophers, and to show the degree of truth reached by his assertions, for
this is the primary intention of this book.
Ghazali says, refuting the
philosophers:
What you affirm are only suppositions and in fact you do nothing but add obscurities to obscurities. If a man were to say that he had seen such things in a dream, it would be a proof of his bad constitution, or if one should advance such arguments in juridical controversies, in which everything under discussion is conjectural, one would say these were stupidities which could not command any assent.
I say:
This
is very much the way the ignorant treat the learned and the vulgar the eminent,
and in this way, too, the common people behave towards the products of
craftsmanship. For, when the artisans show the common people the products of
their craftsmanship which possess many qualities from which they draw wonderful
actions, the masses scoff at them
and regard them as insane, whereas in reality they themselves are insane and
ignorant in comparison with the wise. With such utterances as these the learned
and the thoughtful need not occupy themselves. What Ghazali
ought to have done, since he relates these theories, is to show the motives
which led to them, so that the reader might compare them with the arguments
through which he wants to refute them.
Ghazali
says:
The ways of refuting such theories are countless, but we shall bring here a certain number. The first is that we say: You claim that one of the meanings of plurality in the first effect is that it is possible in its existence, but we ask whether its being possible in its existence is identical with its being or something different? If you say ‘identical’, then no plurality proceeds from it, but if you say that it is different, why then do you not assert that there is a plurality in the First Principle, for it not only has existence, but is necessary in its existence, and existence and necessary existence are not identical. Therefore, because of this plurality in the First Principle, let us allow that different entities proceed from it. If it is said: ‘Necessity of existence cannot mean anything but existence’, we answer: ‘Possibility of existence cannot mean anything but existence. If, however, you say: ‘Its existence can be known without its possibility being known, and therefore they are different,’ we answer: ‘In the same way the existence of the necessary existent can be known without its necessity being known, unless another proof is added,’ let them therefore be different! Generally speaking, existence is a universal which can be divided into necessary and possible, and if the one specific difference is an addition to the universal, the other specific difference is also an addition, for both cases are the same. If you say, ‘It possesses the possibility of its existence through itself and its existence through another, how then can what it possesses through itself and what it possesses through another be identical?’ we answer: ‘How then can the necessity of its being be identical with its being, so that the necessity of its existence can be denied and its existence affirmed? And to God, the One, the Absolute Truth, negation and affirmation cannot be applied equivocally, for one cannot say of Him that He is and is not, or that His existence is at the same time necessary or not necessary; but it can be said of Him that He exists, but that His existence is not necessary, as it can be said of Him that He exists, but that His existence is not possible. And it is through this that His Unity can be recognized. But this unity in the First cannot be upheld, if what you say is true, that possibility of existence is something different from the possible existent.
I say:
Ghazali affirms that, when we say of a
thing that it is possible in its existence, this must either mean that it is
identical with its existence or different from it, i.e. something additional to
its existence. If it is identical, there is no plurality, and the statement of
the philosophers that there is a plurality in the possible existent has no
sense. If, however, it is not identical, the philosophers will have to make the
same admission about the necessary existent, i.e. that there is a plurality in
it, but this is in contradiction to their own principle. This reasoning,
however, is not valid, for Ghazali has
overlooked a third case, namely, that necessity of being might be not something
added to existence outside the soul but a condition’ in the necessary existent
which adds nothing to its essence; it might be said to refer to the denial of
its being the effect of something else, a denial of that which is affirmed of
all other entities, just as, when we say of something that it is one, nothing
additional to its essence existing outside the soul is meant-as is, on the
contrary, the case when we speak of a white existent-but only a negative
condition, namely, indivisibility. In the same way, when we speak of the
necessary existent, we mean by the necessity of His existence a negative
condition which is the consequence of His existence, namely, that His existence
is necessary through Himself, not through something else. And also when we speak
of the existent which is possible through itself, it is not something additional
to its essence outside the soul-as is the case with the real possible-that
should be understood, but merely that its essence determines that its existence
can become necessary only through a cause; what is meant, therefore, is an
essence which will not be by itself necessary in its existence when its cause is
removed and therefore is not a necessary existent, i.e. it is denied the quality
of necessary existence. It is as if Ghazali said
that the necessary existent is partially necessary through itself, partially
through a cause, and that which is necessary through a cause is not necessary
through itselfb Nobody doubts that these specific differences are neither
substantial differences which divide the essence nor additions to the essence,
but that they are only negative or relative relations, just as, when we say that
a thing exists, the word ‘exists’ does not indicate an entity added to its
essence outside the soul, which is the case when we say of a thing that it is
white. It is here that Avicenna erred, for he believed that unity is an addition
to the essence and also that existence, when we say that a thing exists, is an
addition to the things This question will be treated later. And the first to
develop this theory of the existent, possible by itself and necessary through
another, was Avicenna; for him possibility was a quality in a thing, different
from the thing in which the possibility is, and from this it seems to follow
that what is under the First is composed of two things, one to which possibility
is attributed, the other to which necessity is attributed; but this is a
mistaken theory. But he who has understood our explanation will not be concerned
about the difficulty which Ghazali adduces
against Avicenna. The only question he will have to ask, when he has understood
the meaning of ‘possibility of existence’ for the first effect, is whether
this possibility brings about a compound character in the first effect or not,
for if the quality is relative, it does not bring about a compound character.
For not all the different dispositions which can be imagined in a thing need
determine additional qualities in its essence outside the soul; indeed, this is
the case with the disposition of privations and relations, and for this reason
certain philosophers do not count the category of relation among things which
exist outside the soul, i.e. the ten categories. Ghazali,
however, implies in his argument that any additional meaning must apply to an
additional entity actually outside the soul; but this is a mistake, and a
sophistical argument. This follows from his words
Generally
speaking, existence is a universal which can be divided into necessary and
possible, and if the one specific difference is an addition to the universal,
the other specific difference also is an addition, for both cases are the same.
But
the division of existence into possible and necessary is not like the division
of animal into rational and irrational, or into walking, swimming, and flying
animals, for those things are additional to the genus and provide additional
species-animality is their common concept and they are specific differences
added to it. But the possible into which Avicenna divides existence is not an
entity actually outside the soul, and his theory is wrong, as we said before.
For the existence which for its existence is in need of a cause can, as an
entity by itself, only be understood as non-existence-that is to say, anything
that exists through another thing must be non-existent by itself, unless its
nature is the nature of the true possible. Therefore the division of existence
into necessary and possible existence is not a valid one, if one does not mean
by ‘possible’ the true possible; but we will treat of this later. The
summary of what we said here is that the existent can be divided either into
essential differences or into relative conditions or into accidents additional
to its essence; out of the division into essential differences there must
necessarily result a plurality of acts which arise out of the existent, but out
of the division into relational and accidental dispositions no such plurality of
different acts results. And if it should be claimed that out of relational
qualities a plurality of acts results, well then, a plurality will proceed from
the First Principle of necessity without need of the intervention of an effect
as the principle of plurality; on the other hand, if it should be claimed that
out of relational qualities no plurality of acts results, well then, out of the
relational qualities of the first effect also there will result no plurality of
acts, and this latter assumption is the better.’
Ghazali
says:
How then can what it possesses through itself, and what it possesses through another, be identical?
But
how can this same man who affirms that possibility exists only in the mind, say
such a thing? Why then does he not apply this doctrine here, for it is not
impossible for the one essence to be positive and negative in its relations
without there resulting a plurality in this essence-which, however, Ghazali
denies. But if you have understood this, you will be able to solve the problem Ghazali
poses in this section.
If
it is said: ‘It follows from this that there is no composition, either in
existence, necessary by itself, or in existence, necessary through another,’
we answer: As to what is necessary through another, the mind perceives in it a
composition through cause and effect; if it is a body , there must be in it both
a unity actually, and a plurality potentially; if it is, however, incorporeal,
the mind does not perceive a plurality either in act or in potency . For this
reason the philosophers call this kind of existent simple, but they regard the
cause as more simple than the effect and they hold that the First is the most
simple of them all, because it cannot be understood as having any cause or
effect at all. But composition can be understood of the principles which come
after the First; therefore, according to the philosophers, the second principle
is more simple than the third, and it is in this way that their theory must be
understood. The meaning of ‘cause’ and ‘effect’ in these existents is
that a potential plurality (as it were) exists in them which shows itself in the
effect, i.e. there proceeds out of it a plurality of effects which it never
contains actually in any definite moments If the hearer has understood their
theory in this way and accepted it, he will see that they are not affected by
the objections of Ghazali. But one should not
understand this theory in the way Ghazali does,
namely, that out of the second principle, because it knows its own essence and
knows its principle, and therefore possesses two forms or a dual existence,
there proceed two different things, for this is a false theory. For this would
mean that this second principle is composed of more than one form and that
therefore this form’ is one in its substratum, many by its definition, as is
the case with the soul. But the theologians keep tenaciously to this false
explanation in their statements about the derivation of these principles from
each other, as if they wanted to understand the divine through an analogy with
perceptible acts; indeed, when metaphysics contains such theories, it becomes
more conjectural than jurisprudence. You will have seen from this that the
conclusion Ghazali wants the philosophers to
draw concerning the plurality in the necessary existent, because of the
plurality which he considers must exist in the possible existent, has no
validity. For, if possibility were understood as real possibility, it would
indeed imply here a plurality, but since this is impossible, according to what
we have said and shall show later, nothing similar follows concerning the
necessary existent. But if possibility is understood as being a concept of the
mind, it follows that neither the necessary existent nor the possible existent
must be regarded as composite for this reason; the only reason why composition
must be admitted here is because of the relation of cause ; and effect.
Ghazali
says:
The second objection is that we say: ‘Is the knowledge the first effect has of its principle identical with its own existence and with the knowledge it has of itself?’ If so, there is only a plurality in the expression used to describe the essence, not in the essence itself; if not, this plurality will exist also in the First, for He knows Himself and He knows others.
I say:
What
is true is that the knowledge the first effect has of its principle is identical
with its own essence and that the first effect belongs to the domain of relation
and is therefore of a lesser rank than the First who belongs to the domain of
what exists by itself. It is true, according to the philosophers, that the First
thinks only His own essencenot something relative, namely, that He is a
principle-but His essence, according to the philosophers, contains all intellects,
nay, all existents, in a nobler
and more perfect way than they all
possess in reality, as we shall explain later. Therefore
this theory does not imply the abominable consequences he ascribes to it.
Ghazali says:
It may be said by the philosophers that His knowing Himself is identical with His essence, and that he who does not know that he is a principle for others does not know his own essence, for knowledge conforms to the thing known and refers therefore to His essence.
I
say:
This
statement is wrong, for His being a principle is something relative and cannot
be identical with His essence. If He could think that He is a principle, He
would be conscious of the things the principle of which He is, in the way these
things really exist, and in this case the higher would be perfected through the
lower, for the thing known is the perfection of the knower according to the
philosophers, as is set forth in the sciences about the human intellect.’
Ghazali
says:
But we answer: In this case the knowledge the effect has of itself is identical with its essence, for it thinks with its substance and knows itself, and intellect and knower and thing known are all one. Therefore, if its knowing itself is identical with its essence, well then, let it think itself as the effect of a cause, for this it really is. But the intellect conforms to the thing known; therefore all this refers solely to its essence and so there is no plurality. If, indeed, there is a plurality, it must exist in the First. Therefore, let differentiation proceed from the First.
I
say:
What
he says here of the philosophers, about the exclusive existence of a plurality
in the principles under the First Principle, is wrong and does not follow from
their principles. There is, according to them, no plurality in these intellects,
and they do not distinguish themselves by simplicity and plurality, but only by
being cause and effect. And the difference between the knowledge of the First
Principle, as knowing itself, and the knowledge of the other principles, as
knowing themselves, is that the First Principle thinks itself as existing by
itself, not as being related to a cause, whereas the other intellects think
themselves as related to their cause and in this way plurality is introduced
into them. They need not all have the same degree of simplicity, since they are
not of the same rank in relation to the First Principle and none of them is
simple in the sense in which the First Principle is simple, because the First
Principle is regarded as an existence by itself whereas they are in related
existence.
And as to Ghazali’s
words:
Therefore, if its knowing itself is identical with its essence, well then, let it think itself as the effect of a cause, for this it really is. But the intellect conforms to the thing known, and therefore all this refers solely to its essence and so there is no plurality. If, indeed, there is a plurality, it must exist in the First Principle.
I
say:
It
does not follow from the fact that intellect and the thing known are identical
in the separate intellects that they are all similar in simplicity, for in this,
according to the philosophers, some are superior to others in a greater or
lesser degree; absolute simplicity is only found in the First Intellect, and the
reason is that the essence of the First Intellect is subsistent by itself, and
the other intellects, when they think themselves, are conscious that they
subsist by it; if intellect and the intelligible were in each of them of the
same degree of unity as in the First Principle, either the essence existing by
reason of itself and the essence existing by reason of another would be
congruous, or intellect would not conform to the nature of the intelligible
thing;’ which is impossible, according to the philosophers. All these
arguments and their answers, as set forth by Ghazali,
are dialectical and the only man who can-notwithstanding the deficiency of the
human understanding concerning these questions-give a demonstrative argument
about them is the man who knows (to begin with) what the intellect is, and the
only man who knows what the intellect is is the man who knows what the soul is,
and the only man who knows what the soul is is the man who knows what a living
being is. There is no sense in discussing these matters in a superficial way and
according to the common notions, which do not contain specific knowledge and are
not properly related to the problem. To discuss these questions, before knowing
what the intellect is, is nothing more than babbling. The Ash’arites,
therefore, when they relate the philosophical doctrines, make them extremely
hateful and something very different from even the first speculation of man
about what exists.
Ghazali says:
Let us therefore drop the claim of its absolute unity, if this unity is annulled through plurality of this kind.
I say:
Ghazali means that, when the
philosophers assume that the First thinks its own essence and knows through this
that it is the cause of others, they must conclude that it is not absolutely
one. For it has not yet been proved that God must be absolutely one. This is the
theory of some Peripatetics who interpreted it as the theory of Aristotle
himself.
Ghazali says:
If it is said that the First knows only its own essence, and the knowledge of its own essence is identical with its essence, for intelligence, thinker, and intelligible are all one and it does not know anything but itself-this can be refuted in two ways. First, because of its worthlessness this theory was abandoned by Avicenna and other philosophers of repute, who affirm that the First knows itself as the principle of what emanates from it and knows all other existents in their species by a universal thought, and not individually. For they repudiate the theory that there emanates out of the First Principle, which does not know what emanates from it, only one intellect; that its effect is an intellect from which there emanates an intellect and the soul and the body of a sphere, and that this intellect knows itself and its three effects, whereas its cause and principle knows only itself. For according to this theory the effect is superior to the cause, since from the cause only one thing emanates, whereas from the effect three things emanate; moreover, the First Principle knows only itself, but the effect knows its principle and effects besides itself. Who can be satisfied with the idea that such words can apply to the status of God, for indeed they make Him lower than any of His creatures, who know themselves and know Him, and he who knows Him and knows himself is of a nobler rank than He is, since He knows none but Himself. Their profound thoughts about God’s glory end therefore in a denial of everything that is understood by His greatness, and assimilate the state of God to that of a dead body which has no notion of what happens in the world, with the sole exception that God possesses self-knowledge. So does God deal with those who turn aside from His way and deviate from the path of His guidance, denying His words: ‘I did not make them witnesses of the creation of the heavens and the earth nor of the creation of themselves, ‘ who think wicked thoughts about God, who believe that the powers of man suffice to reach the essence of the divine, who, deceived in their minds, believe that the human understanding is competent to free itself from the authority of the prophets and from obedience to them. For no doubt they are now forced to acknowledge that the quintessence of their thought is reduced to absurdities which would make one wonder if they were told in a dream.
I
say:
One
who wants to enter deeply into these speculations must know that much of what is
firmly established in the speculative sciences seems at first sight, and
compared to the opinions the common man holds about them, like the visions of a
dreamer, as Ghazali truly says; many of these
truths are deduced from a different kind of premisses from that which satisfies
the masses; indeed there is no other way for anyone to become convinced of their
truth than that of comprehending them by logical proof and evidence. If, for
example, the common man, and even he who has reached a somewhat higher degree of
culture, is told that the sun, which appears to the eye as being the size of a
foot, is about a hundred and seventy times bigger than the earth, he will say
that it is absurd, and will regard him who believes it as a dreamer; and it is
difficult for us to convince him through propositions which he can easily
understand and acknowledge in a short time. The only way, indeed, to attain such
knowledge is through deductive proof-that is, for the man who is amenable to
proof. If it is the case even with geometrical questions and mathematical
problems in general, that, when a solution is explained to the common man, it
will appear to him fallacious and open to criticism at first sight and to have
the character of a dream, how much more this will be the case in the
metaphysical sciences, since for this kind of knowledge there are no plausible
premisses which satisfy the superficial understanding, by which I mean the
understanding of the masses. One might say that the final knowledge the
understanding can reach will seem to the common man at first sight something
absurd. And this happens not only in the theoretical sciences but in the
practical sciences as well. Therefore, the assumption that one of the sciences
should vanish and then come into existence again, at first sight would seem to
be impossible. For this reason many have thought that those sciences are of
supernatural origin and some attribute them to the Jinn, others to the prophets,
so that Ibn Hazm goes so far as to affirm that the strongest proof of the
existence of prophecy is the existence of these sciences. Therefore, if a lover
of truth finds a theory reprehensible and does not find plausible premisses
which remove its reprehensible character, he must not at once believe that the
theory is false, but must inquire how he who puts it forward has arrived at it,
must employ much time in learning this, and follow the systematic order
corresponding to the nature of the topic. And if this is necessary in other
sciences than metaphysics, how much more will this hold for metaphysics, since
that science is so remote from the sciences built on common sense. Thus it
should be learned that in metaphysics rhetorical reasoning cannot be applied, as
it may be applied in other questions; for dialectics is useful and permissible
in the other sciences but forbidden in this. For this reason most students of
this science seek refuge in the theory that metaphysics is wholly concerned with
the qualification of the substance which the human mind cannot qualify, for if
it could do so, the eternal and the transitory would be on the same level. If
this is so, may God judge him who discusses these questions with common opinions
and who argues about God without scientific knowledge. So it is often thought
that the philosophers are extremely inefficient in this science, and for this
reason Ghazali says that metaphysics is only
conjectural.
But
in any case we shall try to show
some plausible premisses and true propositions-and we try this only because Ghazali
gave such a false representation of this noble science and denied people the
possibility of attaining happiness through excellent acts, and God is the
inquirer and the reckoner-in order to set out the motives which moved the
philosophers to believe these theories about the First Principle and other
existents, the limit which the human understanding can reach in this matter, and
the doubts which beset these problems; and we shall show all this also in
respect to the Muslim theologians and indicate how far their wisdom attained. We
hope through this to help the lover of knowledge to find the truth, and to urge
him to study the sciences of both parties, hoping also that God may assist him
in all this!
We
say:
The philosophers tried to acquire knowledge about reality through
speculation alone, without relying on the words of anyone who should induce them
to acquiesce in them without proof; on the contrary, sometimes through
speculation they came into contradiction with the facts as shown by the senses.
They discovered that the sublunary world can be divided into two classes, the
living and the inanimate, any instance of which only comes into being through
something, called form, which is the entity by which it comes into being after
having been non-existent; through something, called matter, out of which it
comes into being; through something, called the agent, from which it comes into
being; and through something, called the end, for the sake of which it comes
into being; and so they established that there are four causes. And they found
that the form by which a thing comes into being, i.e. the form of the thing
generated, is identical with the proximate agent, from which it comes into
being, either in species, like the generation of man out of man, or in genus,
like the generation of the mule from a horse and a donkey. And since, according
to them, the causes do not form an infinite series, they introduced a primary,
permanent efficient cause. Some of them believed that the heavenly bodies are
this efficient cause, some that it is an abstract principle, connected with the
heavenly bodies, some that it is the First Principle, some again that it is a
principle inferior to it,’ and these philosophers thought it sufficient to
regard the heavens and the principles of the heavenly bodies
as the cause for the coming into being of the elements, since according
to them they too need an efficient cause. As to the generation of living beings
from each other in the sublunary world, the philosophers had, because of this
faculty of life, to introduce another principle, which was the bestower of soul
and of form, and of the wisdom which is manifested in this world. This is what
Galen calls the formative faculty’ and some regard it as an abstract
principle, some as an intellect, some as a soul,’ some as the body of the
heavens, and some as the First. Galen called this potency the demiurge and was
in doubt whether it is God or another principle. This faculty acts in the
generative animals and in plants, and is needed still more in those plants and
animals which have an equivocal generation. This was the point they reached in
the examination of the sublunary world.
When
they had agreed that the heavens were the principles of the perceptible bodies,
they investigated the heavens also and agreed that the heavenly bodies are the
principles of the changeable perceptible bodies and of the species in the
sublunary world, either by themselves or in combination with an abstract
principle. And from their investigation of the heavenly bodies it appeared to
them that these do not come into being in the way that the transitory things of
the sublunary world come into being, for what comes into being, in so far as it
comes into being, is seen to be a part of this perceptible world and its coming
into being is only effected in so far as it is a part of it, for what has come
into being has come into being out of something, through the act of something,
by means of something, in time and in space. And they discovered that the
celestial bodies are, as remote efficient causes, a condition for the coming
into being of perceptible things. If, however, the celestial bodies themselves
had come into being in this way, they would, as a condition of their becoming,
have required prior to them other bodies which would have needed to be parts of
another world, and there would be in this other world bodies like these, and if
these bodies had also come into being, they would have required other celestial
bodies before, and so ad infinitum. And since this was established in this way
and many others, they were convinced that the heavenly bodies neither come into
being nor are destroyed in the way that sublunary things come into being and are
destroyed, for ‘coming into being’ has no other definition or description or
explanation or meaning than that which we have laid down here. Then they found
that the celestial bodies have also moving principles by means of which and by
the agency of which they are moved. And when they investigated their principles,
they found that the moving principles were neither bodies nor potencies in
bodies. They are not bodies because they are the first principles of the bodies
encircling the world; they are not potencies in bodies, i.e. their bodies are
not a condition for their existence (as is the case in this sublunary world with
the composite principles in animals), because any potency in a body is,
according to the philosophers, finite, since it can be divided through the
division of the body’ and every body which can be divided is generable and
corruptible, i.e. composed of matter and form, and the existence of its matter
is a condition for the existence of its form. And again, if the
principles of heavenly bodies were like the principles of earthly bodies, the
former would be like the latter and would need other bodies prior to them. Thus
they were convinced of the existence of incorporeal principles which are not
potencies in a body.
Moreover,
they had already found, concerning the human intellect, that form has two modes
of existence, a sensible existence in matter, as in the stone there is the form
of the inorganic which exists in the matter outside the soul, and an
intelligible existence, namely, perception and intellect, which is separate from
matter and exists in the sou. From this they concluded that these absolutely
abstract existences are pure intellects, for if what
is separated from another is already intellect, how much better suited to
be intellect will something be that is absolutely separates And so, of
necessity, they deduced that the objects of thought of those intellects are the
forms of the existents and of the order which exists in the world, as is the
case with the human intellect, for the human intellect is nothing other than the
perception of the forms of the existents, in so far as they are without matter.
They concluded, therefore, that existents have two modes of existence, a
sensible existence and an intelligible existence, and that the relation between
sensible and intelligible existence is like the relation between the products of
art and the arts of the craftsman, and they believed therefore that the heavenly
bodies are conscious of these principles and that they can only guide what
exists in the sublunary world because they are animated. And when they compared
the separate intellects with the human intellect, they found that these
intellects are superior to the human intellect, although they have it in common
with the human intellect that their intelligibles are the forms of existents,
and that the form of each of these intellects is nothing but the forms and the
order of the existents it perceives, in the way that the human intellect is
nothing but the forms and the order of the existents it perceives. The
difference between these two kinds of intellect is that the forms of the
existents are a cause of the human intellect, since it receives its perfection
through them, in the way that the existent is brought into being through its
form, whereas the intelligibles of these intellects are the cause of the forms
of the existents. For the order and arrangement in the existents of this
sublunary world are only a consequence and result of the order which exists in
these separate intellects; and the order which exists in the intellect which is
in us is only a consequence of the order and arrangement which it perceives in
the existents, and therefore it is very imperfect, for most of this order and
arrangement it does not perceive. If this is true, there are different degrees
in the forms of the sensible existents; the lowest is their existence in
matters, then their existence in the human intellect is superior to their
existence in matters, and their existence in the separate intellects is still
superior to their existence in the human intellect. Then again they have in the
separate intellects different degrees of superiority of existence, according to
the different degrees of superiority in these intellects in themselves.
And
again when they investigated the body of the heavens they found that in reality
it is one unique body similar to one single animal, and that it has one general
movement-which is like the general movement of the animal which moves the whole
body of the animal -namely, the daily movement, and they found that the other
heavenly bodies and their individual movements were similar to the particular
members of a single animal and its particular movements. And they believed,
because of this connexion between these bodies, their referring to one body and
to one end, and their collaboration in one act-namely, the world in its
totality-that they depended on one principle, as happens to different arts which
aim at one product and which depend on one primary art. For this reason they
believed that these abstract principles depend on a unique abstract principle
which is the cause of all of them, that the forms and the order and arrangement
in this principle are the noblest existence which the forms, the order, and the
arrangement in all reality can possess, that this order and arrangement are the
cause of all the orders and arrangements in this sublunary world, and that the
intellects reach their different degrees of superiority in this, according to
their lesser or greater distance from this principle. The First amongst all
these principles thinks only its own essence and, by thinking its essence,
thinks at the same time all existents in the noblest mode of existence and in
the noblest order and arrangement. The substance of everything under the First
Principle depends on the way in which it thinks the forms, order, and
arrangement which exist in the First Intellect; and their greater or lesser
superiority consists only in this. They conclude therefore that the inferior
cannot think the superior in the way the superior thinks its own essence, nor
does the superior think the inferior in the way the inferior thinks its own
essence; this means that no one of any pair of existents can be of the same rank
as its fellow, since if this were possible they would have become one and would
not form a numerical plurality. Because of this they say that the First thinks
only its own essence, and that the next principle can think only the First, but
cannot think what is under itself, because this is its effect and if it should
think its effect, the effect would become a cause. The philosophers believe that
the consciousness which the First has of its own essence is the cause of all
existents, and that which each of the intellects inferior to it thinks is in
part the cause of those existents the creation of which pertains especially to
it, in part the cause of its own essence, i.e. the human intellect in its
universality.
It
is in this way that the doctrine of the philosophers concerning these things and
concerning the motives which lead them to these beliefs about the world must be
understood. On examination they will not be less convincing than the motives of
the theologians of our religion, first the Mu’tazilites and secondly the
Ash’arites, which lead them to their view of the First Principle. They
believed, namely, that there exists an essence-neither corporeal, nor in a
body-which is living, knowing, willing, provided with power, speaking, hearing,
and seeing, while the Ash’arites, but not the Mu’tazilites, held besides
that this essence is the agent of everything without intermediary and knows them
with an infinite knowledge, since the existents themselves are infinite. The
Ash’arites denied the existence of causes, and professed that this living,
knowing, willing, hearing, seeing, powerful, speaking essence exists in
continuous existence connected with everything and in everything. But this
assumption may be thought to imply consequences open to criticism, for an
essence with qualities as mentioned above must necessarily be of the genus of
the soul, for the soul is an essence, incorporeal, living, knowing, provided
with power, willing, hearing, seeing, speaking, and therefore these theologians
assumed the principle of reality to be a universal soul, separated from matter
in a way they did not understand.’
We
shall now mention the difficulties which result from this assumption. The most
obvious one concerning their theory of the qualities is that there must exist a
composite, eternal essence and therefore an eternal compound, which contradicts
the Ash’arite theory that every compound is temporal, because it is an
accident and every accident is according to them a temporal product. They
assumed besides that all existents are possible acts, and they did not believe
that there is in them an order, a proportion, and a wisdom which the nature of
these existents requires; no, they held that all things could be different from
what they are and this applies necessarily also to the intellect; still, they
believed that in the products of art, to which they compared the products of
nature, there exist order and proportion, and this was called wisdom, and they
called the Creator wises The argument by which they tried to show that there is
in the universe something like this principle was that they compared natural
acts to acts of will and said that every act, in so far as it is an act,
proceeds from an agent endowed with will, power, choice, life, and knowledge,
and that the nature of an act, in so far as it is an act, demands this; and they
tried to prove the truth of this by arguing that what is not living is inorganic
and dead, and, since from the dead there cannot proceed any act, there does not
proceed any act from what is not alive. Thus they denied the acts which proceed
from natural things and moreover they refused to admit that the living beings
which we see in the empirical world have acts; they said that these acts seem
connected with the living in the empirical world, but their agent is only
the living God in the divine world. But the logical conclusion for them would be
that there is in the empirical world no life at all, for life is inferred from
things in the empirical world, because of their acts;b and, further, it would be
interesting to know how they arrived at this judgement about the divine
world.’
The
manner in which they established this creator was by assuming that every
temporal product must have a cause, but that this cannot go on infinitely, and
that therefore of necessity the series must end in an eternal cause; and this is
true enough, only it does not follow from this that this eternal principle
cannot be body. They need therefore the additional proposition that a body
cannot be eternal, but this proposition causes them many difficulties. For it is
not sufficient for them to prove that this world is produced, since it might
still be argued that its cause is an eternal body which has none of the
accidents, no circular movements, nor anything else, through which---although
they themselves admitted an eternal composite being-they proved that the heavens
must be produced. Now, having assumed that the lileavcnly body has been
produced, they supposed that this production had taken place in quite a
different way from what is understood by production in the empirical world. In
the empirical world, namely, things are produced from something, in time and
space, and with a definite quality, not in their totality, and in the empirical
world there is no production of a body from that which is not a body. Nor did
they suppose its agent to act like an agent in the empirical world, for the
empirical agent changes one quality in the existent into another; it does not
change absolute nonexistence into existence-no, it brings the existent into a
form and an intelligible quality through which this existent becomes another
existent instead of this, different from it in substance, definition, name, and
act, as it is expressed in the Divine Words: ‘We have created man from [an
extract of] clay, then we made him a clot in a sure depository, then we created
the clot congealed blood, and we created the congealed blood a morsel, etc.
It is for this reason that the ancient philosophers believed that the absolute
existent neither comes into existence nor can be destroyed.
Now,
if one concedes to the theologians that the heavens were created in time, they
are unable to prove that they are the first of created things, as is the evident
meaning of what is said in the Venerable Book in more than one verse, for
instance, in the Divine Words, ‘Do not those who misbelieve see that the
heavens and the earth were both solid, &c.?’
and in the words, ‘and His throne was upon the water’ and in the words,
‘then He made for heaven and it was but smoke, &c.’s
And as concerns this agent, according to the theologians, it creates the matter
and the form of that which becomes, if they believe that it has a matter, or it
creates the thing in its totality, if they believe it to be simple in the way
they believe the atom to be simple; and if this is so, this kind of agent
changes either non-existence into existence, namely, when there is generation,
that is when the atom, which according to them is the element of the bodies,
comes into being; or existence into non-existence, namely, when there is
destruction, that is, when the atom is destroyed. But it is clear that an
opposite cannot be changed into its opposite, and that non-existence itself
cannot become existence nor warmth itself cold. It is the privation which
becomes existent, it is the warm thing which becomes cold and the cold thing
which becomes warm, and for this reason the Mu’tazilites say that privation is
an entity although they deprive this entity of the attribute of existence before
the becoming of the world. And their arguments by which they believe it can be
proved that a thing does not come into being from another thing are incorrect.
The most plausible of them is their affirmation that, if a thing came into being
from another thing, this would imply an infinite regress. The answer is that
this is only impossible for production in a straight line, which, indeed, needs
an infinite existence in act; but, as to circular production, it is not
impossible that, for instance, fire should come from air and air from fire ad infinitum,
while the substratum is eternal. They support their theory of the temporal
production of the universe by saying that that which cannot be devoid of things
produced must itself be produced, and the universe, being the substratum of the
things that are produced, must therefore be produced. The greatest mistake in
this argument, when its premiss is conceded, is that it is a false
generalization, for that which cannot be devoid of things produced in the
empirical world is a thing produced out of something else, not out of nothing,
whereas they assume that the universe is produced out of nothing. Further, this
substratum which the philosophers call primary matter cannot be devoid of
corporeality according to the philosophers, and, according to the philosophers,
absolute corporeality is not produced. Besides, the premiss which affirms that
what cannot be devoid of things produced is produced, is only true when the
things produced of which it cannot be devoid are individual things, but if the
things produced are one generically, they have no initial term; and from whence
then should it follow that their substratum must be produced? And since among
the theologians the Ash’arites understood this, they added to this proposition
another, namely, that it is not possible that infinite generated things (i.e.
without initial and final term) should exist, a proposition which the
philosophers regard as necessary. Such difficulties follow from the assumption
of the theologians, and they are much more numerous than those which can be held
against the philosophers.
And
again their assumption that the identical agent which is the First Principle is
an agent for everything in the world without an intermediary contradicts the
evidence of the senses that things act upon other things. Their most convincing
argument on this point is that, if the agent were an effect, this would lead to
an infinite regress. But this would only follow if the agent were agent only in
so far as it is effect, and if what is moved were the mover, in so far as it is
moved, but this is not the case; on the contrary the agent is only agent in so
far as it is an actual existent, for the non-existent does not produce any
effect. What follows from this is not that there are no acting effects, as the
theologians thought, but that the acting effects end in an agent which itself is
not an effect at all. Further, the impossibility which is the consequence of
their deduction is still greater than the impossibility which follows from the
premisses from which they draw this conclusion. For if the principle of the
existents is an essence, endowed with life, knowledge, power, and will, and if
these qualities are additional to its essence and this essence is incorporeal,
then the only difference between the soul and this existent is that the soul is
in a body and this existent is a soul which is not in a body. But that which has
such a quality is necessarily composed of an essence and attributes, and each
compound requires of necessity a cause for its being a compound, since a thing
can neither be compounded by itself nor produced by itself, for producing, which
is an act of the producer, is nothing but the putting together of the product.
And, in general, just as for each effect there must be an agent, so for each
compound there must be an agent which puts it together, for the putting together
is a condition of the existence of the compounds And nothing can be a cause of
the condition of its own existence, because this would imply that a thing should
be its own cause. Therefore the Mu’tazilites assumed that these attributes in
the First Principle refer to its essence and are nothing additional to it, in
the way in which this happens with many essential qualities in many existents,
like a thing’s being existent and one and eternal and so on
This comes nearer to the truth than the theory of the Ash’arites, and
the philosophers’ theory of the First Principle approaches that of the
Mu’tazilites.
We
have now mentioned the motives which led these two parties to their theories
about the First Principle, and the conclusions which their adversaries can draw
from them and hold against them. As concerns the objections against the
philosophers, Ghazali has related them in full;
we have answered some of them already, and we will answer some of them
later. The difficulties which beset the theologians we have shown in this
discussion in detail.
We
shall now return to distinguish the degree of conviction and plausibility
reached by the different statements which Ghazali
makes in this book, as we proposed to do, and we were only compelled to mention
the plausible propositions which led the philosophers to their theories about
the principles of the universe because they answer the objections which their
adversaries, the theologians, adduce against them; on the other hand, we
mentioned the difficulties which beset the theologians because it is only right
that their arguments on this problem should be known and their views
represented, since they are free to use them as they wish. It is right, as
Aristotle says, that a man should adduce the arguments of his adversaries as he
brings forward his own; that is, he should exert himself to find the arguments
of his opponents in the same way as he exerts himself to find the arguments of
his own school of thought, and he should accept the same kind of arguments from
them as he accepts when he has found the arguments himself.’
We
say: The objection that the First Principle, if it can think only its own
essence, must be ignorant of everything it has created would be only a valid
inference if the way it thinks its essence were to exclude all existents
absolutely. But the philosophers mean only that the manner in which it thinks
its own essence includes the existents in their noblest mode of existence, and
that it is the intellect which is the cause of the existents; and that it is not
an intellect because it thinks the existents, in so far as they are the cause of
its thinking, as is the case with our intellect. The meaning of their words,
that it does not think the existents which are under it, is that it does not
think them in the way we think them, but that it thinks them in a way no other
thinking existent can think them, for if another existent could think them in
the way it thinks them, it would participate in the knowledge of God, and God is
far too exalted for this . This is a quality which is peculiar to God, and for
this reason certain theologians concluded that God, besides the seven qualities
which they attribute to Him, has yet another which is peculiar to Him. Therefore
His knowledge can be described neither as universal nor as individual, for both
the universal and the individual are effects of existents, and the knowledge of
both universal and individual is transitory. We shall explain this still better
when we discuss the question whether God knows individuals or does not know
them, as the philosophers mostly assert when they pose this problem, and we
shall explain that the whole problem is absurd in relation to Gods This problem
as a whole is based on two necessary points. First, if God thought existents in
such a way that they should be the cause of His knowledge, His intellect would
necessarily be transitory and the superior would be brought into being through
the inferior. Secondly, if His essence did not contain the intelligibles of all
things and their order, there would exist a supreme intellect which would not
perceive the forms of existents in their order and proportion. And since these
two cases are absurd, it follows that when this principle thinks its own
essence, these existents exist in it in a nobler mode than that in
which they exist by themselves. And that one and the same existent can have
different degrees of existence can be shown from what occurs with colour . For
we find that colour has different degrees of existence, some higher than others;
the lowest degree is its existence in matter, a higher degree is its existence
in sight, for it exists in such a way that the colour becomes conscious of
itself, whereas existence in matter is an inorganic existence without
consciousness; further, it has been proved in the science of psychology that
colour has also an existence in the imaginative faculty, and this is a superior
existence to its existence in the faculty of sight; it has equally been shown
that it has an existence in the remembering faculty superior to that in the
imaginative faculty,s and, finally, it has in the intellect an existence
superior to all these existences. Now, in the same way, we are convinced that it
has in the essence of the First Knowledge an existence superior to all its other
existences, and that this is the highest degree of existence possible.
As
for what Ghazali mentions concerning the
philosophical theory of the order in the emanation of these separate principles
and of the number of entities which emanate out of each of them, there is no
proof that this really takes place and that this happens exactly in this way;
and the form in which Ghazali relates it is
therefore not to be found in the works of the ancient philosophers. But these
philosophers all agree on the theory that the principles, both separate and
nonseparate, all emanate from the First Principle, and that through the
emanation of this unique power the world in its totality becomes a unity, and
that through this power all its parts are connected, so that the universe aims
at one act, as happens with the one body of an animal; which, however, has
different potencies, members, and acts; and indeed the world is according to the
learned one and the same existent only because of this one power which emanates
from the First Principle. And they agree about all this, because according to
them the heavens are like a single animal and the daily movement which is common
to all the heavens is like the animal’s general movement in space, and the
particular movements which the different parts of heaven have are like the
particular movements of the members of the animal. And the philosophers had
already proved that there is one power in the animal through which it becomes
one and through which all the potencies which it possesses tend towards one act,
that is, towards the preservation of the animal,’ and all these potencies are
connected with the potency which emanates from the First Principle; and if this
were not the case, its parts would disconnect themselves and it would not
persist for the twinkling of an eye. If, however, it is necessary that for a
single animal there should be a single spiritual potency, permeating all its
parts, through which the plurality of potencies and bodies in it becomes
unified, so that it can be said of its bodies and potencies that they are one,
and if, further, the relations of individual beings to the universe in its
totality are like the relation of the parts of an animal to the animal itself,
it needs must be the case that all the potencies in the particular parts of this
unique animal and in the psychological and intellectual motive powers of these
parts should be such that there is in them one single spiritual force which
connects all the spiritual and bodily potencies and which permeates the universe
in one and the same penetration. If this were not the case, no order and no
proportion would exist. And in this way it is true that God is the creator,
supporter, and preserver of everything, and to this the Divine Words apply:
‘Verily, God supports the heavens and the earth lest they should decline.’S
And it in no way follows from the fact that this one potency permeates many
things that there should be a plurality in it, as those thought who said that
from the First Principle there can in the first place emanate only one from
which plurality can then emanate; for this statement can only be regarded as
valid if the immaterial agent is compared to the material agent. Therefore the
term ‘agent’ can only be applied equivocally to both the immaterial agent
and the material. And this will explain to you the possibility of the procession
of plurality from the Monad.
Again,
the existence of all other separate principles consists only in the forms in
which they conceive the First Principle, and it is not impossible that this
should be one identical thing, notwithstanding the difference of the forms in
which they conceive it, in the same way as it is not impossible that a plurality
should be conceived through one and the same form. And we find, indeed, that all
the heavenly bodies in their daily movement, and the sphere of the fixed stars,
conceive one identical form’ and that they all, moving in this daily movement,
are moved by one and the same mover, who is the mover of the sphere of the fixed
stars; and we find, too, that they have also different particular movements.
Therefore it needs must be that their movements proceed partly from different
movers, partly namely through the connexion of their movements with the first
sphere-from one unique mover . And just as the removal of an organ or a potency
vital to the whole animal would invalidate all the organs and potencies of this
animal, so the same applies to heaven with respect to its parts and its moving
potencies, and in general with respect to the principles of the world and their
parts in relation to the First Principle and in their mutual relations.
According to the philosophers the world is closely similar to a single state: a
state is upheld through one ruler and many deputies subordinate to him; all the
deputies in the state are connected with the first ruler, because the authority
of each of them is based on him alone, with respect to the ends and the order of
the acts which lead to these ends for the sake of which these deputies exist;
and so is the relation of the First Ruler in the world to His deputies. And it
is evident to the philosophers that he who bestows on the immaterial existents
their end is identical with him who bestows on them their existence, for
according to them form and end are identical in this kind of existent and he who
bestows on these existents both form and end is their agent. And therefore it is
clear that the First Principle is the principle of all these principles, and
that He is an agent, a form, and an ends And as to His relation to the sensible
existents, He is-since He bestows on them the unity which causes their plurality
and the unification of their plurality-the cause of all of them, being their
agent, form, and end, and all the existents seek their end by their movement
towards Him, and this movement by which they seek their end is the movement for
the sake of which they are created, and in so far as this concerns all
existents, this movement exists by nature, and in so far as this concerns man,
it is voluntary. And therefore man is of all beings the one charged with duty
and obligation. And this is the meaning of the Divine Words: ‘Verily, we
offered the trust to the heavens and the earth and the mountains, but they
refused to bear it and shrank from it; but man bore it: verily he is ever unjust
and ignorant.’
And
the philosophers only assert that, although all these ruling principles proceed
from the First Principle, it is only some of them that do so directly, whereas
others, ascending gradually from the lower world to the higher, proceed
mediately. For they discovered that certain parts of heaven exist for the sake
of the movements of other parts, and they related them in each instance to a
first principle, till they finally arrived at the absolutely First Principle;
and so it was evident to them that there was one unique
order and one unique act in which they all participate. But to ascertain
the order, which he who contemplates reality and aspires to the knowledge of the
First Principle perceives, is difficult, and what human understanding can grasp
of it is only its general principle. What led the philosophers to believe in a
gradation of these principles, in conformity with the spatial order of their
spheres, is that they saw that the highest sphere seems in its action superior
to what is under it, and that all the other spheres follow its movement . And
therefore they believed that what was said about their order was based on their
spatial order. But one might perhaps object that the order in the spheres is
perhaps only based on their activity, not on their spatial order; for since it
seemed that the activities and movements of the planets exist because of the
movement of the sun, perhaps their movers in setting them in motion follow the
sun, and the movement of the sun derives perhaps directly from the First. For
this reason there are in this question no indubitable assertions, but only
assertions more or less plausible and likely to be true. And since this is
established, let us now return to our subject.
Ghazali
says:
The second answer is: people say of the First Principle that it knows only itself, because they want to avoid the implication of plurality in it, for the statement that it ]snows another would imply a duality: its knowing itself and its knowing another. However, the same applies to the first effect: it must necessarily know only itself. If it knew another and not itself alone, there would have to be a different cause for its knowing another than that for its knowing itself, but there is no other cause than that for its knowing itself, namely the First Principle. So it can only know itself, and the plurality which arose in this way disappears.
If it is said that it follows from its existence and from its knowing itself that it must know its principle, we answer: Does this necessity arise from a cause or without a cause? If the former is the case, there is no other cause than the one first cause from which only one effect can proceed, and indeed has proceeded, namely this first effect itself; how, therefore, could this second effect proceed from it? In the latter case, then, let the existence of the First Principle imply a plurality of existents without a cause, and let the plurality follow from them! But if such a thing cannot be imagined, because the necessary existent can be only one, and anything added to it must be a possible, and the possible needs a cause, then the following conclusion must be drawn concerning the effect: if it is an existent necessary by itself, then what the philosophers say is untrue, that there is only one necessary existent; if it is a possible,’ then it needs a cause; but it has no cause,’ and therefore it cannot know the existence of its cause.
There is no special necessity for the first effect to have a possible existence; this is necessary for any effect. However, that the effect should know its cause is not necessary for its existence, just as the knowledge of its effect is not necessary for the existence of the cause; still, it seems more plausible that the cause should know its effect than that the effect should know its cause. Therefore the plurality which would arise from its knowing its principle is impossible; there is no principle for this knowledge and it is not a necessary consequence of an effect that it should know its principle; and out of this there is no issue.
I say:
This
is a proof of one who affirms that the First Principle must, besides knowing
itself, know its effect; for, if not, its knowing itself would be imperfect.
The
meaning of Ghazali’s objection is that the
knowledge the effect has of its principle must either be based on a cause or be
without a cause. In the former case, there must be a cause in the First
Principle, but there is none; in the latter case, a plurality must follow from
the First Principle, even if it does not know it; if, however, a plurality
follows from it, it cannot be a necessary existent, for there can be only one
necessary existent, and that from which there proceeds more than one is only a
possible existent; but the possible existent needs a cause, and therefore their
assertion that the First Principle is a necessary existent is false, even if it
does not know its effect. He says
also that if it is not a necessity of its existence that the effect should have
knowledge of its cause, it even seems more fitting that it is not a necessity of
its existence that the cause should know its effect.
My
answer to this is that all this is sophistical. If we assume that the cause is
an intellect and knows its effect, it does not follow that this is an addition
to the essence of the cause; on the contrary, it belongs to the essence itself,
since the emergence of the effect is the consequence of its essences And it is
not true that if the effect proceeds from the First Principle not because of a
cause, but because of the essence of this principle, a plurality proceeds from
it, for according to the thesis of the philosophers the emergence of the effect
depends on the essence of the First Principle: if its essence is one, one
proceeds from it; if many, many proceed from it. What he assumes in this
discussion, namely, that every effect is a possible existent, is only true for
the composite effect, for there cannot be a compound that is eternal, and
everything that is of a possible existence is generated, according to the
philosophers, as Aristotle has shown in different passages of his works;’ and
we shall prove this more fully later in our discussion of the necessary being.
What Avicenna calls the possible existent has only its name in common with what
is in reality the possible existent; it is, therefore, by no means clear that it
needs an agent in the way it is clear that the possible existent needs an agent.
Ghazali
says:
The third objection is: Is the self-knowledge of the first effect identical with its essence or not? If the former , this is impossible, for knower and known cannot be identical; if the latter, let the same apply to the First Principle, so that plurality will follow from the First Principle. And if the self-knowledge of the effect is not identical with the essence of the effect, there will not only be a triplicity in the effect, as they affirm, but a quadruplicity, to wit: its essence, its knowledge of itself, its knowledge of its principle, and its being a possible existent by itself, and to this it should perhaps be added that it is an existent necessary through another-and then it would be fivefold. From this you can see and measure the depth of their ignorance.
I
say:
In
this discussion of the intellects there are two points: first the question about
what these intellects know or do not know (this question was fully treated by
the ancients); secondly, the question of what proceeds from these intellects.
What Ghazali mentions here as the theory of the
philosophers is in fact the individual opinion of Avicenna on this latter
problem. Ghazali exerts himself especially to
refute him and his followers, in order to create the impression that he has
refuted them all; and this is acting like one who is, as he puts it, in the
depths of ignorance. But this theory is not found in the works of any of the
ancients; and there is no proof of it except the supposition that from the one
there can proceed only one. But this proposition does not apply in the same way
to the agents which are forms in matter as to the agents which are forms
separate from matter, and according to the philosophers an intellect which is an
effect must necessarily know its principle, and there are here not two entities,
i.e. the intellect and something additional to its essence, for, if so, it would
be a compound, and the intellect, which is simple, cannot be composite. And the
difference in the separate forms between cause and effect is that the First
Cause exists by itself and the second cause exists through its relation with the
First Cause, for the fact of its being an effect lies in its substance and is
not an additional entity, in contrast with material effects; e.g. colour is an
entity which exists by itself in a body, but it is the cause of sight, in so far
as it is related, and sight has no existence except in this relation;’ and in
the same way substances which are
separate from matter are substances which are of the nature of relation. For
this reason the cause and the effect are unified in the forms separated from
matter, and in the same way sensible forms are of the nature of relation, as has been
proved in the book on psychology.’
Ghazali
says:
The fourth objection is that it can be said: Triplicity is not sufficient in the first effect, for the body of heaven which, according to the philosophers, proceeds from one entity out of the essence of its principle is composite, and this in three ways.
The first way is that it is composed of form and matter, as is body generally, according to the philosophers, and both must have a principle, since matter differs from form and they are, according to the philosophers, interdependent causes, so that the one cannot come into being by means of the other without the intervention of another cause.
I say:
What
he says here is that according to the philosophers the body of the heavens is
composed of matter, form, and soul, and that therefore there must be in the
second intellects from which the body of the heavens proceeds, four entities,
namely, one from which the form proceeds, one from which the hyle proceeds-as
both are interdependent, for matter is in one way a cause of form and form in
one way a cause of matterb-one from which the soul proceeds, and one from which
the mover of the second sphere proceeds. But the view that the body of the
heavens is composed of form and matter like other bodies is falsely ascribed by
Avicenna to the Peripatetics. On the contrary, according to them the body of the
heavens is a simple body; if it were composite, it would, according to them,
suffer corruption, and therefore they say that it neither comes into being nor
perishes, and does not possess the potency for contraries. If it were as
Avicenna says, it would be composite like a living being, and if this were true,
quadruplicity would be a necessary consequence for the man who asserted that
from the one only one can proceed. And we have already stated that the way these
forms are causes for each other, for the heavenly bodies, and for the sublunary
world, and the way the First Cause is a cause for all of them, is quite
different from all this.
Ghazali
says:
The second way is that the highest sphere has a definite measure of size, and its determination by this special measure taken from among all other measures is an addition to the existence of its essence, since its essence might be smaller or bigger than it is; therefore, it must have a determinant for this measure, added to the simple entity which causes its existence. The same necessity does not exist for the existence of the intellect, which is pure existence and not specified by any measure taken from among other measures, and therefore may be said to need only a simple cause.
I
say:
The
meaning of this statement is that when the philosophers say that the body of the
sphere proceeds as a third entity, which by itself is not simple (for it is a
body possessing quantity), there are here in reality two entities, the one which
provides the substantial corporeality, the other the definite quantity;
therefore there must be in the intellect from which the body of the sphere
proceeds more than one entity, and therefore the second cause is not triple but
quadruple. But this is a false assumption, for the philosophers do not believe
that body in its entirety’ proceeds from the separate principles; if anything
proceeds from them, according to the philosophers, it is only the substantial
form, and according to them the measures of the bodily parts follow from the
forms; this, however, refers only to the forms in matter, but the heavenly
bodies, since they are simple, are not susceptible of measure. Therefore, to
assume that form and matter proceed from an abstract principle is by no means in
conformity with philosophical principles, and is quite absurd. In reality, the
agent in transitory things,’ according to the philosophers, produces neither
the form nor the matter; it only makes a compound out of matter and form. If the
agent produced the form in matter, it would produce the form in something, not
from something. This is not philosophical theory, and there is no sense in
refuting it, as if it were.
Ghazali says, on behalf of the
philosophers:
It might be said: If the sphere were bigger than it is, this greater size would be superfluous for the order of the universe; if smaller, it would not suffice for the intended order.
I
say:
He means by
this statement that the philosophers do not believe that, for example, the body
of the sphere could be bigger or smaller than it is, for in either case the
order intended in the universe would not be realized, and the sphere would not
set the world in motion according to its natural power, but either too strongly
or too weakly, both of which would involve the corruption of the world. A
greater size of the world would not be a superfluity, as Ghazali
says; no, out of both, bigness and smallness, the
corruption of the world would result.’
Ghazali
says, to refute the philosophers:
We answer: Does the determination of the manner of this order suffice in itself for the existence of what possesses this order, or does it need a cause to effect it? If you believe it suffices, then you regard it as superfluous to assume causes at all, and you may well judge that from the order of these existents the existents themselves result without any additional cause; if, however, you believe it does not suffice, but a cause is necessary, this new cause will not suffice either for the specification of these measures, but will itself need a cause for its specifying .’
I say:
The
summary of this is that he makes the objection against them that in the body
there are many things which cannot proceed from one agent, unless they admit
that many acts can proceed out of one agent, or unless they believe that many
accidents of the body result from the form of the body and that the form of the
body results from the agent. For, according to such an opinion, the accidents
resulting from the body which comes into being through the agent do not proceed
from the agent directly but through the mediation of the form. This is a
conception permissible to the doctrines of the philosophers, but not to those of
the theologians. However, I believe that the Mu’tazilites think as the
philosophers do that there are things which do not directly proceed from the
agent . We have already explained how the Monad is the cause of the order, and
of the existence of all things which support this order, and there is no sense
in repeating ourselves.
Ghazali says:
The third way is that in the highest heavens there are marked out two points, the poles, which are immovable and do not leave their position, whereas the parts of the equator change their position. Now either all the parts of the highest sphere are similar (and then there will not be a special determination of two points amongst all the points to be poles), or the parts of the sphere are different and some have a special character which others have not. What, then, is the principle of these differences? For the body of the heavens proceeds from only one and the same simple entity and the simple can cause only that which is simple of shape, namely the sphere, and that which is homogeneous, that is, has no special distinguishable character. And out of this there is no issue.
I
say:
‘Simple’
has two meanings: first, simplicity can be attributed to that which is not
composed of many part, although it is composed of form and matter, and in this
way the four elements are called simple;’ secondly, it can be attributed to
that which is not composed of form and matter capable of changing its form,
namely to the heavenly bodies; further, simplicity can be attributed to the
agglomerate which has the same definition for its whole and its part, even when
it is composed of the four elements. The simple character which is attributed to
the heavenly bodies can very well possess parts which are differentiated by
nature, as are the right and left sides of the sphere and the poles; for the
globe, in so far as it is a globe, must have definite poles and a definite
centre through which globes differ individually, and it does not follow from the
fact that the globe has definite sides that it is not simple, for it is simple
in so far as it is not composed of form and matter in which there is potency,
and it is non-homogeneous in so far as the part which receives the place of the
poles cannot be any part of the
globe, but is a part determined by nature in each globe individually. If this
were not so, globes could not have centres by nature through which they were
differentiated; thus they are heterogeneous-in this special meaning of the word
‘heterogeneous’-but this does not imply that they are composed of bodies
different by nature, nor that their agent is composed of many potencies, for
every globe is one. Nor do the philosophers regard it as true that every point
of whatever globe can be a centre and that only the agent specifies the points,
for this is only true in artificial things, not in natural globes. And from the
assumption that every point of the globe can be a centre, and that it is the
agent which specifies the points, it does not follow that the agent is a
manifold unless one assumes that there is in the empirical world nothing that
can proceed from a single agent; for in the empirical world things are composed
of the ten categories and therefore anything whatever in the world would need
ten agents. But all this, to which the view in question leads, which is very
much like babbling in metaphysics, is stupid and senseless talk. The artificial
product in the empirical world is produced, indeed, by only one agent, even if
it possesses the ten categories. How untrue is this proposition that the one can
produce only one, if it is understood in the way Avicenna and Farabi understand
it, and Ghazali himself in his Niche for Lights, where he accepts their theory of the First
Principle.’
Ghazali
says:
One might say: ‘Perhaps there are in the principle different kinds of plurality which do not result from its being a principle, only three or four are manifest to us, and the rest we do not perceive, but our incapacity for observation does not shake our belief that the principle of plurality is plurality and that from the one no manifold can proceed.’
I say:
If
the philosophers made such a statement, they would have to believe that there is
in the first effect an infinite plurality, and one would necessarily have to ask
them whence plurality comes in the first effect. And since they say that from
the one no manifold proceeds, they would have to concede that the manifold
cannot proceed from the One, but their statement that from the one only one proceeds contradicts their
statement that what proceeds from
the First Monad possesses plurality, for from the One one must proceed. Of
course they can say that each term in the plurality of the first effect is a
first term, but then there must be a plurality of first terms. It is most
astonishing how this could remain hidden from Farabi and Avicenna, for they were
the first who made these silly statements, and many followed them and attributed
these theories to the philosophers. For when Farabi, Avicenna, and their school
say that the plurality in the second principle arises through its self-knowledge
and its knowing another, it follows for them that its essence has two natures or
two forms, and it would be interesting to know which form proceeds from the
First Principle and which does not. And there is a similar difficulty in their
statement that the second principle is possible by itself, but necessary by
another, for its possible nature must necessarily be different from its
necessary nature, which it acquires from the necessary being. But the possible
nature cannot become necessary, unless the nature of the possible can become
necessary. Therefore there is in necessary natures no possibility at all, be it
a possibility necessary by itself or a possibility necessary by another. All
these are senseless statements and assertions, weaker than those of the
theologians, extraneous to philosophy, and not congruous with its principles,
and none of these affirmations reaches the level of rhetorical persuasion, to
say nothing of dialectic persuasion.
And therefore
what Ghazali says in different passages of his
books is true, that the metaphysics of Farabi and Avicenna are conjectural.
Ghazali
says:
We answer: If you regard this as possible, say then that all existing things in their multiplicity (and indeed their number reaches thousands) derive from the first effect and one need not limit this to the body of the extreme sphere’ and its soul, but all souls, heavenly and human, and all earthly and heavenly bodies can proceed from it, with the many diversities, belonging to them, which nobody has ever seen. But then the first effect will suffice.
I say:
This
conclusion is true, especially when they imagine that the first act proceeding
from the First Principle is the unity through which the first effect becomes a
unique existent, notwithstanding the plurality in it. And indeed, if they allow
an undetermined plurality in the first effect, it must be less or more than the
number of existents, or equal to it; if less, they must introduce a third
principle unless there is a thing without cause, if equal or more, the plurality
assumed in it will be superfluous.
Ghazali says:
And then it follows that the First Cause by itself will suffice too. For if one regards it as possible that a plurality should arise inevitably, although without a cause, and although there is no necessity for it in the existence of the first effect, this will be permissible also with reference to the First Cause, and the existence of all things will be without a cause, although it is said that they follow inevitably and their number is not known. And if their existence without a cause can be imagined with reference to the First Cause, it can also be imagined with reference to the second cause; indeed, there is no sense in speaking of a reference to the first or to the second cause, since there is no distinction between them in time and place and neither the first nor the second cause can be characterized by its relation to things which do not differ from them in time and place and can exist without a cause.
I say:
He says that if a plurality in the first effect is
permissible without a cause, because out of the First Cause there does not
follow a plurality,
one
may also suppose a plurality within the First Cause, and there is no need to
assume a second cause and a first effect. And if the existence of something
without cause within the First Cause is impossible, then it is also impossible
within the second cause; indeed, our expression ‘second cause’ has no sense,
since in fact they are one and the same thing, and the one is not different from
the other either in time or in space, and if it is permissible that something
should exist without a cause, neither the First Cause nor the second can be
specially distinguished by this; it suffices that it refers to one of them and
therefore it is not necessary to refer it to the second cause.
Ghazali
says by way of an answer in the name of the philosophers:
It might be said: ‘The entities have become so many that they exceed thousands, but it seems absurd that a plurality of that extent exists in the first effect and for this reason we have multiplied the intermediates.’
Then
he says in refutation of this:
We answer, however: To say ‘it seems absurd’ is pure conjecture, and such a judgement should not be applied to intelligibles. But if one says that it is impossible, we ask: ‘Why is it impossible, what will refute it, and where is the criterion?’ For, once we exceed the one and believe that one, two, or three entities can arise in the first effect without a cause, what makes it impossible that there should be four, five, indeed, a thousand and many thousands , and who could fix the limit? No, if unity is once exceeded, nothing can be rejected. This proof again is decisive.
I say:
If,
however, Avicenna and these other philosophers had answered that the first
effect possesses plurality, and that necessarily any plurality becomes one
through a unity which requires that plurality should depend on unity, and that
this unity through which plurality becomes one is a simple entity which proceeds
from an individual simple Monad, then they would have saved themselves from
these objections of Ghazali, and disengaged
themselves from these false theories. But since Ghazali
secured his point by ascribing a false assumption to the philosophers, and did
not find anyone to give him a correct answer, he made merry and multiplied the
impossibilities which can be deduced from their theory, for anyone who lets his
horse canter in an empty space can make merry. But if he had known that he did
not thereby refute the philosophers, he would not have been so delighted about
it. The fundamental mistake of Avicenna and Farabi was that they made the
statement that from the one only one can proceed, and then assumed a plurality
in the one which proceeds. Therefore they were forced to regard this plurality
as uncaused. And their assumption that this plurality was a definite plurality;
which demanded the introduction of a third and fourth principle was a
supposition not enforced by any proof. And generally, this assumption is not a
legitimate assumption for a first and second principle, for they might be asked,
‘Why has only the second principle and
rot the first this special character of possessing a plurality?’ All this is
foolish and senseless talk. The fact is that Avicenna and Farabi did not know
how the Monad was a cause in the system of Aristotle and the Peripatetics.
Aristotle, in the twelfth book of his Metaphysics,
expresses pride in his solution,’ and says that none of his predecessors
could say anything about this problem. In the sense in which we have expounded
the Aristotelian doctrine, this statement that out of the one only one can
proceed is true, and the statement that out of the one a plurality proceeds is
equally true.
Ghazali
says:
Further, we affirm that the statement that out of the one only one can proceed is false in respect of the second effect, for out of it there emanates the sphere of the fixed stars, in which there are a thousand and twenty-odd stars ,’ different in magnitude, shape, position, colour,’ and influence, be it of ill omen or auspicious, some in the shape of a ram, a bull, or a lion, ; others in the shape of a man; they influence one and the same place of the sublunary world differently in conferment of cold and warmth, fortune and misfortune,’ and their own measures are variable . On account of their differences it cannot be said that they are all of one kind; for if this could be said, it might also be said that all the bodies of the world were of one and the same kind of corporeal nature, and that one cause sufficed for them all. But just as the differences in qualities, substances, and natures of the bodies of the sublunary world show that they themselves are different, in the same way the stars, no doubt, are shown to differ, and each of them will need a cause for its form, a cause for its matter, a cause for the special function in its nature, to bring warmth or cold or happiness or calamity, a cause for its being in the definite place it occupies, then again a cause for its special tendency to group itself with others in the shapes of different animals. And if this plurality can be imagined to be known in the second intellect, it can also be imagined in the first intellect; and then this first intellect will suffice.
I say:
He
had already exhausted this difficulty which is of a type he uses abundantly in
this book, and if the answer we have given in defence of the philosophers is
valid, none of these impossibilities need follow. But if by this expression one
understands that, from the simple numerically one, only one simple one-not
something numerically one in one way, but plural in another-can proceed, and
that its unity is the cause of the existence of plurality, then one can never
escape from these doubts. And again, things only become many, according to the
philosophers, through substantial differences, and differences through
accidents-be they quantitative, qualitative, or in whichsoever of the nine
categories of the accident-do not cause, according to them, differentiations in
the substance,’ and the heavenly bodies, as we said, are not composed of
matter and form and are not specifically different, since they have, according
to the philosophers, no common genus (for, if so, they would be composite, not
simple). But we have treated of this already, and there is no sense in repeating
ourselves.
Ghazali says:
The fifth objection is to say: If we concede these inept assumptions and these erroneous judgements, how is it then that they are not ashamed to say that from the fact that the first effect is of a possible existence, there results the existence of the highest sphere, and that from its knowledge of itself there follows the existence of the soul of the sphere and from its knowledge of the First Principle there follows the existence of an intellect? What is the difference between this and the statement that the existence of an unknown man is necessary , and that he is of a possible existence and knows himself and his Creator and then that from the fact that he is of a possible existence there follows the existence of a sphere? But it will be objected: What is the relation between his having a possible existence and the existence of a sphere following from him? And the same holds for the fact that from his knowing himself and his Creator there follow two other entities. But it would be ridiculous to say such a thing about a man or any other existent whatever, for the possibility of existence is a concept which does not change through the changing of the possible object, be it a man or an angel or a sphere. I do not know how any madman could content himself with any of these assertions, let alone the learned who split hairs in their discussions about intelligibles.
I say:
These
are all theories of Avicenna and his followers, which are not true and are not
built on the foundations of the philosophers; still they are not so inept as
this man says they are, nor does he represent them in a true light. For the man
whom he supposed to be of a possible existence through himself and necessary
through another, knowing himself and his agent, is only a true representation of
the second cause, when it is assumed in addition that through his essence and
through his knowledge he is the agent of the existents, in the way this is
assumed by Avicenna and his school of the second principle, and in the way all
philosophers must admit it of the First Principle, God, glory be to Him. If this
is admitted, it follows that from this man two things proceed: one in so far as
he knows himself, the other, in so far as he knows his Creator, for he is
supposed to act only because of his knowledge, and it is not absurd, if he is
supposed to act because of his essence, to say that what proceeds from him, in
so far as lie has a possible existence, is different from what proceeds from him
in so far as he has a necessary existence, since both these attributes exist in
his nature. This theory, therefore, is not so ignominious as this man tries to
represent it to be through this comparison, in order to cast odium on the
theories of the philosophers and to make them despicable in the eyes of
students.’
There
is no difference between Ghazali’s comparison
and a person who said: If you assume a being living through life, willing
through will, knowing through knowledge, hearing, seeing, and speaking through
audition, sight, and speech, and the whole world proceeds from him, it is
possible that from man, living,
knowing, hearing, seeing, speaking, the whole world proceeds, for if these
attributes by themselves determine the existence of the world, it cannot make
any difference in the effect through whichever being possessing these attributes
they produce it. If this man Ghazali sought to
speak the truth in this and erred, he might be forgiven; if, however, he
understood how to deceive in these things and tried that, and if there were no
necessity for him to do so, there is no excuse for him. And if he only wanted to
show that he possessed no proof by which he could provide an answer to the
question whence plurality proceeds, as might be inferred from what he says
below, he speaks the truth, for Ghazali had not
reached the degree of knowledge necessary for comprehending this problem, as
will be seen from what he says later; and the reason is that he studied only the
books of Avicenna, and through this the deficiency in his knowledge arose.
Ghazali says:
But if one should say to us: ‘Certainly, you have refuted their theory, but what do you say yourself? Do you affirm that from one thing two different things can in any way proceed? In that case you offend reason. Or will you say that in the First Principle there is plurality? In that case you abandon the doctrine of God’s unity. Or will you say that there is no plurality in the world? In that case you contradict the evidence of the senses. Or will you say that plurality occurs through intermediates? In that case you are forced to acknowledge the theory of your opponents. We answer: ‘We have not made a deep inquiry in this book; our aimwhich we have attained-was only to disturb the claims of our opponents. To this we may add that the claim that the thesis that two proceed from one is an affront to reason, and the claim that the attribution of eternal attributes to the First Principle contradicts the doctrine of God’s unityboth these claims, we say, are vain and possess no proof. The impossibility that two should proceed from one is not known in the way the impossibility of one single person’s being in two places is known in short, it is known neither by intuitive necessity nor by deduction. What is the objection against saying: ‘The First Principle is provided with knowledge, power, will; He acts as He wants, He judges as He wants, He creates the dissimilar and the similar as He Hants and in the way He wants?’The impossibility of this is known neither by immediate necessity nor by deduction. But the prophets have brought us this truth, justifying it through their miracles, and we must accept it. To inquire, however, how God’s act proceeds from Him through His Will is vain and an illusory pursuit. Those who have sought to represent and understand this have arrived as a result of their inquiry at a first effect from which as a possible existent there proceeds a sphere, and from which, so far as it knows itself, there proceeds the soul of the sphere. But this is nonsense and is by no means an appropriate explanation. Let us therefore accept the principles of these things from the prophets, and let us believe in this, since the intellect does not regard it as impossible. And let us abandon the inquiry about quality, quantity, and quiddity,’ for the human powers do not suffice for this. And therefore the master of the Divine Law has said: Think about God’s creation, but do not think about God’s essence.
I
say:
His
statement is true, that we have to refer to the Law of God everything which the
human mind is unable to grasp. For the knowledge which results from revelation
comes only as a perfection of the sciences of the intellect; that is, any
knowledge which the weakness of the human mind is unable to grasp is bestowed
upon man by God through revelation. This inability to comprehend things the
knows ledge of which is, however, necessary in the life and existence of man, is
either absolute-i.e. it is not in the nature of the intellect, in so far as it
is intellect, to comprehend such a thing-or it is not in the nature of a certain
class of men, and this kind of weakness is either a fundamental character of his
disposition or something accidental through a lack of education. Revelation is a
mercy bestowed on all these classes of men.
And
as to Ghazali’s words:
Our aim-which we have attained-was only to disturb our opponents; this aim is not a proper one for him and is censurable in a learned man, for the intention of the learned, in so far as they are learned, must be to seek the truth, not to sow doubts and perplex minds.
And
as to his words:
the impossibility that two should proceed from one is not known in the way the impossibility a single person’s being in two places is known; although these two propositions are not of the same degree of assent, still the proposition that from the simple unit there proceeds only one single unit keeps its evidence inside the empirical world. Propositions which are evident differ in their degree of evidence, as has been shown in the Posterior Analytics, and the reason for this is that when evident propositions are supported by imagination they receive a stronger degree of assent, and unsupported by imagination their assent is weakened; but only the masses rely on imagination, and he who is well trained in intellectual thought and renounces imagination accepts both propositions with the same degree of assent.
The
strongest degree of evidence pertains to this proposition when a man makes an
induction from transitory existents and sees that they only change their names
and definitions through their acts and that, if any existent whatever could
arise from any act and any agent whatever, the essences and definitions would
become mixed and knowledge would be annihilated. The soul, for instance,
distinguishes itself from the inorganic only through its special acts which
proceed from it, and inorganic things are only distinguished from one another
through the acts that are proper to them; and the same applies to souls. And if
many acts were to proceed from a single potency, in the way that many acts
proceed from composite potencies, there would be no difference between the
simple and the composite essence and they would be indistinguishable for us. And
again, if many acts could proceed from one single essence, an act without an
agent would be possible, for an existent comes to be through an existent, not
through a non-existent, and therefore the non-existent cannot come to be by
itself; and if it is true that the mover of the privation and the transposer of
its potency into act transposes it only through the actuality it possesses
itself, of necessity the actuality it possesses must be of the same kind as the
act it transposes If any effect
whatever could proceed from any agent whatever, it would not be impossible that
the effects should be actualized by themselves without an agent. And if many
kinds of potency could be actualized through one and the same agent, this agent
would itself have to possess these kinds or related kinds, for if it possessed
only one of these kinds, all the other kinds would have to be actualized by
themselves without a cause. It is not permissible to say: The only condition for
the agent is that it exists as acting with an absolute action, not with a
specified kind of action; for, in that case, any existent whatever would be able
to perform any act whatever and what exists would be mixed;’ besides, the
absolute, that is the universal, existent stands nearer to non-existence than
the real individual existent. So those who denied the theory of universals
denied the belief in a universal existent and in a universal becoming , whereas
the champions of this theory regarded them as something midway between being and
non-being; but if this were the case, it would follow that the universals could
be a cause of existents. The proposition that from the one only one act can
proceed is more evident for the empirical than for the divine world. For
knowledge multiplies through the multiplying of the objects of thought in the
world, since the intellect knows these objects in the way that they exist in the
world, and they are the cause of its knowledge. It is not possible for many
objects of thought to be known through one act of thought, nor can one act of
thought produce many effects in the empirical world, e.g. the knowledge of the
artisan which produces, for example, a cupboard is different from the knowledge
which produces a chair. But eternal wisdom and the eternal agent differ in this
matter from temporal knowledge and the temporal agent.
If
I were asked ‘what is your own point of view in this question? You have denied
Avicenna’s theory of the cause of plurality, but what do you say yourself? For
it has been pointed out that the different schools of philosophy have three
different answers to this question; that the plurality comes only through
matter; that the plurality comes only through instruments; that the plurality
comes through mediators. And it is said of the Peripatetics that they accept the
theory which makes mediation the cause of plurality’-I cannot give in this
book an answer to this question supported by a demonstrative proof. We find,
however, neither in Aristotle nor in any of the known Peripatetics this theory
which is ascribed to them, with the exception of Porphyry, the Tyrian, the
author of the Introduction to Logic, and
he is not among the most subtle of philosophers My opinion is that according to the principles of the
Peripatetics the cause of plurality is a combination of three factors, the
intermediates, the dispositions, and the instruments; and we have already
explained how all these depend on the Monad and refer to it, for each of them
exists through an absolute unity which is the cause of plurality. For it seems
that the cause of the plurality of the separate intellects is the difference in
their natures, by which they receive the knowledge they gain of the First
Principle and which acquire from the First Principle a unity which by itself is
one single act, but which becomes many through the plurality of the recipients,
just as there are many deputies under the power of a king and many arts under
one art. This we shall examine in another place, and if some part of it becomes
clear it will suffice; otherwise we must take refuge in revelation. In so far as
the differences depend on differences between the four causes, the question is
clear. For the differentiation of the spheres arises from the differences of
their movers, of their forms, of their matter, supposing they have matter,’
and of their acts which serve a special end in the world, even if the
philosophers did not believe that these spheres exist for the sake of these acts
As to the differences which arise primarily in the sublunary world in the
elements, as for instance the differences between fire and earth, and in short
the opposites, they are based on the differentiation of matter and on their
varying distances from their movers, which are the heavenly bodies. As to the
difference between the two supreme movements, one of which is the agent of
generation and the other the agent of corruption, they depend on the
differentiation of the heavenly bodies and their motions, as is proved in the
book On Generation and Corruption. For
the difference which arises from the heavenly bodies resembles the difference
which arises from the difference in the instruments. To sum up: the factors for
the origination of plurality from the one Agent are three, according to
Aristotle, and he refers to the One in the sense mentioned above, namely, that
the One is the cause of the plurality. In the sublunary world the differences
arise from the four causes, that is to say, the difference of the agents, the
matter, the instruments, and the intermediaries which transmit the acts of the
First Agent without its direct interference, and those intermediaries are very
similar to the instruments. And an example of the differentiation which arises
through the difference of the recipients, and out of the fact that certain
differentiated things cause others, is colour. For the colour which arises in
the air differs from the colour in the body, and the colour in the faculty of
sight, i.e. in the eye, from the colour in the air, and the colour in the common
internal sense from the colour in the eye, and the colour in the imagination
from the colour in the common internal sense, and the colour in the memorative
and retentive faculty from the colour in the imagination; and all this has been
explained in the book of psychology.
Ghazali
says:
We say: Mankind is divided into two categories; one, the men of truth who have acknowledged that the world has become and know by necessity that what has become does not become by itself but needs a creator, and the reasonableness of their view lies in their affirmation of a creator; the other, the materialists, believe the world, in the state in which it exists,, to be eternal and do not attribute a creator to it, and their doctrine is intelligible, although their proof shows its inanity. But as to the philosophers, they believe the world to be eternal and still attribute a creator to it. This theory is self-contradictory and needs no refutation.
I
say:
The
theory of the philosophers is, because of the factual evidence, more
intelligible than both the other theories together. There are two kinds of
agent: (t) the agent to which the object which proceeds from it is only attached
during the process of its becoming; once this process is finished, the object is
not any more in need of it-for instance, the coming into existence of a house
through the builder; (2) the agent from which nothing proceeds but an act which
has no other existence than its dependence on it. The distinctive mark of this
act is that it is convertible with the existence of its object, i.e. when the
act does not exist the object does not exist, and when the act exists the object
exists-they are inseparable. This kind of agent is superior to the former and is
more truly an agent, for this agent brings its object to being and conserves it,
whereas the other agent only brings its objects to being, but requires another
agent for its further conservation. The mover is such a superior agent in
relation to the moved and to the things whose existence consists only in their
movement. The philosophers, believing that movement is the act of a mover and
that the existence of the world is only perfected through motion, say that the
agent of motion is the agent of the world, and if the agent refrained for only
one moment from its action, the world would be annihilated. They use the
following syllogism: The world is an act, or a thing whose existence is
consequent upon this act. Each act by its existence implies the existence of an
agent. Therefore the world has an agent existing by reason of its existence. The
man who regards it as necessary that the act which proceeds from the agent of
the world should have begun in time says: The world is temporal through an
eternal agent. But the man for whom the act of the Eternal is eternal says: The
world has come into being, from an eternal agent having an eternal act, i.e. an
act without beginning or end; which does, however, not mean that the world is
eternal by itself, as people who call the world eternal imagine it to be.
Ghazali
says, on behalf of the philosophers:
The philosophers might answer: When we affirm that the world has a creator, we do riot understand thereby a voluntary agent who acts after not having acted, as we observe in the various kinds of agents, like tailors, weavers, and builders, but we mean the cause of the world, and we call it the First Principle, understanding by this that there is no cause for its existence, but that it is a cause of the existence of other things; and if we call this principle the Creator, it is in this sense. It is easy to establish by a strict proof an existent for the existence of which there is no cause. For we say that the world and its existents either have a cause or have not. If it has a cause, this cause itself either has or has not a cause, and the same can be said about the latter cause, and either we go on ad infinitum in this way, and this is absurd, or we arrive at a last term, and this end is the First Cause, which has no cause for its existence and which we call First Principle. And if the world existed by itself without cause, then it would be clear what the First Principle is, for we only mean by it an existent without a cause and which is necessarily eternal. However, it is not possible that the First Principle should be the heavens, for there are many of these and the proof of unity contradicts this, and its impossibility is shown on examination of the attribute of the principle. Nor can it be said that one single heaven, or one single body, the sun or any other body, can be the First Principle; for all these are bodies, and body is composed of matter and form, and the First Principle cannot be composite, as is clear on a second examination. Our intention is to show that an existent which has no cause is eternal by necessity and by universal consent, and only about its qualities is there a divergence of opinion. And this is what we mean by a first principle.
I
say:
This
argument carries a certain conviction, but still it,is not true. For the term
`cause' is attributed equivocally to the four causesagent, form, matter, and
end. Therefore if this were the answer of the philosophers, it would be
defective. For if they were asked which cause they mean by their statement that
the world has a first cause, and if they answered, `That agent whose act is
uncreated and everlasting, and whose object is identical with its act', their
answer would be true according to their doctrine; for against this conception,
in the way we expounded it, there is no objection. But if they answered `The
formal cause', the objection would be raised
whether they supposed the form of the world to subsist by itself in the
world, and if they answered, `We mean a form separate from matter', their
statement would be in harmony with their theory; but if they answered, `We mean
a form in matter', this would imply that the First Principle was not something
incorporeal; and this does not accord with philosophical doctrine. Further, if
they said, `It is a cause which acts for an end', this again would agree with
the philosophical doctrine. As you see, this statement is capable of many
interpretations, and how can it be represented there as an answer of the
philosophers?
And as to Ghazali's
words
We call it the First Principle, understanding by this that there is no cause for its existence, but that it is a cause for the existence of other things.
This
again is a defective statement, for this might be said also of the first sphere,
or of heaven in its entirety, or generally of any kind of existents which could
be supposed to exist without a cause; and between this and the materialistic
theory' there is no difference.
And
as to Ghazali's words:
It is easy to establish by a strict proof an existent for the existence of which there is no cause.
This
again is a defective statement, for the causes must be specified, and it must be
shown that each kind has an initial term without cause-that is, that the agents
lead upwards to a first agent, the formal causes to a first form, the material
causes to a first matter, and the final causes to a first end. And then it must
still be shown that these four ultimate causes lead to a first cause. This is
not clear from the statement as he expresses it here.
And in the
same way the statement in which he brings a proof for the existence of a first
cause is defective, i.e. his statement:
For we soy that the world and its existents either have a cause or have not ....
For
the term `cause' is used in an equivocal way. And similarly the infinite regress
of causes is according to philosophical doctrine in one way impossible, in
another way necessary; impossible when this regress is essential and in a
straight line and the prior cause is a condition of the existence of the
posterior, not impossible when this regress is accidental and circular, when the
prior is not a condition for the posterior and when there exists an essential
first cause-for instance, the origin of rain from a cloud, the origin of a cloud
from vapour, the origin of vapour from rain. And this is according to the
philosophers an eternal circular process, which of necessity, however,
presupposes a first cause. And similarly the coming into existence of one man
from another is an eternal process, for in such cases the existence of the prior
is not a condition for the existence of the posterior; indeed, the destruction
of some of them is often a necessary condition. This kind of cause leads upwards
to an eternal first cause which acts in each individual member of the series of
causes at the moment of the becoming of its final effect; for instance, when
Socrates engenders Plato, the ultimate mover, according to the philosophers, is
the highest sphere, or the soul, or the intellect,z or all together, or God the
Creator. And therefore Aristotle says that a man and the sun together engender a
man, and it is clear that the sun leads upwards to its mover and its mover to
the First Principle. Therefore the past man is not a condition for the existence
of the future man. Similarly, when an artisan produces successively a series of
products of craftsmanship with different instruments, and produces these
instruments through instruments and the latter again through other instruments,
the becoming of these instruments one from another is something accidental, and
none of these instruments is a condition for the existence of the product of
craftsmanship except the firsts instrument which is in immediate contact with
the work produced . Now the father is necessary for the coming into existence of
the son in the same way as the instrument which comes into immediate contact
with the product of craftsmanship is necessary for its coming into existence.
And the instrument with which this instrument is produced will be necessary for
the production of this instrument, but will not be necessary for the production
of the product of craftsmanship unless accidentally. Therefore sometimes, when
the posterior instrument is produced from the matter of the anterior, the
destruction of the anterior is a condition for the existence of the posterior,
for instance, when a man comes into being from a man who has perished, through
the latter becoming first a plant, then sperm or menstrual blood? And we have
already discussed this problem. Those, however, who regard an infinite series of
essential causes as possible are materialists, and he who concedes this does not
understand the efficient cause. And about the efficient cause there is no
divergence of opinion among philosophers.
And as to Ghazali's
words:
And if the world existed by itself without cause, then it would be clear what the First Principle is.
He
means that the materialists as well as others acknowledge a first cause which
has no cause, and their difference of opinion concerns only this principle, for
the materialists say that it is the highest sphere and the others that it is a
principle beyond the sphere and that the sphere is an effect; but these others
are divided into two parties, those who say that the sphere is an act that has a
beginning and those who say that it is an eternal act. And having declared that
the acknowledgement of a first cause is common to the materialists as well as to
others, Ghazali says:
However, it is not possible that the First Principle should be the heavens, for there are many of these and the proof of unity contradicts this;
Meaning
that from the order of the universe it is evident that its directing principle
is one, just as it appears from the order in an army that its leader is one,
namely, the commander of the army. And all this is true.
And as to Ghazali's
words:
Nor can it be said that one single heaven or one single body, the sun or any other body, can be the First Principle; for all these are bodies, and body is composed of matter and form, and the first body cannot be composite.
I
say:
The
statement that each body is composed of matter and form does not accord with the
theory of the philosophers (with the exception of Avicenna) about the heavenly
body, unless one uses `matter' here equivocally. For according to the
philosophers everything composed of matter and form has a beginning, like the
coming into existence of a house and a cupboard; and the heavens, according to
them, have not come into existence in this sense, and so they called them
eternal, because their existence is coeternal with the First Principle. For
since according to them the cause of corruption is matter, that which is
incorruptible could not possess matter, but must be a simple entity. If
generation and corruption were not found in sublunary bodies, we should not draw
the conclusion that they were composed of matter and form, for the fundamental
principle is that body is a single essence not less in its existence than in
perception, and if there were no corruption of sublunary bodies, we should judge
that they were simple and that matter was body. But the fact that the body of
the heavens does not suffer corruption shows that its matter is actual
corporeality. And the soul which exists in this body does not exist in it
because this body requires, as the bodies of animals do, the soul for its
continuance, nor because it is necessary for the existence of this body to be
animated, but only because the superior must of necessity exist in the condition
of the superior and the animate is superior to the inanimate. According to the
philosophers there is no change in the heavenly bodies, for they do not possess a potency in
their substance. They therefore need not have matter in the way the generable
bodies need this, but they are either, as Themistius affirms, forms,z or possess
matter in an equivocal sense of the word. And I say that either the matters of
the heavenly bodies are identical with their souls, or these matters are
essentially alive, not alive through a life bestowed on them.
Ghazali
says:
To this there are two answers. The first is that it can be said: Since it follows from the tenets of your school that the bodies of the world are eternal, it must follow too that they have no cause, and your statement that on a second examination such a conclusion must be rejected will itself be rejected when we discuss God's unity and afterwards the denial of attributes to God.
I
say:
Ghazali means that since they cannot
prove the unity of the First Principle, and since they cannot prove either that
the One cannot be body-for since they cannot deny the attributes, the First
Principle must, according to them, be an essence endowed with attributes, and
such an essence must be a body or a potency in a body4-it follows that the First
Principle which has no cause is the celestial bodies. And this conclusion is
valid against those who might argue in the way he says the philosophers argue.
The philosophers, however, do not argue thus, and do not say that they are
unable to prove the unity and incorporeality of the First Principle. But this
question will be discussed later.
Ghazali
says:
The second answer, and it is the answer proper to this question, is to say: it is established as a possibility that these existents can have a cause, but perhaps for this cause there is another cause, and so on ad infinitum. And you have no right to assert that to admit an infinite series of causes is impossible, for we ask you, `Do you know this by immediate necessary intuition or through a middle term?' Any claim to intuition is excluded, and any method of deductive proof is forbidden to you, since you admit celestial revolutions without an initial term; and if you permit a coming into existence for what is without ends it is not impossible that the series should consist of causal relations and have as a final term an effect which has no further effect, although in the other direction the series does not end in a cause which has no anterior cause,' just as the past has a final term, namely the everchanging present, but no first term. If you protest that the past occurrences do not exist together at one moment or at certain moments, and that what does not exist cannot be described as finite or infinite, you are forced to admit this simultaneous existence for human souls in abstraction from their bodies; for they do not perish, according to you, and the number of souls in abstraction from their bodies is infinite, since the series of becoming from sperm a to man and from man to sperm a is infinite, and every man dies, but his soul remains and is numerically different from the soul of any man who dies before, simultaneously, or afterwards, although all these souls are one in species. Therefore at any moment there is an infinite number of souls in existence.
If you object that souls are not joined to each other, and that they have no order, either by nature or by position, and that you regard only those infinite existents as impossible which have order in space, like bodies which have a spatial order of higher and lower, or have a natural order like cause and effect, and that this is not the case with souls; we answer: 'This theory about position does not follow any more than its contrary;' you cannot regard one of the two cases as impossible without involving the other, for where is your proof for the distinction? And you cannot deny that this infinite number of souls must have an order, as some are prior to others and the past days and nights are infinite. If we suppose the birth of only one soul every day and night, the sum of souls, born in sequence one after the other, amounts at the present moment to infinity.
The utmost you can say about the cause is that its priority to the effect exists by nature, in the way that its superiority to the effect is a matter of essence and not of space. But if you do not regard an infinite sequence as impossible for real temporal priority, it cannot be impossible for natural essential priority either. But what can the philosophers mean when they deny the possibility of an infinite spatial superposition of bodies, but affirm the possibility of an infinite temporal sequence? Is this theory not really an inept theory without any foundation?
I
say:
As to Ghazali's words:
But perhaps for this cause there is another cause and so on ad infinitum . . . and any method of deductive proof is forbidden to you, since you admit celestial revolutions without an initial term: To this difficulty an answer was given above, when we said that the philosophers do not allow an infinite causal series, because this would lead to an effect without a cause, but assert that there is such a series accidentally from an eternal cause-not, however, in a straight line, nor simultaneously, nor in infinite matters, but only as a circular process.
What
he says here about Avicenna, that he regarded an infinite number of souls as
possible and that infinity is only impossible in what has a position, is not
true' and no philosopher has said it; indeed, its impossibility is apparent from
their general proof which we mentioned, and no conclusion can be drawn against
them from this assumption of an actual infinity of souls. Indeed, those who
believed that the souls are of a certain number through the number of bodies and
that they are individually immortal profess to avoid this assumption through the
doctrine of the transmigration of souls.
And as to Ghazali's
words:
But what can the philosophers mean when they deny the possibility of an infinite spatial superposition of bodies, but affirm the possibility of an infinite temporal sequence?
I
say:
The
difference between these two cases is very clear to the philosophers, for from
the assumption of infinite bodies existing simultaneously there follows an
infinite totality and an actual infinite, and this is impossible. But time has
no position, and from the existence of an infinite temporal series of bodies no
actual infinite follows.
Ghazali
says on behalf of the philosophers:
The philosophers might say: The strict proof of the impossibility of an infinite causal series is as follows: each single cause of a series is either possible in itself or necessary; if it is necessary, it needs no cause, and if it is possible, then the whole series needs a cause additional to its essence, a cause standing outside the series.
I
say:
The
first man to bring into philosophy the proof which Ghazali
gives here as a philosophical one, was Avicenna, who regarded this proof as
superior to those given by the ancients, since he claimed it to be based on the
essence of the existent, whereas the older proofs are based on accidents
consequent on the First Principle! This proof Avicenna took from the
theologians, who regarded the dichotomy of existence into possible and necessary
as self-evident, and assumed that the possible needs an agent and that the world
in its totality, as being possible, needs an agent of a necessary existence.
This was a theory of the Mu'tazilites before the Ash'arites,s and it is
excellent, and the only flaw in it is their assumption that the world in its
totality is possible, for this is not self-evident. Avicenna wanted to give a
general sense to this statement, and he gave to the `possible' the meaning of
`what has a cause',' as Ghazali relates. And
even if this designation can be conceded, it does not effect the division which
he had in view. For a primary division of existence into what has a cause and
what has no cause is by no means self-evident. Further, what has a cause can be
divided into what is possible and what is necessary. If we understand by
`possible' the truly possible we arrive at the necessary-possibles and not at
the necessary which has no cause; and if we understand by `possible' that which
has a cause and is also necessary, there only follows from this that what has a
cause has a cause and we may assume that this cause has a cause and so
ad infinitum. We do not therefore arrive at an existent without cause-for
this is the meaning of the expression `entity of a necessary existence'-unless
by the possible which Avicenna assumes as the opposite of what has no cause we
understand the truly possible, for in these possibles there cannot exist an
infinite series of causes. But if by `possible' is meant those necessary things
which have a cause, it has not yet been proved that their infinite number is
impossible, in the way it is evident of the truly possible existents, and it is
not yet proved that there is a necessary existent which needs a cause, so that
from this assumption one can arrive at a necessary entity existing without a
cause. Indeed, one has to prove that what applies to the total causal series of
possible entities applies also to the total causal series of necessary
existents.
Ghazali
says:
The terms `possible' and `necessary' are obscure, unless one understands by `necessary' that which has no cause for its existence and by `possible' that which has a cause for its existence;' then, by applying the terms as defined to the statement, we say: Each member of a causal series is possible in this sense of `possible', namely, that it has a cause additional to its essence, but the series as a whole is not possible in this sense of `possible'.'' And if anything else is meant by `possible', it is obscure. If it is objected that this makes the necessary existent consist of possible existents and this is impossible, we answer: By defining `necessary' and `possible' as we have done, you have all that is needed and we do not concede that it is impossible. To say that it is impossible would be like saying that it is impossible that what is eternal should be made up of what is temporal, for time according to you philosophers is eternal, but the individual circular movements are temporal and have initial terms, though collectively they have no initial term; therefore, that which has no initial term consists of entities having initial terms, and it is true of the single units that they have a beginning, but not true of them collectively. In the same way it can be said of each term of the causal series that it has a cause, but not of the series as a whole. And so not everything that is true of single units is true of their collectivity, for it is true of each single unit that it is one and a portion and a part, but not true of their collectivity; and any place on the earth which we choose is illuminated by the sun by day and is dark by night, and according to the philosophers each unit has begun, but not the whole. Through this it is proved that the man who admits temporal entities without a beginning, namely, the forms of the four elements,' cannot at the same time deny an infinity of causes, and we conclude from this that because of this difficulty there is no way in which they can prove the First Principle, and their dichotomy is purely arbitrary.
I
say:
The
assumption of infinite possible causes implies the assumption of a possible
without an agent, but the assumption of infinite necessary entities having
causes implies only that what was assumed to have a cause has none, and this
argument is true with the restriction that the impossibility of infinite
entities which are of a possible nature does not involve the impossibility of
infinite necessary entities. If one wanted to give a demonstrative form to the
argument used by Avicenna one should say: Possible existents must of necessity
have causes which precede them, and if these causes again are possible it
follows that they have causes and that there is an infinite regress; and if
there is an infinite regress there is no cause, and the possible will exist
without a cause, and this is impossible. Therefore the series must end in a
necessary cause, and in this case this necessary cause must be necessary through
a cause or without a cause, and if through a cause, this cause must have a cause
and so on infinitely; and if we have an infinite regress here, it follows that
what was assumed to have a cause has no cause, and this is impossible. Therefore
the series must end in a cause necessary without a cause, i.e. necessary by
itself, and this necessarily is the necessary existent. And when these
distinctions are indicated, the proof becomes valid . But if this argument is
given in the form in which Avicenna gives it, it is invalid for many reasons,
one of which is that the term `possible' used in it is an equivocal one and that
in this argument the primary dichotomy of all existents into what is possible
and what is not possible, i.e. this division comprising the existent qua
existent, is not true.
And as to Ghazali's
words in his refutation of the philosophers:
We say: Each member of a causal series is possible in this sense of `possible', namely, that it has a cause additional to its essence, but the whole series is not possible in this sense of `possible'.
I
say:
Ghazali means that when the
philosophers concede that they understand by `possible existent' that which has
a cause and by `necessary existent'
that which has no cause, it can be said to them `According to your own
principles the existence of an infinite causal series is not impossible, and the
series in its totality will be a necessary existent,' for according to their own
principles the philosophers admit that different judgements apply to the part
and to the whole collectively. This statement is erroneous for many reasons, one
of which is that the philosophers, as was mentioned before, do not allow an
infinite series of essential causes, whether causes and effects of a possible'
or of a necessary nature, as we have shown. The objection which can be directed
against Avicenna is that when you divide existence into possible and necessary
and identify the possible existent with that which has a cause and the necessary
existent with that which has none, you can no longer prove the impossibility of
the existence of an infinite causal series, for from its infinite character it
follows that it is to be classed with existents which have no cause and it must
therefore be of the nature of the necessary existent, especially as, according
to him and his school, eternity can
consist of an infinite series of causes each of which is temporal. The fault in
Avicenna's argument arises only from his division of the existent into that
which has a cause and that which has none. If he had made his division in the
way we have done, none of these objections could be directed against him. And Ghazali's
statement that the ancients, since they admit an infinite number of circular
movements, make the eternal consist of an infinite number of entities, is false.
For the term `eternal', when it is attributed both to this infinite series and
to the one eternal being, is used equivocally.'
And as to the
words of Ghazali:
If it is objected that this makes the necessary existent consist of possible existents, and this is impossible, we answer: By defining `necessary' and `possible' as we have done you have all that is needed, and we do not concede that it is impossible.
I
say:
Ghazali means that the philosophers
understand by `necess: that which has no cause and by `possible' that which has
a cause, and that he, Ghazali, does not regard
it as impossible that what has no cause should consist of an infinite number of
causes, because, if he conceded that this was impossible, he would be denying
the possibility of an infinity of causes, whereas he only wants to show that the
philosophers' deduction of a necessary being is a petitio principii.`
Then Ghazali
says:
To say that it is impossible would be like saying that it is impossible that what is eternal should be made up of what is temporal, for time, according to you philosophers, is eternal, but the individual circular movements are temporal and have initial terms; therefore that which has no initial term consists of entities having initial terms, and it is true of the single units that they have a beginning, but not true of them collectively. In the same way it can be said of each term of the causal series that it has a cause, but not of the series as a whole. And so not everything that is true of single units is true of their collectivity, for it is true of each single unit that it is one and a portion and a part, but not true of their collectivity.
I
say:
Ghazali means that it is not impossible
that what has no cause should consist of infinite effects in the way the
eternal, according to the philosophers, consists of temporal entities, which are
infinite in number. For time, according to the philosophers, is eternal, and
consists of limited temporal parts, and likewise the movement of heaven is
eternal according to the philosophers, and the circular movements of which it
consists are infinite. And the answer is that the existence of an eternal
consisting of temporal parts, in so far as they are infinite in number, is not a
philosophical principle; on the contrary they deny it most strongly, and only
the materialists affirm it. For the sum must consist either of a finite number
of transitory members or of an infinite number. If the former is the case, it is
generally admitted that the members must also be generically transitory. For the
latter case there are two theories. The materialists believe that the totality
is of a possible nature and that the collectivity must be eternal and without a
cause . The philosophers admit this infinity and believe that such genera,
because they consist of possible transitory constituents, must necessarily have
an external cause, lasting and eternal, from which they acquire their eternity .
It is not true either, as Ghazali seems to
imply, that the philosophers believe that the impossibility of an infinite
series of causes depends on the impossibility that the eternal should consist of
an infinity of constituents. They affirm that the eternity of these generically
different movements must lead to one single movement, and that the reason why
there exist genera which are
transitory in their individuals, but eternal as a whole, is that there is an
existent, eternal partly and totally, and this is the body of the heavens. The
infinite movements are generically infinite only because of the one single
continuous eternal movement of the body of the heavens. And only for the mind
does the movement of heaven seem composed of many circular movements. And the
movement of the body of the heavens acquires its eternity-even if its particular
movements are transitory-through a mover which must always move and through a
body which also must always be moved and cannot stop in its motion, as happens
with things which are moved in the sublunary world.
About
genera there are three theories, that of those who say that all genera are
transitory, because the individuals in them are finite, and that of those who
say that there are genera which are eternal and have no first or last term,
because they appear by their nature to have infinite individuals; the latter are
divided into two groups: those, namely the philosophers, who say that such
genera can only be truly said to be everlasting, because of one and the same
necessary cause, without which they would perish on innumerable occasions in
infinite time; and those, namely the materialists, who believe that the
existence of the individuals of these genera is sufficient to make them eternal.
It is important to take note of these three theories, for the whole controversy
about the eternity or non-eternity of the world, and whether the world has an
agent or not, is based on these fundamental propositions. The theologians and
those who believe in a temporal creation of the world are at one extreme, the
materialists at the other, while the philosophers hold an intermediate position.
If
all this is once established, you will see that the proposition that the man who
allows the existence of an infinite series of causes cannot admit a first cause
is false, and that on the contrary the opposite is evident, namely, that the man
who does not acknowledge infinite causes cannot prove the existence of an
eternal first cause, since it is the existence of infinite effects which demands
the necessity of an eternal cause from which the infinite causes acquire their
existence; for if not, the genera, all of whose individuals are temporal, would
be necessarily finite. And in this and no other way can the eternal become the
cause of temporal existents, and the existence of infinite temporal existents
renders the existence of a single eternal first principle necessary, and there
is no God but He.
Ghazali, answering this objection in
the name of the philosophers, says:
The philosophers might say: The circular movements and the forms of the elements do not exist at the present moment; there actually exists only one single form of them, and what does not exist can be called neither finite nor infinite, unless one supposes them to exist in the imagination, and things which are only suppositions in the mind cannot be regarded as impossible, even if certain of these suppositions are supposed to be causes of other suppositions;' for man assumes this only in his imagination, and the discussion refers only to things in reality, not to things in the mind. The only difficulty concerns the souls of the dead and, indeed, some philosophers have arrived at the theory that there is only one eternal soul before it is united with bodies, and that after its separation from the bodies it becomes one again, so that it has no numerical quantity and can certainly not be called infinite. Other philosophers have thought that the soul follows from the constitution of the body, that death is nothing but the annihilation of the soul, and that the soul cannot subsist by itself without the body. In that case souls have no existence except in respect of the living, and the living are beings limited in number, and their finitude is not denied, and those that have ceased to exist cannot be qualified at all, either by finitude or by infinity, except when they are supposed to exist in imagination.
Then Ghazali
says:
We answer: This difficulty about the souls has come to us from Avicenna and Farabi and the most acknowledged philosophers, since they concluded that the soul was a substance subsistent by itself; and this is also the view taken by Aristotle and by the commentators on the ancient philosophers. And to those philosophers who turn aside from this doctrine we say: Can you imagine that at each moment something comes into being which will last for ever? A negative answer is impossible, and if they admit this possibility, we say: If you imagine that every day some new thing comes into being and continues to exist, then up to the present moment there will have been an infinite collection of existents and, even if the circular movement itself comes to an end, the lasting and endless existence of what has come into being during its revolution is not impossible. In this way this difficulty is firmly established, and it is quite irrelevant whether this survival concerns the soul of a man or a Jinni, the soul of a devil or an angel, or of any being whatever. And this is a necessary consequence of every philosophical theory which admits an infinity of circular movements.
I
say:
The
answer which lie gives in the name of the philosophers, that the past
revolutions and the past forms of the elements which have come from each others
are non-existent, and that the non-existent can be called neither finite nor
infinite, is not a true one. And as to the difficulty he raises against them as
to their theory about souls, no such theory is held by any philosophers, and the
transference of one problem to another is a sophistical artifice.
Ghazali
says:
The philosophers have two proofs of this. The first is to say, ‘If there were two necessary existents, the species of necessary existence would be attributed to them both. ‘ But what is said to be a necessary existent must either be so through itself, and cannot be imagined to be so through another, or it must be so through a cause, and the essence of the necessary existent will be an effect; and its cause then determines its necessity of existence. ‘ ‘But’, say the philosophers, ‘we understand by “necessary existent” only an entity whose existence has no connexion with a cause. ‘ And the philosophers affirm that the species ‘man’ is asserted of Zaid and of Amr and that Zaid is not a man through himself-for in that case Amr would not be a man-but through a cause which makes both him and Amr a man; and the plurality of men arises from the plurality of matter in which humanity inheres, and its inherence in matter is an efficct which does not lie in the essence of humanity. The same is the case with necessary existence in respect to the necessary existent: if it is through itself a necessary existent, it must possess this qualification exclusively, and if it exists because of a cause, it is an effect and cannot be a necessary existent. And from this it is clear that the necessary existent must needs be one.
To this Ghazali
objects and says:
We say: Your statement that the species of necessary existence must belong to the necessary existent either through the necessary existent itself or through a cause is a self-contradictory disjunction, for we have already shown that the expression ‘necessary existence’ is obscure, unless we mean by it the denial of a cause, and so let us rather use the term which is really meant by it and say: To admit two existents without a cause, and without the one’s being a cause of the other, is not impossible. And your statement that what has no cause has none, either because of its own essence or through some cause, is a faulty disjunction, for one does not ask for the cause of a thing which is said to have no cause and to need no cause for its existence. And what sense is there in the statement that what has no cause has no cause either because of its own essence or through a cause? For to say ‘no cause’ is an absolute negation, and an absolute non-entity has no cause, and cannot be said to exist either by its own essence or not by its own essence. But if you mean by ‘necessary existence’ a positive qualification of the necessary existent, besides its being an existent without a cause for its existence, it is quite obscure what this meaning is. But the genuine meaning of this word is the negation of a cause for its existence, and this is an absolute negation about which it cannot be said that it is due to its essence or to a cause, such that the intended proof might be based on the supposition of this disjunction. To regard this as a proof is senseless and has no foundation whatever. On the contrary, we say that the meaning of its necessity is that it has no cause for its existence and no cause for its coming into existence, without there being any cause whatever for this; its being without a cause is, again, not caused by its essence; no, the fact that there is no cause for its existence and no cause for its being, has itself no cause whatsoever. This disjunction cannot be applied even to positive qualities, not to speak of that which is really equivalent to a negation. For suppose one were to say: ‘Black is a colour because of its essence or through a cause, and if it is a colour because of its essence, then red cannot be a colour, and then the species of colouredness can exist only because of the essence of black; if, however, black is a colour because of a cause which has made it a colour, then black can be thought of as being without a colour, i. e. as not having been made a colour by a cause, for a determination added to an essence through a cause can be represented in the imagination as absent, even if it exists in reality. “ ‘But’, it will be objected, ‘this disjunction is false in itself, for one cannot say of black that it is a colour because of its essence, meaning by this that it cannot be through anything but its essence, and in the same way one cannot say that this existent is necessary because of its essence, i. e. that it has no cause because of its own essence, meaning by this that it cannot exist through anything but its essence. ‘
I
say:
This
method of proving the unity of God is peculiar to Avicenna, and is not found in
any of the ancient philosophers; its premisses are common-sense premisses, and
the terms are used in a more or less equivocal way. For this reason many
objections can be urged against it. Still, when those terms and the aim they
intend are properly analysed, this statement comes near to being a proof.
That
this primary disjunction is faulty, as Ghazali
asserts, is not true. He says that the meaning of ‘necessary existent’ is
‘that which has no cause’, and that the statement ‘that what has no cause,
has no cause, either because of its own essence or through another cause’, and
similarly the statement ‘that the necessary existent is a necessary existent,
either because of its own essence or through another cause’ are meaningless
statements. But this is by no means the case. For the meaning of this
disjunction is only whether the necessary existent is such, because of a nature
which characterizes it, in so far as it is numerically one, ‘ or because of a
nature which it has in common with others-for instance, when we say that Amr is
a man because lie is Amr, or because of a nature he has in common with Khalid.
If he is a man because he is Amr, then humanity does not exist in anyone else,
and if he is a man because of a general nature, then he is composed of two
natures, a general one and a special one and the compound is an effect; but the
necessary existent has no cause, and therefore the necessary existent is unique.
And when Avicenna’s statement is given in this form it is true.
And Ghazali’s
words:
and an absolute non-entity has no cause and it cannot be said to exist either by its own essence or not by its own essence form a statement which is not true either. For there are two kinds of negation, the negation of a particular quality, proper to something (and this kind of negation must be understood in respect of the words ‘by its own essence’ used in this statement), and the negation of a quality, not particular to something (and this kind of negation must be understood here in respect of the term ‘cause’). ‘
Ghazali
affirms that this disjunction is not even true of positive qualities and
therefore certainly not of negative and he objects to thus disjunction by giving
as ati example black acid colouredness. And lie means that now we say of black
that it is a colour, either because of its essence or through a cause, neither
alternative can be true, send both are false. For it black were a cause, because
of its essence, red could not he a colour. just as if Amr were a man because of
his essence, Khalid could not be cc man; on the other hand, if black were a
colour through a cause, colour would have to be an addition to its essence, and
an essence which receives an addition can be represented without this addition,
and therefore this assumption would imply that black could be represented
without colouredness, and this is absurd. But this argument, Ghazali
is erroneous and sophistical, because of the equivocation in the terms
‘essence’ and ‘cause’. For if by ‘by its essence’ is understood the
opposite of ‘by accident’, our statement that black is a colour because of
its essence is true, and at the same time it is not impossible that other
things, red for instance, should be colours. And if by ‘cause’, in the
expression that black is a colour through a cause, is understood something
additional to its essence, i. e. that it is a colour through a cause external to
black, it does not follow that black can be represented without colouredness.
For the genus is an addition to the specific quality and the species, and the
species or the specific quality cannot be represented without the genus, and
only an accidental additional quality-not the essential additional quality-can
be represented without the genus. And therefore our statement that black is a
colour either because of its essence or through a cause is a disjunction of
which, indeed, one of the alternatives must be true, i. e. black must be a
colour either by black itself or through an entity additional to black. And this
is what Avicenna meant by his assertion that the necessary existent must be a
necessary existent, either through its own special character or through an
addition which is not peculiar to it; if through the former, there cannot be two
existents which are both necessary existents; if through the latter, both
existents must be composed of a universal and of a peculiar entity, and the
compound is not a necessary existent through itself. And if this is true, the
words of Ghazali : ‘What prevents us from
representing two existents which should both be of a necessary existence?’ are
absurd.
And
if it is objected, ‘You have said that this statement comes near being a
proof, but it seems to be a proper proof’, we answer: We said this only
because this proof seems to imply that the difference between those two assumed
necessary existents must lie either in their particularity, and then they
participate in their specific quality, or in their species, and then they
participate in their generic quality, and both these differences are found only
in compounds, and the insufficiency of this proof lies in this, that it has been
demonstrated that there are existents which are differentiated, although they
are simple and differ neither in species nor individually, namely, the separate
intellects. ‘ However, it appears from their nature that there must be in
their existence a priority and posteriority of rank, for no other
differentiation can be imagined in them. Avicenna’s proof about the necessary
existent must be therefore completed in this way: If there were two necessary
existents, the difference between them must consist either in a numerical
difference, or in a specific difference, or in rank. In the first case they
would agree in species; in the second case in genus, and in both cases the
necessary existent would have to be composite. In the third case, however, the
necessary existent will have to be one, and will be the cause of all the
separate existents. And this is the truth, and the necessary existent is
therefore one. For there is only this tripartite disjunction, two members of
which are false, and therefore the third case, which necessitates the absolute
uniqueness of the necessary existent, is the true one. ‘
Ghazali
says:
The second proof of the philosophers is that they say: If we assumed two necessary existents, they would have to be similar in every way or different. If they were similar in every way, they could not be thought to be a plurality or a duality, since two blacks can have only a duality, when they are in two places, or in one place at different times, for black and movement can only exist in one place and be two at the same time, because they differ essentially. When the two essences, like the two blacks, do not differ and at the same time are simultaneous and in one place, they cannot be thought to be a plurality; if one could speak of two simultaneous blacks as being in the same place, any individual could be said to be two, although not the slightest difference could be perceived between the two. Since they cannot be absolutely similar, they must be different, but they cannot differ in time or in place, and they can therefore only differ in essence. But two things which differ in something must either participate in something or not participate in anything. The latter is impossible, for it would mean that they would participate neither in existence, ‘ nor in the necessity of existence, nor in being subsistent in themselves and not inhering in a substratum. But if they agree in something and differ in something, that in which they agree must be different from that through which they differ; there will therefore be composition in them, and it will be possible to analyse them in thought. But there is no composition in the necessary existent, and just as it cannot be divided quantitatively, so it cannot be analysed by thought either, for its essence is not composed of elements which intellectual analysis could enumerate. ‘ The words ‘animal’ and ‘rational’, for instance, mean that which constitutes the essence of man, namely, animal and rational, and what is meant by the word ‘animal’ when one speaks of a man is different from what is meant by ‘rational’, and therefore man is composed of parts which are ordered in the definition by words which indicate these parts, and the term ‘man’ is applied to the whole of them. ‘ This composition, however, cannot be imagined in the necessary existent, while duality cannot be imagined except in this way.
The answer is that we concede that duality can only be imagined where there is a differentiation, and that in two things, similar in every way, no difference can be imagined. But your statement that this kind of composition is impossible in the First Principle is a mere presumption, and where is your proof of it?
Let us now treat this problem in detail. It belongs to their well-known theories that the First Principle can as little be analysed intellectually as divided quantitatively, and on this fundamental truth, according to the philosophers, the uniqueness of God must be based.
I
say:
Ghazali does not know the mistake which
is in this second proof, and he begins to discuss with the philosophers the
question to which they give a negative answer, namely, if one may introduce a
plurality into the definition of the necessary existent. He wants to consider
this problem in detail, since the Ash’arites allow a plurality in God,
regarding Him as an essence with attributes. ‘ The mistake in this second
proof is that two different things can be essentially different and have nothing
in common but their name, in the case where they have no common genus, either
proximate or remote, for instance, the term ‘body’, attributed by the
philosophers to both the body of the heavens and the transitory body, and the
term ‘intellect’ attributed to the intellect of man and the separate
intellects, and the term ‘existent’ attributed to transitory things and to
eternal. Such terms must be regarded as equivocal rather than as univocal, and
therefore it does not follow that things which are differentiated must be
composite. And since Ghazali, in his answer to
this proof of the philosophers, limits himself in the way he has indicated, he
begins first by stating their theory of God’s unity and then tries to refute
the philosophers.
Ghazali,
expounding the philosophical theory, says:
For the philosophers assert that God’s unity can only be perfected by establishing the singleness of God’s essence in every way, and by the denial of any possible plurality in Him. Now plurality can belong to things in five ways. ‘
First, to what can undergo division actually or in imagination, and therefore the single body is not absolutely one-it is one through the continuity which exists in it, which can suffer a decrease and can be quantitatively divided in imagination. This is impossible in the First Principle.
Secondly: a thing may be divided by thought, not quantitatively, into two different concepts, as for instance the division of body into matter and form, for although neither matter nor form can subsist separately, they are two different things in definition and in reality, and it is by their composition that a unity results, namely body. This also must be denied of God, for God cannot be a form or a matter in a body, or be the compound of both. There are two reasons why God cannot be their compound, first because this compound can be divided into quantitative parts, actually or in imagination, secondly, because this compound can be divided conceptually into form and matter, and God cannot be matter, because matter needs a form, and the necessary existent is self-sufficient in every respect and its existence cannot be conjoined with the condition of something else besides it, and God cannot be form, because form needs matter.
Thirdly: the plurality through attributes implied in knowledge, power, and will; if these attributes had a necessary existence, the essence and these attributes would participate in necessary existence and the necessary existent must be a plurality, and its uniqueness would be denied.
Fourthly: the rational plurality which results from the composition of genus and species. For black is black and colour, and blackness is not colouredness for the intellect, but colouredness is a genus, and blackness a specific difference, and therefore black is composed of genus and species; and animality is for the mind something different from humanity, for man is a rational animal, animal is a genus and rational a specific difference, and man is composed of genus and species, and this is a kind of plurality, and the philosophers affirmed that this kind also must be denied of the First Principle.
Fifthly: the plurality which results from the duality of a quiddity and the existence of this quiddity; for man before his existence has a quiddity, and existence occurs to it and enters into relation with it, and in this way the triangle has a quiddity, namely, it is a figure surrounded by three sides, and existence is not a component of this quiddity, and therefore the intellect can perceive the quiddity of man and the quiddity of a triangle without knowing whether they exist in the external world or not. z If existence were a component of the quiddity to which it is added, the fixation of this quiddity in the mind before its existence could not be imagined. Existence stands in a relation to quiddity, whether in a necessary inseparable relation, for instance, heaven, or in an accidental relation occurring after a thing’s non-existence, like the quiddity of man in respect of Zaid or Amr and the quiddity of accidents and forms which occur. ‘ And the philosophers affirm that this kind of plurality also must be denied of the First Principle. They say that the First Principle has no quiddity to which existence is joined, but existence is necessary to it, as is quiddity to the other entities. Therefore necessary existence is at once a quiddity, a universal reality and a real nature, in the same way as a man, a tree, and heaven are quiddities. For if the necessary existent needed a quiddity for its existence, it would be consequent on this essence and would not constitute it, and the consequent is something secondary and an effect, so that the necessary existent would be an effect, and that would be in opposition to its being necessary.
I
say:
These arc the
theories of the philosophers which Ghazali
mentions on the subject of their denial of plurality in the Monad. Then he
begins to show how they contradict themselves on this question. We must now
first examine these statements which he ascribes to them, and explain the degree
of consent they reach; we shall then investigate the contradictions of the
philosophers which he mentions, and his methods of opposing them on this
problem.
The
first kind of division which, according to Ghazali,
the philosophers deny of the First Principle, is the quantitative division,
either in supposition or in reality. Everyone who believes that the First
Principle is not a body, whether he believes that a body is composed of atoms or
not, agrees about this. The proof of this is that the First Principle is not a
body, and its discussion will follow.
The
second kind is the qualitative division, like the division of body into matter
and form, and this according to the doctrine of those, namely, the philosophers,
who believe that body is composed of matter and form and this is not the place
to discuss the truth of either of these theories. This division also is denied
of the First Principle by everyone who believes that the First Principle is not
body. As to the denial of the corporeality of the First Principle in so far as
it is essentially a necessary existent, the discussion of this will follow
later, when we give a complete account of the whole argument used in this
matter. For as to Ghazali’s words that the
necessary existent does not need another, i. e. it does not consist of anything
else, but that body consists of form and matter and neither of them are
necessary existents, for form cannot dispense with matter and matter cannot
dispense with form-there is here a problem; for according to the philosophers
the body of the heavens is not composed of matter and form, but is simple, and
it has sometimes been thought that it is a necessary existent by its own
essence; but this problem will be treated later, and I do not know of any
philosopher who has believed that the body of the heavens is composed of matter
and form, with the sole exception of Avicenna. We have already spoken on this
question in another place, and shall discuss it still later on.
The
third kind is the denial of the plurality of attributes in the necessary
existent, for if these attributes were of a necessary existence, the necessary
existent would be more than one, since the essence also is a necessary existent.
And if the attributes were caused by- the essence, they could not be necessary
existents, and attributes of the necessary existent would not be necessary
existents, otherwise the term ‘necessary existent’ would comprise the
necessary existent and that which is not a necessary existent, and this is
impossible and absurd. And this is a proof which comes very near to being an
absolute truth, when it is conceded that the ‘necessary existent’ must
indicate an immaterial existent, and in such existents, which subsist by
themselves without being bodies, there cannot be imagined essential attributes
of which their essence is constituted, not to speak of attributes which are
additional to their essence, that is, the so-called accidents, for when
accidents are imagined to be removed, the essence remains, which is not the case
with the essential attributes. And therefore it is right to attribute essential
attributes to their subject, since they constitute its identity, but it is not
right to attribute non-essential attributes to it, except through derivative
words, for we do not say of a man that he is knowledge, but we only say that he
is an animal and that he is knowing;; however, the existence of such attributes
in what is incorporeal is impossible, since the nature of these attributes is
extraneous to their subject, and for this reason they are called accidents and
are distinct from what is attributed essentially to the subject, be it a subject
in the soul or in the external world. If it is objected that the philosophers
believe that there are such attributes in the soul, since they believe that the
soul can perceive, will, and move, although at the same time they hold that the
soul is incorporeal, we answer that they do not mean that these attributes are
additional to the essence, but that they are essential attributes, and it is of
the nature of essential attributes not to multiply the substratum which actually
supports them; they are a plurality only in the sense that the thing defined
becomes a plurality through the parts of the definitions, that is, they are only
a subjective plurality in the mind according to the philosophers, not an actual
plurality outside the soul. For instance, the definition of man is ‘rational
animal’, but reason and life are not actually distinguishable from each other
outside the soul in the way colour and shape are. And therefore he who concedes
that matter is not a condition for the existence of the soul must concede that
in the separate existences there is a real oneness existing outside the soul,
although this oneness becomes a plurality through definition . This is the
doctrine of the Christians concerning the three hypostases in the divine Nature.
They do not believe that they are attributes additional to the essence, but
according to them they are only a plurality in the definition-they are a
potential, not an actual, plurality. Therefore they say that the three are one,
i. e. one in act and three in potency. We shall enumerate later the
reprehensible consequences and absurdities which arise from the doctrine that
the First Principle possesses attributes additional to His essence.
The
fourth kind of plurality is that which occurs to a thing because of its genus
and specific difference; this plurality comes very near to that which belongs to
a thing because of its matter and form, for there are only definitions for that
which is composed of matter and form, and not for simple, non-compound things,
and nobody need disagree about denying a plurality through definition to the
First Principle.
The
fifth kind of plurality is the plurality of essence and existence. Existence in
the nature of things is a logical concept which affirms the conformity of a
thing outside the soul with what is inside the soul. Its meaning is synonymous
with the true, and it is this that is meant by the copula in categorical
propositions. The term ‘existence’ is used in two senses; the first
synonymous with the true, when we ask, for instance, if something exists or not,
or whether a certain thing has such and such a quality or not. The second sense
stands in relation to the existing things as their genus, in the way the
existent is divided into the ten categories, and into substance and accident.
When by existent is understood the true, there is no plurality outside the souks
when by existent is understood what is understood by entity and thing,
the term ‘existent’ is attributed essentially to God and analogically
to all other things in the way warmth is attributed to fire and to all warm
things? This is the theory of the philosophers.
But
Ghazali based his discussion on the doctrine of
Avicenna, and this is a false doctrine, for Avicenna believed that existence is
something additional to the essence outside the soul and is like an accident of
the essence. And if existence were a condition for the being of the essence and
a condition for the essence of the necessary existent, the necessary existent
would be composed of the conditioning and the conditioned and it would be of a
possible existence. Avicenna affirms also that what exists as an addition to its
essence has a cause. Now, existence for Avicenna is an accident which supervenes
on the essence, and to this Ghazali refers when
he says:
For man before his existence has a quiddity and existence occurs to it and enters into relation with it, and in this way the triangle has a quiddity, namely, it is a figure surrounded by three sides, and existence is not a component of this quiddity, and therefore the intellect can perceive the quiddity of man and the quiddity of a triangle without knowing whether they exist in the exterior world or not.
This
shows that the term ‘existence’ which he uses here is not the term which
signifies the most universal genus of all entities, nor the term which indicates
that a thing exists outside the soul. For the term ‘existence’ is used in
two meanings, the former signifies the true and the latter the opposite of
non-existence, and in this latter sense it is that which is divided into the ten
categories and is like their genus. This essential sense which refers to the
things which exist in the real world outside the soul is prior to the sense it
has in the existents of second intention, ‘ and it is this sense which is
predicated of the ten categories analogically, and it is in this sense that we
say of the substance that it exists by itself and of the accident that it exists
through its existing in the existent which subsists by itself. As to the
existent which has the meaning of the ‘true’, all the categories participate
in it in the same way, and the existent which has the meaning of the ‘true’
is something in the mind, namely that a thing is outside the soul in conformity
with what it is inside the sou1, and the knowledge of this is prior to the
knowledge of its quiddity; that is, knowledge of the quiddity of a thing cannot
be asked for, unless it is known that it exists. ‘ And as to those quiddities
which precede in our minds the knowledge of their existence, they are not really
quiddities, but only nominal definitions, and only when it is known that their
meaning exists outside the soul does it become known that they are quiddities
and definitions. And in this sense it is said in the book of the Categories
that the intelligible universals of things become existent through their
particulars, and that the particulars become intelligible through their
universals. s And it is said in the De
Anima that the faculty by which it is perceived that a thing is a definite
particular and exists is another faculty than the faculty by which the quiddity
of the definite particular is perceived, b and it is in this way that it is said
that particulars exist in the external world and universals in the mind? And
there is no difference in the meaning of the ‘true’, whether it concerns
material existents or separate existents. The theory that existence is an
addition to the quiddity and that the existent in its essence does not subsist
by its-and this is the theory of Avicenna-is a most erroneous theory, for this
would imply that the term ‘existence’ signified an accident outside the soul
common to the ten categories. And then it can be asked about this accident when
it is said to exist, if ‘exist’ is taken here in the meaning of the
‘true’ or whether it is meant that an accident exists in this accident, and
so on ad infinitum, which is absurd,
as we have shown elsewhere. ‘ I believe that it is this meaning of
‘existence’ which Ghazali tried to den) of
the First principle, and indeed in this sense it must be denied of all existents
and a fortiori of the First Principle,
since it is a false theory.
Having
mentioned this sense of unity in the statements of the philosophers, Ghazali
now proceeds to describe . the ways in which they contradict themselves in his
opinion, and lie says:
Now notwithstanding all this, the philosophers affirin of God that He is the First and a principle, an existent, a substance, a monad, that He is eternal, everlasting, knowledge and knower and known, an agent and a creator, that He is endowed with will and power and life, that He is the lover and the beloved, the enjoyer and the enjoyed, that He is generous, and the absolute good, and they believe that all this is meant by the term ‘one’, and does not imply airy plurality. And this indeed is something very wonderful.
Now we must first state their theory clearly in order to understand it well, and then we shall occupy ourselves with its refutation, for it is an absurd undertaking to refute a theory before it is well understood. Now the central point for- the understanding of their doctrine is that they say that the essence of the Principle is one, and the plurality of terms arises only through bringing something in relation to it or through bringing it in relation to something, or through denying something of it; for the negation of something does not cause plurality in that of which it is denied, nor does the establishment of relation produce a plurality. Therefore they do not deny the plurality of the negations and the relations, and it is thus their task to refer all the qualities mentioned to negation and relation.
They say that when God is said to be the First this means a relation to all the existents after Him. When He is said to be a principle, it signifies that the existence of everything else depends on Him and is caused by Him; it means therefore a relation to an effect. And when He is said to exist, it means that He is apprehended, and when He is said to be a substance it means that He is the being of which it is denied that it inheres in a substratum and this is a negation. When He is said to be eternal, it means that His non-existence in the past is denied; and when He is said to be everlasting, it means that His non-existence in the future is denied, and the terms ‘eternal’ and ‘everlasting’ are reduced to an existence not preceded nor followed by a non-existence. When He is said to be a necessary existent, it means that there is no cause for His existence and that He is the cause of everything else, and this is a combination of negation and relation: the denial of a cause for His existence is a negation, and making Him the cause of everything else is a relation.
When He is said to be intellect, this means that He is free from matter and everything free from matter is intellect, i. e. thinks its own substance, is self-conscious, and knows everything else, and the essence of God is such: He is free from matter and therefore-for these two expressions have the same meaning-He is an intellect. When He is said to be knowing, it means that His essence which is intellect has an object of thought, namely His essence, for He is self-conscious and knows His own self, and His essence is the known and the knower for all that is one, since He is the known in so far as He is a quiddity, abstract from matter, not hidden from His essence which is intellect in the sense that it is a quiddity abstract from matter, from which nothing is hidden; and because He thinks His own self, He is knowing, and because He is His own object of thought, He is an object known, and since He thinks through His own essence, not through something additional to His own essence, He is intellect, and it is not impossible that the knower and the thing known should be one, for the knower, when he knows that he knows, knows it because he is a knower, so that knower and known are in a way the same; although our intellect is in this respect different from the intellect of the First Principle, for the intellect of the First Principle is eternally in act, whereas our intellect is sometimes in potency, sometimes in act. And when He is said to be a creator, an agent and an originator and to have the other attributes of action, it means that His existence is eminent, from which the existence of the universe emanates in a necessary emanation, and that the existence of everything derives from Him and is consequent on His existence in the way that light is consequent on the sun and heat consequent on fire. But the relation of the world to God resembles the relation of light to the sun only in this, that both are effects, and not in any other way, for-the sun is not aware of the emanation of light from it, nor fire of the emanation of heat from it; for this is mere nature. But the First is conscious of Himself and is aware that His essence is the principle of everything else, and the emanation of everything which emanates from Him is known to Him, and He is not inattentive to anything that proceeds from Him. Nor can He be compared to one of us who puts himself between a sick man and the sun, for then it is the case that because of him, but not through his choice (although he does it consciously and not unwillingly either), the sick man is protected against the sun’s heat, and it is his body which causes the shadow, but it is his soul, not his body, which knows that the shadow is falling and is pleased about it. But this does not apply to the First: in Him the agent is at the same time the knower and the one that is pleased; that is, He is not unwilling, and He is conscious that His perfection consists in the emanation proceeding from Him. Yes, even if it were possible to assume that the man’s body causing the shadow were identical with the knower of the shadow, who is pleased with it, even then he would not be similar to the First. For the First is both knower and agent, and His knowledge is the principle of His act; and His consciousness of Himself as the principle of the universe is the cause of the emanation of the universe and the existing order; and the existing order is the consequence of the order thought of, in the sense that it occurs through Him and that He is the agent of the universe without there being an addition to His knowledge of the universe, since His knowledge of the universe is the cause of the emanation of the universe from Him, and His knowledge of the universe does not add anything to His self-consciousness, for He could not be self-conscious if He did not know that He is the principle of the universe, the object of His knowledge is in first intention His own essence, and the universe is the object of His knowledge in second intention, ‘ and this is the meaning of His being an agent. And when it is said that He has power, nothing is meant but that He is an agent in the way we have stated, namely, that His existence is the existence from which the powers emanate through the emanation of which the arrangement of the world is ordered in the most perfect way possible in accomplishment and beauty. And when it is said that He is willing, nothing is meant but that He is not inattentive to what emanates from Him and that He is not opposed to it; no, He knows that in the emanation of the universe His own perfection is attained, and it is permissible to say in this sense that He is satisfied, and it is permissible to say of the satisfied that He is willing; and His will is nothing but His very power and His power is nothing but His very knowledge and His knowledge nothing but His very essence, so that everything is reduced to His very essence. For His knowledge of things is not derived from things, for otherwise He would acquire His quality and perfection through another, and this is impossible in the necessary existent. But our knowledge is twofold: partly knowledge of a thing which results from its form like our knowledge of the form of heaven and earth, partly knowledge of our own invention, when we represent in ourselves the form of a thing we do not see and then produce it; in this case the existence of the form is derived from the knowledge and not the knowledge from the existence. Now the knowledge the First has is of the second category, for the representation of the order in Himself is the cause of the emanation of the order from Him. Indeed, if the mere presence of the form of a picture or of writing in our souls were sufficient for the occurrence of this form, then our knowledge would be identical with our power and our wills but through our deficiency our representation does not suffice to produce the form, but we need besides a new act of will which results from our appetitive faculty, so that through these two the power which moves our muscles and our nerves in our organs can enter into motion, and through the movement of our muscles and nerves our hand or any other member can move, and through its movement the pen or any other external instrument can come into motion and through the movement of the pen the matter, e. g. the ink, can move, and so the form is realized which we represented in our souls. Therefore the very existence of this form in our souls is not a power and an act of will; no, in us power lies in the principle which moves our muscles and this form moves the mover which is the principle of the power. But this is not the case with the necessary existent, for He is not composed of bodies from which the powers in His extremities originate, and so His power, His will, His knowledge, and His essence are all one.
When it is said that He is living, nothing is meant but that He is conscious of the knowledge through which the existent which is called His act emanates from Him. For the living is the doer, the perceiver, and the meaning of the term is His essence in relation to His acts in the way we have described, not at all like our life, which can be only perfected through two different faculties from which perception and action result. But His life again is His very essence.
And when it is said that He is generous, what is meant is that the universe emanates from Him, but not for an end which refers to Himself, for generosity is perfected by two conditions: first that the receiver of the benefit has profit of what is given to him, for the giving of something to one who is not in need of it is not called generosity; secondly, that the benefactor is not himself in need of generosity, so that he himself becomes a benefactor through a need he experiences himself, and anyone who is generous out of a desire for praise and approbation or to avoid blame seeks a reward and is not generous. But true generosity belongs to God alone, for He does not seek to avoid blame, nor does He desire a perfection acquired through praise, and the term ‘generosity’ indicates His existence in relation to His act and with the denial of an end, and this does not imply a plurality in His essence.
When He is said to be the absolute good, it means that His existence is free from any imperfection and from any possibility of non-existence, for badness has no essence, but refers to the non-existence of an essence or to the absence of the goodness of the essence. , For existence itself, in so far as it is existence, is good, and therefore this term refers to the negation of the possibility of non-existence and of badness. Sometimes ‘good’ means that which is the cause of the order in things, and the First is the principle of the order of everything and therefore He is good;’ and in this case the term signifies existence in a certain kind of relation.
When He is said to be a necessary existent, this existence is meant with the denial of a cause for His existence and the impossibility of a cause for His non-existence, in the beginning and at the end.
When it is said that He is the lover and the beloved, the enjoyer and the enjoyed, it means that He is every beauty and splendour and perfection, and that He is beloved and desired by the possessor of this perfection and the only meaning of ‘enjoyment’ is the perception of appropriate perfection. If it could be imagined of a single man that he knew his own perfection in comprehending all intelligibles, if he could comprehend them, that he knew the beauty of his own form, the perfection of his power, the strength of his limbs, in short if he perceived in himself the presence of all perfection of which he was capable, he would love his perfection and enjoy it, and his enjoyment would only be incomplete through the possibility of its loss and its diminution, for the joy which refers to the transitory, or to what is feared to be transitory, is not perfect. ‘ But the First possesses the most perfect splendour and the most complete beauty, since all perfection is possible to Him and present in Him, and He perceives this beauty, secure against the possibility of its diminution and loss, and the perfection He possesses is superior to all perfection, and His love and His enjoyment of this perfection are superior to all love and to all enjoyment, and His enjoyment cannot be compared in any way to our enjoyment and is too glorious to be called enjoyment, joy, and delight, for we have no expressions for such concepts, and using these terms metaphorically for Him, we must be conscious of the great difference, just as when we apply to Him metaphorically our terms, ‘willing’, choosing’, ‘acting’, we are convinced of the great distance between His will, power, and knowledge, from our will, power, and knowledge, and it is not impossible that this term ‘enjoyment’ should be regarded as improper and that another term should be used. , What we want to express is that His state is more glorious than the conditions of the angels, and more desirable, and the condition of the angels is more glorious than our condition; and if there were no other joy than in bodily desire and sex, the condition of the ass and the pig would be superior to the state of the angels, but the angels, who are separate from matter, have no other joy than the joy arising from the knowledge of their share in perfection and beauty, the cessation of which is not to be feared. But the joy of the First is superior to the joy of the angels, and the existence of the angels which are intellects separate from matter is possible in its essence and necessary of existence through another, and the possibility of non-existence is a kind of badness and imperfection, and nothing is absolutely free from badness except the First, and He is the absolute good and He possesses the utmost splendour and beauty; further, He is the beloved, whether anyone else loves Him or not, as He is the knower and the known, whether anyone else knows Him or not. And all these concepts refer to His essence and to His perception and to His knowledge of His essence, and the knowledge of His essence is His very essence, for He is pure intellect, and all this leads back to one single notion.
This is the way to set forth their doctrine, and these things can be divided into that which may be believed (but we shall show that according to their own principles they must regard it as untrue) and into that which may not be believed (and we shall show its falsehood). We shall now return to the five classes of plurality and to their claim to deny them, and shall show their inability to establish their proof, and shall treat each question separately.
I
say:
The
greater part of what he mentions in his description of the philosophical
theories about God as being one, notwithstanding the plurality of attributes
ascribed to Him, he has stated accurately, and we shall not argue with him about
it, with the exception of his statement that to Him the designation of
‘intellect’ is a negation; for this is not true-on the contrary it is the
most special appellation for His essence according to the Peripatetics, in
contrast to Plato’s opinion that the intellect is not the First Principle and
that intellect cannot be attributed to the First Principle? Nor is his statement
that in the separate intellects there is potency, non-existence, and badness a
philosophical theory. But we shall now return to his refutations in these five
questions.
Ghazali
says:
The philosophers agree-exactly as do the Mu’tazilites-that it is impossible to ascribe to the First Principle knowledge, power, and will, and they affirm that we have received these terms through the Divine Law, and that they may be used as verbal expressions, but that they refer to one essence as we have explained previously, and that it is not permissible to accept an attribute additional to its essence in the way we may consider, as regards ourselves, our knowledge, power, and will, as attributes of ourselves, additional to our essence. And they affirm that this causes a plurality, because if these attributes are supposed to occur to us in the course of our development, we know that they are additional to our essence, because they constitute new facts; on the other hand, if they are supposed to be simultaneous with our existence without any time-lag, their simultaneity does not prevent them from being an addition to our essence. ; For when one thing is added to another and it is known that they are not identical, it is thought, even if they are simultaneous, that they are two. Therefore the fact that these qualities would be simultaneous with the essence of the First does not prevent them from being extraneous to its essence, and this causes a plurality in the necessary existent, and this is impossible; and therefore they all agree in the denial of the attributes.
I
say:
The
difficulty for the man who denies a plurality of attributes consists in this:
that different attributes are reduced to one essence, so that for instance
knowledge, will, and power would mean one and the same thing and signify one
single essence, and that also knowledge and knower, power and possessing power,
will and willer would have one and the same meaning. The difficulty for the man,
however, who affirms that there exist both an essence and attributes additional
to the essence, consists in this: that the essence becomes a condition for the
existence of the attributes and the attributes a condition for the perfection of
the essence, and that their combination would be a necessary existent, that is,
one single existent in which there is neither cause nor effect. And this latter
difficulty cannot be really solved when it is assumed that there exists an
essentially necessary existent, for this implies that it must be one in every
way and can in no way be composed of the condition and the conditioned and of
cause and effect, for such a composition would have to be either necessary or
possible; (t) if necessary, it would be necessary through another, not through
itself, since it is difficult to assume an eternal compound as existing through
itself, i. e. as not having a cause for its composition, and this is especially
difficult for the man who believes that every accident is temporal, ‘ since
the fact of being a compound would be an eternal accident; (2) if possible, a
cause would be needed to join together the effect and the cause. Now, according
to philosophical principles it is quite impossible that there should be a
compound existing by itself, having eternal attributes, since the composition
would be a condition of its existence; and its parts could not be agents for the
composition, for the composition would have to be a condition for their
existence. Therefore, when the parts of any natural compound are disjoined,
their original name can be only applied to them equivocally, e. g. the term
`hand’, used of the hand which is a part of the living man and the hand which
has been cut off; and every compound is for Aristotle transitory and a fortiori
cannot be without a cause?
But
as to the system of Avicenna, with its division of the necessary existent from
the possible existent, it does not lead to the denial of an eternal compound;
for when we assume that the possible ends in a necessary cause and that the
necessary cause must either have a cause or not, and in the former case must end
in a necessary existent which has no cause, this reasoning leads through the
impossibility of an infinite regress to a necessary existence which has no
efficient causenot, however, to an existent which has no cause at all, for this
existent might have a formal or a material cause, unless it is assumed that
everything which has matter and form, or in short every compound, must have an
external cause; but this needs a proof which the demonstration based on the
principle of the necessary existent does not contain, even if we do not consider
the mistake in it we have already mentioned. And for exactly the same reason the
proof of the Ash’arites that every temporal occurrence needs a cause does not
lead to an eternal First Principle which is not composite, but only to a First
Principle which is not temporal.
As
to the fact that knower and knowledge are one, it is not impossible, but
necessary, that such pairs of things lead up to the unity of their concepts; e.
g. if the knower knows through knowledge, that through which he becomes a knower
is more apt to be a knower, for the quality which any thing acquires from
another is in itself more apt to possess the concept which is acquired, e. g. if
the living bodies in our sublunary world are not alive by themselves, but
through a life which inheres in them, then necessarily this life through which
the non-living acquires life is alive by itself, or there would be an infinite
regress; and the same is the case with knowledge and the other attributes.
Now,
it cannot be denied that one essence can have many attributes related, negative,
or imaginary, in different ways without this implying a plurality in the
essence, e. g. that a thing is an existent and one and possible or necessary, l
for when the one identical entity is viewed in so far as something else proceeds
from it, it is called capable and acting, and in so far as it is viewed as
differentiating between two opposite acts, it is called willing, and in so far
as it is viewed as perceiving its object, knowing, and in so far as it is viewed
as perceiving and as a cause of motion, it is called living, since the living is
the perceiving and the self-moving. What is impossible is only a single simple
existence with a plurality of attributes, existing by themselves, and especially
if these attributes should be essential and exist in act, and as to these
attributes existing in potency, it is not impossible, according to the
philosophers, that something should be one in act and a plurality in potency,
and this is the case according to them, with the parts of the definition in
their relation to the thing defined.
And as to Ghazali’s
words:
And they affirm that this causes a plurality . . . that they are two.
He
means by them that the fact that these attributes are simultaneous with the
essence does not prevent them from being necessarily a plurality by themselves,
just as, if their existence were posterior to the essence, or if some of them
were posterior to others, mind would not conceive them as being one.
After stating
the view of the philosophers, Ghazali says:
But it must be said to the philosophers: How do you know the impossibility of plurality of this kind? for you are in opposition to all the Muslims, the Mu’tazilites excepted, and what is your proof of it? If someone says: ‘Plurality is impossible, since the fact that the essence is regarded as one is equivalent to the impossibility of its having a plurality of attributes’ this is just the point under discussion, and the impossibility is not self-evident, and a proof is needed. They have indeed two proofs. The first is that they say that, when subject and attribute are not identical, either both, subject and attribute, can exist independently of the other, or each will need the other, or only one of them will depend on the other. In the first case they will both be necessary existents, and this implies an absolute duality and is impossible. In the second case neither of them will be a necessary existent, because the meaning of a necessary existent is that it exists by itself and does not depend in any way on anything else, and when a thing requires something else, that other is its cause, since, if this other were annulled, its existence would be impossible and it would therefore exist not by itself but through another. In the third case the one which was dependent would be an effect and the necessary existent would be the other, on which it would be dependent, and that which was an effect would need a cause and therefore this would necessarily involve connecting the essence of the necessary existent with a cause. ‘
I
say:
When
their opponents concede to the philosophers that there is an existent necessary
by itself and that the meaning of the necessary existent is that it has no cause
at all, neither in its essence through which it subsists, or through something
external, they cannot escape the conclusion which the philosophers forced upon
them: that if the attributes existed through the essence, the essence would be
an existent necessary through itself, and the attributes would be necessary
through something different from themselves, and the essence of the necessary
existent would exist by itself, but the attributes would be necessary through
something different from themselves, and essence and attributes together would
form a compound. z But the Ash’arites do not concede to the philosophers that
the existence of a necessary existent, subsisting by itself, implies that it has
no cause whatsoever, for their argument leads only to the denial of an efficient
cause additional to the essence. ;
Ghazali
says:
The objection against this is to say: The case to be accepted is the last, but we have shown in the fifth discussion that you have no proof for your denial of the first case, that of absolute duality; what is affirmed by you in the fifth discussion can only be justified by basing it upon your denial of plurality in this and the following discussions: how can you therefore base this discussion upon what” is itself the upshot of this discussion?’ But the correct solution is to say: `The essence does not need the attributes for its subsistence, whereas the attributes need a subject, as is the case with us ourselves. ‘ There remains their statement that what is in need of something else is not a necessary existent.
One may ask them: Why do you make such a statement, if you understand by `necessary existent’ only that which has no efficient cause, and why is it impossible to say that, just as there is no agent for the essence of the necessary existent, which is eternal, there is no agent for its attributes, which are equally eternal? If, however, you understand by `necessary existent’ that which has no receptive cause, we answer that that is not implied in this conception of the necessary existent, which, according to this conception is all the same eternal and has no agent; and what is wrong with this conception?
If it is answered that the absolute necessary existent is that which has no efficient cause and no receptive cause, x for if a receptive cause for it were conceded, it would be conceded that it was an effect-we say: To call the receptive essence a receptive cause is one of your technical terms, and there is no proof of the real existence of a necessary existent corresponding to your terminology; all that. is proved is that there must be a final term to the series of causes and effects, and no more, and this series can end in a unit with eternal attributes which have no more an agent than the essence itself, and are supposed to be in the essence itself. But let us put aside this term ‘necessary existent’, which is full of possible confusion. The proof indeed only demonstrates the end of the series and nothing more, and your further claims are pure presumption.
If it is said: In the same way as the series of efficient causes must have an end, the series of receptive causes must have an end, since if every existent needed a substratum to inhere in it and this substratum again needed a substratum, this would imply an infinite series, just as this would be the case if every existent needed a cause and this cause again another cause-we answer: You are perfectly right and for this very reason we say that the series has an end and that the attribute exists in its essence and that this essence does not exist in something else, just as our knowledge exists in our essence and our essence is its substratum, but does not exist itself in a substratum. The series of efficient causes comes to an end for the attribute at the same time as for the essence, since the attribute has an agent no more than the essence has, still the essence provided with this attribute does not cease to exist, although neither itself nor its attribute has a cause. As to the receptive causes, its series can only end in the essence, for how could the negation of a cause imply the negation of a substratum? The proof does not demonstrate anything but the termination of the series, and every method by which this termination can be explained is sufficient to establish the proof which demands the existence of the necessary existent. But if by `necessary existent’ is understood something besides the existent which has no efficient cause and which brings the causal series to an end, we do not by any means concede that this is necessary. And whenever the mind regards it as possible to acknowledge an eternal existent which has no cause for its existence, it regards it as possible to acknowledge an eternal subject for which there is no cause, either for its essence or for its attribute.
As to Ghazali’s
words:
We have shown in the fifth discussion that you have no proof for your denial of the first case, that of absolute duality; what is affirmed by you in the fifth discussion can only be justified by basing it upon your denial of plurality.
I
say:
Ghazali means the philosophers’
denial that subject and attribute are both subsistent by themselves, for from
this it follows that they are independent of each other and that both are
independent gods, which is a dualistic theory, since there is no connexion
through which attribute and subject could become a unity. And since the
philosophers used as an argument for the denial of this kind of plurality the
fact that it has dualism as its consequence, ‘ and a demonstration ought to
proceed in the opposite sense, namely, that dualism would have to be denied,
because of the impossibility of plurality, he says that their proof is circular
and that they proved the principle by the conclusion.
Their
objection, however, was not based upon the facts themselves, but on the theory
of their opponents who deny dualism. And you have learned in another place that
there are two kinds of refutation, one based on the objective facts, the other
based on the statement of the opponent, and although the former is the true kind
of refutation, the second type may also be used .
As to Ghazali’s
words:
But the correct solution is to say: ‘The essence does not need the attributes for its subsistence, whereas the attributes need a subject, as is the case with us ourselves. ‘ There remains their statement that what is in need of another is not a necessary existent.
I
say:
Ghazali means that, when this
tripartite division which they use to deny plurality is submitted to them, the
facts lead them to establish that (i) the necessary existent cannot be a
compound of attribute and subject; (2) the essence cannot be a plurality of
attributes, for they cannot accept these things according to their principles.
Then he starts to show that the impossibility which they strive to deduce from
this division is not strict.
As to Ghazali’s
words:
One may ask them: Why do you make such a statement, if you understand by `necessary existent’ only that which has no efficient cause, and why is it impossible to say that, just as there is no agent for the essence of the necessary existent, which is eternal, there is no agent for its attributes, which are equally eternal?
I
say:
All
this is an objection to Avicenna’s method of denying the attributes by
establishing the necessary existent which exists by itself, but in this question
the most convincing method of showing the necessity of unity and forcing it as a
consequence upon the Ash’arites is the method of the Mu’tazilites. For the
latter understand by ‘possible existence’ the truly possible, ‘ and they
believe that everything below the First Principle is such. Their opponents, the
Ash’arites, accept this, and believe also that every possible has an agent,
and that the series comes to an end through what is not possible in itself. The
Mu’tazilites concede this to them, but they believe that from this concession
it follows that the First, which is the final term of the series of possibility,
is not a possible, and that this implies its absolute simplicity. The
Ash’arites, however, say that the denial of true possibility does not imply
simplicity, but only eternity and the absence of an efficient cause, and
therefore there is among the Ash’arites no proof of the simplicity of the
First through the proof based on the necessary existent. z
And Ghazali
says:
If it is answered that the absolute necessary existent is that which has no efficient cause and no receptive cause, for if a receptive cause for it were conceded, it would be conceded that it was an effect.
I
say:
Ghazali means that, if the philosophers
say that the proof has led to a necessary existent which has no efficient cause,
it has, according to them, no receptive cause either, and that according to the
philosophers the assumption of essence and attributes implies the assumption of
a receptive cause.
Then Ghazali,
answering this, says:.
We say: To call the receptive essence a receptive cause is one of your technical terms, and there is no proof for the real existence of a necessary existent corresponding to your terminology; all that is proved is that there must be a final term to the series of causes and effects.
I
say:
Ghazali means that the Ash’arites do
not concede that this essence in which the attributes inhere is a receptive
cause, ‘ so as to be forced to admit an efficient cause for it. He says that
the proof of the philosophers does not lead to an existent which has no
receptive cause, let alone proving the existence of what has no essence and no
attributes. It only proves that it has no efficient cause. This objection is a
necessary consequence of their own proof. Even if the Ash’arites had accepted
the philosophical theory that what has no efficient cause has no receptive
cause, their own statement would not have been overthrown, for the essence which
they assume only receives attributes which do not belong to the First, since
they assume that the attributes are additional to the essence of the First, and
they do not admit essential attributes in the way the Christians do.
And as to Ghazali’s
words:
If it is said: In the same way as the series of efficient causes must have an end, the series of receptive causes must have an end, since if every existent needed a substratum to inhere in it and this substratum again needed a substratum, this would imply an infinite series, just as this would be the case if every existent needed a cause and this cause again another causewe answer: You are perfectly right and for this very reason we say that the series has an end and that the attribute exists in its essence and that this essence does not exist in something else, just as our knowledge exists in our essence and our essence is its substratum, but does not exist itself in a substratum.
I
say:
This
statement has no connexion with this discussion either with respect to the
philosophical theories he mentions or with respect to the answers he gives, and
it is a kind of sophism, for there exists no relation between the question,
whether the receptive causes must or must not have an end, and the problem which
is under discussion, namely whether it is a condition of the First Agent that it
should have a receptive cause. For the inquiry about the finiteness of receptive
causes differs from the inquiry about the finiteness of efficient causes, since
he who admits the existence of receptive causes admits necessarily that their
series must end in a primary receptive cause which is necessarily external to
the First Agent, just as he admits the existence of a First Agent external to
the receptive matter. For if the First Agent possessed matter, this matter would
not exist numerically and individually either in the first recipient or in the
inferior recipients of other things; ‘ no, if the First Agent possessed
matter, this matter would have to be a matter peculiar to it, and in short it
would belong to it; that is, either it would be its primary matter or we should
arrive at a first recipient, and this recipient would not be of the genus which
is the condition for the existence of all the other existents proceeding from
the First Agent. ‘ But if matter were the condition for the existence of the
First Agent, it would be a condition for the existence of all agents in their
actions, and matter would not only be a condition for the existence of the
agent’s act-since every agent acts only on a recipient -but it would be a
condition for the existence of the agent itself, and therefore every agent would
be a body. ;
All
this the Ash’arites neither admit nor deny. But when the philosophers tell
them that an essence to which such an attribute is ascribed must be a body, they
answer: `Such an attribute is ascribed by you to the soul and yet, according to
you, the soul is not a body. ‘ This is the limit to which dialectical
arguments in this question can be carried. But the demonstrations are in the
works of the ancients which they wrote about this science, and especially in the
books of Aristotle, not in the statements of Avicenna about this problem and of
other thinkers belonging to Islam, if anything is to be found in them on this
question. For their metaphysical theories are pure presumptions, since they
proceed from common, not particular, notions, i. e. notions which are extraneous
to the nature of the inquiry.
And as to Ghazali’s
words:
The series of efficient causes comes to an end for the attribute at the same time as for the essence, since the attribute has an agent no more than the essence has, still the essence provided with this attribute does not cease to exist, although neither itself nor its attribute has a cause.
I
say:
This
is a statement which is not accepted by their opponents, the philosophers; on
the contrary, they affirm that it is a condition of the First Agent that it
should not receive an attribute, because reception indicates matter and it is
therefore not possible to assume as the final term of the causal series an agent
of any description whatsoever, but only an agent which has absolutely no agent,
and to which no attribute-from which it would follow that it had an agent-can be
ascribed. For the assumption of the existence of an attribute of the First Agent
existing in a receptive cause which would be a condition for its existence is
thought by the philosophers to be impossible. Indeed, anything for the existence
of which there is a condition can only be connected with this condition through
an external cause, for a thing cannot itself be the cause of its connexion with
the condition of its existence, just as it cannot be the cause of its own
existence. For the conditioned, if it were not connected with its condition,
would have to exist by itself, and it needs an efficient cause to connect the
condition with it, since a thing cannot be the cause of the existence of the
condition of its own existence; but all these are common notions. And in general
one cannot imagine that it is possible to arrive by this method, as applied to
this problem, at something near evidence, because of the equivocation in the
term `existent necessary by itself’, and in the term `possible by itself,
necessary through another’, and the other preliminary notions which are added
to them.
Ghazali
says:
The second proof of the philosophers is that they say that the knowledge and the power in us do not enter the quiddity of our essence, but are accidental, and when these attributes are asserted of the First, they too do not enter the quiddity of its essence, but are accidental in their relation to it, even if they are lasting; for frequently an accident does not separate itself from its quiddity and is a necessary attribute of it, but still it does not therefore become a constituent of its essence. And if it is an accident, it is consequent on the essence and the essence is its cause, and it becomes an effect, and how can it then be a necessary existent?’
Then Ghazali
says, refuting this:
This proof is identical with the first, notwithstanding the change of expression. For we say: If you mean by its being consequent on the essence, and by the essence’s being its cause, that the essence is its efficient cause, and that it is the effect of the essence, this is not true, for this is not valid of our knowledge in relation to our essence, since our essence is not an efficient cause of our knowledge. If you mean that the essence is a substratum and that the attribute does not subsist by itself without being in a substratum, this is conceded, and why should it be impossible? For if you call this `consequent’ or `accident’ or `effect’ or whatever name you want to give it, its meaning does not change, since its meaning is nothing but `existing in the essence in the way attributes exist in their subjects’. And it is by no means impossible that it should exist in the essence, and be all the same eternal and without an agent. All the proofs of the philosophers amount to nothing but the production of a shock by the use of a depreciating expression: `possible’, `permissible’, ‘consequent’, `connected’, `effect’-but all this may be ignored. For it must be answered: If by this you mean that it has an agent, it is not true, and if only it is meant that it has no agent, but that it has a substratum in which it exists, then let this meaning be indicated by any expression you want, and still it will not become impossible.
I
say:
This
is using many words for one idea. But in this question the difference between
the opponents consists in one point, namely: `Can a thing which has a receptive
cause be without an agent or not?’ Now it belongs to the principles of the
theologians that the connexion of condition and conditioned appertains to the
domain of the permissible’ and that whatever is permissible needs for its
realization and actualization an agent which actualizes it and connects the
condition with the conditioned, and that the connexion is a condition for the
existence of the conditioned and that it is possible neither that a thing should
be the cause of the condition of its existence, nor that the condition should be
the efficient cause of the existence of the conditioned, for our essence is not
the efficient cause of the existence of the knowledge which exists in it, but
our essence is a condition for the existence of the knowledge existing in it.
And because of all these principles it is absolutely necessary that there should
exist an efficient cause which brings about the connexion of condition and
conditioned, and this is the case with every conjunction of a condition and a
conditioned. But all these principles are annulled by the philosophical theory
that heaven is eternal, although it possesses essence and attributes, for the
philosophers do not give it an agent of the kind which exists in the empirical
world, as would be the consequence of these principles; they only assume that
there is a proof which leads to an eternal connexion through an eternal
connecting principle, and this is another kind of connexion, differing from that
which exists in transitory things. But all these are problems which need a
serious examination. And the assumption of the philosophers that these
attributes do not constitute the essence is not true, for every essence is
perfected by attributes through which it becomes more complete and illustrious,
and, indeed, it is constituted by these attributes, since through knowledge,
power, and will we become superior to those existents which do not possess
knowledge, and the essence in which these attributes exist is common to us and
to inorganic things. How therefore could such attributes be accidents consequent
on our essence? All these are statements of people who have not studied well the
psychological and accidental attributes.
Ghazali
says:
And often they shock by the use of a depreciating expression in another way, and they say: This leads to ascribing to the First a need for these attributes, so that it would not be self-sufficient absolutely, since the absolutely self-sufficient is not in need of anything else. ‘
Then Ghazali
says, refuting this:
This is an extremely weak verbal argument, for the attributes of perfection do not differ from the essence of the perfect being in such a way that he should be in need of anything else. And if he is eternally perfect through knowledge, power, and life, how could he be in need of anything, or how could his being attached to perfection be described as his being in need? It would be like saying that the perfect needs no perfection and that he who is in need of the attributes of perfection for his essence is imperfect; the answer is that perfection cannot mean anything but the existence of perfection in his essence, and likewise being self-sufficient does not mean anything but the existence of attributes that exclude every need in his essence. How therefore can the attributes of perfection through which divinity is perfected be denied through such purely verbal arguments?
I
say:
There
are two kinds of perfection: perfection through a thing’s own self and
perfection through attributes which give their subject its perfection, and these
attributes must be in themselves perfect, for if they were perfect through
perfect attributes, we should have to ask whether these attributes were perfect
through themselves or through attributes, and we should have therefore to arrive
at that which is perfect by itself as a final term. Now the perfect through
another will necessarily need, according to the above principles if they are
accepted, a bestower of the attributes of perfection; otherwise it would be
imperfect. But that which is perfect by itself is like that which is existent by
itself, and how true it is that the existent by itself is perfect by itself!If
therefore there exists an existent by itself, it must be perfect by itself and
self-sufficient by itself; otherwise it would be composed of an imperfect
essence and attributes perfecting this essence. If this is true, the attribute
and its subject are one and the same, and the acts which are ascribed to this
subject as proceeding necessarily from different attributes exist only in a
relative way.
Ghazali
says, answering the philosophers:
And if it is said by the philosophers: When you admit an essence and an attribute and the inherence of an attribute in the essence, you admit a composition, and every compound needs a principle which composes it, and just because a body is composed, God cannot be a body-we answer:
Saying that every compound needs a composing principle is like saying that every existent needs a cause for its existence, and it may be answered
The First is eternal and exists without a cause and without a principle for its existence, and so it may be said that it is a subject, eternal, without a cause for its essence, for its attribute and for the existence of its attribute in its essence; indeed all this is eternal without a cause. But the First cannot be a body, because body is a temporal thing which cannot be free from what is temporal’: however, he who does not allow that body has a beginning must be forced to admit that the first cause can be a body, and we shall try later to force this consequence on the philosophers.
I
say:
Composition
is not like existence, because composition is like being set in motion, namely,
a passive quality, additional to the essence of things which receive the
composition, z but existence is a quality which is the essence itself, and
whoever says otherwise is mistaken indeed. Further, the compound cannot be
divided into that which is compound by itself and that which is compound through
another, so that one would finally come to an eternal compound in the way one
arrives, where existents are concerned, at an eternal existent, and we have
treated this problem in another place. ; And again: If it is true, as we have
said, that composition is something additional to existence, then one may say,
if there exists a compound by itself, . then there must exist also something
moved by itself, and if there exists something moved by itself, then also a
privation will come into existence by itself, for the existence of a privation
is the actualization of a potency, and the same applies to motion and the thing
moved. But this is not the case with existence, for existence is not an
attribute additional to the essence, and every existent which does not exist
sometimes in potency and sometimes in act is an existent by itself, whereas the
existence of a thing as moved occurs only when there is a moving power, and
every moved thing therefore needs a movers
The
distinctive point in this problem is that the two parts in any compound must be
either (i) mutually a condition for each other’s existence, as is, according
to the Peripatetics, the case with those which are composed of matters and
forms, b or (2) neither of them a condition for the existence of the other, or
(3) exclusively one the condition for the other.
In
the first case the compound cannot be eternal, because the compound itself is a
condition for the existence of the parts and the parts cannot be the cause of
the compound, nor the compound its own cause, for otherwise a thing might be its
own cause, and this kind of compound, therefore, is transitory and needs an
agent for its actualization. ‘
In
the second case-and for these compounds it is not in the nature of either of
their parts that it implies the other-there is no composition possible without a
composing factor, external to the parts, since the composition is not of their
own nature so that their essence might exist through their nature or be a
consequence of their nature; and if their nature determined the composition and
they were both in themselves eternal, their composition would be eternal, but
would. need a cause which would give it unity, since no eternal thing can
possess unity accidentally.
In
the third case, and this is the case of the non-essential attribute and its
subject, if the subject were eternal and were such as never to be without this
attribute, the compound would be eternal. But if this were so, and if an eternal
compound were admitted, the Ash’arite proof that all accidents are temporal
would not be true, since if there were an eternal compound there would be
eternal accidents, one of which would be the composition, whereas the principle
on which the Ash’arites base their proof of the temporality!of accidents is
the fact that the parts of which a body, according to them, is composed must
exist first separately; if, therefore, they allowed an eternal compound, it
would be possible that there should be a composition not preceded by a
separation, and a movement, not preceded by a rest, and if this were
permissible, it would be possible that a body possessing eternal accidents
should exist, and it would no longer be true for them that what cannot exist
without the temporal is temporal. And further, it has already been said that
every compound is only one because of a oneness existing in it, and this oneness
exists only in it through something which is one through itself. And if this is
so, then the one, in so far as it is one, precedes every compound, and the act
of this one agent-if this agent is eternal-through which it gives all single
existents which exist through it their oneness, is everlasting and without a
beginning, not intermittent; for the agent whose act is attached to its object
at the time of its actualization is temporal and its object is necessarily
temporal, but the attachment of the First Agent to its object is everlasting and
its power is everlastingly mixed with its object. And it is in this way that one
must understand the relation of the First, God, praise be to Him, to all
existents. But since it is not possible to prove these things here, let us turn
away from them, since our sole aim was to show that this book of Ghazali
does not contain any proofs, but mostly sophisms and at best dialectical
arguments. But proofs are very rare, and they stand in relation to other
arguments as unalloyed gold to the other minerals and the pure pearl to the
other jewels. ‘ And now let us revert to our subject.
Ghazali says:
All their proofs where this problem is concerned are imaginary. Further, they are not able to reduce all the qualities which they admit to the essence itself, for they assert, that it is knowing, and so they are forced to admit that this is something additional to its mere existence, and then one can ask them: `Do you concede that the First knows something besides its essence?’ Some of them concede this, whereas others affirm that it only knows its own self. The former position is that taken by Avicenna, for he affirms that the First knows all things in a universal timeless way, but that it does not know individuals, because to comprehend their continual becoming would imply a change in the essence of the knower. z But, we ask, is the knowledge which the First has of all the infinite number of species and genera identical with its self-knowledge or not? If you answer in the negative, you have affirmed a plurality and have contradicted your own principle; if you answer in the affirmative, you are like a man claiming that man’s knowledge of other things is identical with his self-knowledge and with his own essence, and such a statement is mere stupidity. And it may be argued: `The definition of an identical thing is that its negation and affirmation cannot be imagined at the same time, and the knowledge of an identical thing, when it is an identical thing, cannot at the same time be imagined as existing and not existing. And since it is not impossible to imagine a man’s self-knowledge without imagining his knowledge of something else, it may be said that his knowledge of something else is different from his self-knowledge, since, if they were the same, the affirmation or negation of the one would imply the affirmation or negation of the other. For it is impossible that Zaid should be at one and the same time both existing and not existing, but the existence of self-knowledge simultaneously with the non-existence of the knowledge of something else is not impossible, nor is this impossible with the self-knowledge of the First and its knowledge of something else, for the existence of the one can be imagined without the other and they are therefore two things, whereas the existence of its essence without the existence of its essence cannot be imagined, and if the knowledge of all things formed a unity, it would be impossible to imagine this duality. Therefore all those philosophers who acknowledge that the First knows something besides its own essence have undoubtedly at the same time acknowledged a plurality.
I
say:
The
summary of this objection to the proposition that the First knows both itself
and something else is that knowing one’s self is different from knowing
something else. But Ghazali falls here into
confusion. For this can be understood in two ways: first, that Zaid’s
knowledge of his own individuality is identical with his knowledge of other
things, and this is not true; secondly, that man’s knowledge of other things,
namely of existents, is identical with the knowledge of his own essence, and
this is true. ‘ And the proof is that his essence is nothing but his knowledge
of the existents. z For if man like all other beings knows only the quiddity
which characterizes him, and if his quiddity is the knowledge of things, then
man’s self-knowledge is necessarily the knowledge of all other things, for if
they were different his essence would be different from his knowledge of things.
This is clear in the case of the artisan, for his essence, through which he is
called an artisan, is nothing but his knowledge of the products of art. ; And as
to Ghazali’s words, that if his self-knowledge
were identical with his knowledge of other things, then the negation of the one
would be the negation of the other and the affirmation of the one the
affirmation of the other, he means that if the self-consciousness of man were
identical with his knowledge of other things, he could not know his own self
without knowing the other things; that is, if he were ignorant of other things,
he would not know his own self, and this proposition is in part true, in part
false. For the quiddity of man is knowledge, and knowledge is the thing known in
one respect and is something different in another. And if he is ignorant of a
certain object of knowledge, he is ignorant of a part of his essence, and if he
is ignorant of all knowables, he is ignorant of his essence; and to deny man
this knowledge is absolutely the same as to deny man’s selfconsciousness, for
if the thing known is denied to the knower in so far as the thing known and
knowledge are one, man’s self-consciousness itself is denied. But in so far as
the thing known is not knowledge, it is not man, and to deny man this knowledge
does not imply the denial of man’s self-consciousness. And the same applies to
individual men. For Zaid’s knowledge of Amr is not Zaid himself, and therefore
Zaid can know his own self, while being ignorant of Amr.
Ghazali says:
If it is said: `The First does not know other things in first intention. No, it knows its own essence as the principle of the universe, and from this its knowledge of the universe follows in second intention, since it cannot know its essence except as a principle, for this is the true sense of its essence, and it cannot know its essence as a principle for other things, without the other things entering into its knowledge by way of implication and consequence; it is not impossible that from its essence consequences should follow, and this does not imply a plurality in its essence, and only a plurality in its essence is impossible’-there are different ways of answering this. First your assertion that it knows its essence to be a principle is a presumption; it suffices that it knows the existence of its essence, and the knowledge that it is a principle is an addition to its knowledge of its essence, since being a principle is a relation to the essence and it is possible that it should know its essence and not this relation, and if this being-a-principle were not a relation, its essence would be manifold and it would have existence and be a principle, and this forms a duality. And just as a man can know his essence without knowing that he is an effect, for his being an effect is a relation to his cause, so the fact that the First is a cause is a relation between itself and its object. This consequence is implied in the mere statement of the philosophers that it knows that it is a principle, since this comprises the knowledge of its essence and of its being a principle, and this is a relation, and the relation is not the essence, and the knowledge of the relation is not the knowledge of the essence and we have already given the proof of this, namely that we can imagine knowledge of the essence, without the knowledge of its being a principle, but knowledge of the essence without the knowledge of the essence cannot be imagined, since the essence is an identical unity.
I
say:
The
proposition which the philosophers defend against Ghazali
in this question is based on philosophical principles which must be discussed
first. For if the principles they have assumed and the deductions to which,
according to them, their demonstration leads, are conceded, none of the
consequences which Ghazali holds against them
follows. The philosophers hold, namely, that the incorporeal existent is in its
essence nothing but knowledge, for they believe that the forms’ have no
knowledge for the sole reason that they are in matter; but if a thing does not
exist in matter, it is known to be knowing, and this is known because they found
that when forms which are in matter are abstracted in the soul from matter they
become knowledge and intellect, for intellect is nothing but the forms
abstracted from matter, z and if this is true for things which by the principle
of their nature are not abstracted, then it is still more appropriate for things
which by the principle of their nature are abstracted to be knowledge and
intellect. And since what is intelligible in things is their innermost reality,
and since intellect is nothing but the perception of the intelligibles, our own
intellect is the intelligible by itself, in so far as it is an intelligible, and
so there is no difference between the intellect and the intelligible, except in
so far as the intelligibles are intelligibles of things in the nature of which
there is no intellect and which only become intellect because the intellect
abstracts their forms from their matters, and through this our intellect is not
the intelligible in every respect. But if there is a thing which does not exist
in matter, then to conceive it by intellect is identical with its intelligible
in every respect, and this is the case with the intellectual conception of the
intelligibles. And no doubt the intellect is nothing but the perception of the
order and arrangement of existing things, but it is necessary for the separate
intellect that it should not depend on the existing things in its intellectual
conception of the existing things and of their order, and that its intelligible
should not be posterior to them, for every other intellect is such that it
follows the order which exists in the existents and perfects itself through it,
and necessarily falls short in its intellectual conception of the things, and
our intellect, therefore, cannot adequately fulfil the demands of the natures of
existing things in respect of their order and arrangement. But if the natures of
existing things follow the law of the intellect and our intellect is inadequate
to perceive the natures of existent things, there must necessarily exist a
knowledge of the arrangement and order which is the cause of the arrangement,
order and wisdom which exist in every single being, and it is necessary that
this intellect should be the harmony which is the cause of the harmony which
exists in the existents, and that it should be impossible to ascribe to its
perception knowledge of universals, let alone knowledge of individuals, ‘
because universals are intelligibles which are consequent on and posterior to
existents, z whereas on the contrary the existents are consequent on this
intellect. And this intellect necessarily conceives existents by conceiving the
harmony and order which exist in the existents through its essence, not by
conceiving anything outside its essence, for in that case it would be the
effect, not the cause, of the existent it conceives, and it would be inadequate.
And
if you have understood this philosophical theory, you will have understood that
the knowledge of things through a universal knowledge is inadequate, for it
knows them in potency, and that the separate intellect only conceives its own
essence, and that by conceiving its own essence it conceives all existents,
since its intellect is nothing but the harmony and order which exist in all
beings, and this order and harmony is received by the active powers which
possess order and harmony and exist in all beings and are called natures by the
philosophers. For it seems that in every being there are acts which follow the
arrangement and order of the intellect, and this cannot happen by accident, nor
can it happen through an intellect which resembles our intellect; no, this can
only occur through an intellect more exalted than all beings, and this intellect
is neither a universal nor an individual. And if you have understood this
philosophical theory, all the difficulties which Ghazali
raises here against the philosophers are solved; but if you assume that yonder
intellect resembles our own, the difficulties mentioned follow. For the
intellect which is in us is numerable and possesses plurality, but this is not
the case with yonder intellect, for it is free from the plurality which belongs
to our intelligibles and one cannot imagine a difference in it between the
perceiver and the perceived, whereas to the intellect which is in us the
perception of a thing is different from the perception that it is a principle of
a thing, and likewise its perception of another is different in a certain way
from the perception of itself. Still, our intellect has a resemblance to yonder
intellect, and it is yonder intellect which gives our intellect this
resemblance, for the intelligibles which are in yonder intellect are free from
the imperfections which are in our intellect: for instance, our intellect only
becomes the intelligible in so far as it is an intelligible, because there
exists an intellect which is the intelligible in every respect. The reason for
this is that everything which possesses an imperfect attribute possesses this
attribute necessarily through a being which possesses it in a perfect way. For
instance, that which possesses an insufficient warmth possesses this through a
thing which possesses a perfect warmth, and likewise that which possesses an
insufficient life or an imperfect intellect possesses this through a thing which
possesses a perfect life or a perfect intellect. ‘ And in the same way a thing
which possesses a perfect rational act receives this act from a perfect
intellect, and if the acts of all beings, although they do not possess
intellects, are perfect rational acts, then there exists an intellect through
which the acts of all beings become rational acts.
It
is weak thinkers who, not having understood this, ask whether the First
Principle thinks its own essence or if it thinks something outside its essence.
But to assume that it thinks something outside its essence would imply that it
is perfected by another thing, and to assume that it does not think something
outside its essence would imply that it is ignorant of existents. One can only
wonder at these people who remove from the attributes which are common to the
Creator and the created, all the imperfections which they possess in the
created, and who still make our intellect like His intellect, whereas nothing is
more truly free from all imperfection than His intellect. This suffices for the
present chapter, but now let us relate the other arguments of Ghazali
in this chapter and call attention to the mistakes in them.
Ghazali
says:
The second way to answer this assertion is to say that their expression that everything is known to it in second intention is without sense, for as soon as its knowledge comprehends a thing different from itself, in the way it comprehends its own essence, this First Principle will have two different objects of knowledge and it will know them both, for the plurality and the difference of the object known imply a plurality in the knowledge, since each of the two objects known receives in the imagination the discrimination which distinguishes it from the other. And therefore the knowledge of the one cannot be identical with the knowledge of the other, for in that case it would be impossible to suppose the existence of the one without the other, and indeed there could not be an other at all, since they would both form an identical whole, and using for it the expression `second intention’ does not make any difference. Further, I should be pleased to know how he who says that not even the weight of an atom, either in heaven or earth, escapes God’s knowledge, ‘ intends to deny the plurality, unless by saying that God knows the universe in a universal way. However, the universals which form the objects of His knowledge would be infinite, and still His knowledge which is attached to them would remain one in every respect, notwithstanding their plurality and their differentiation.
I
say:
The
summary of this is found in two questions. The first is, `How can its knowledge
of its own self be identical with its knowledge of another?’ The answer to
this has already been given, namely that there is something analogous in the
human mind which has led us to believe in the necessity of its being in the
First Intellect.
The
second question is whether its knowledge is multiplied through the plurality of
its objects known and whether it comprehends all finite and infinite knowables
in a way which makes it possible that its knowledge should comprehend the
infinite. The answer to this question is that it is not impossible that there
should exist in the First Knowledge, notwithstanding its unity, a distinction
between the objects known, and it is not impossible, according to the
philosophers, that it should know a thing, different from itself, and its own
essence, through a knowledge which differs in such a way that there should exist
a plurality of knowledge. The only thing which is absolutely impossible
according to them is that the First Intellect should be perfected through the
intelligible and caused by it, and if the First Intellect thought things
different from itself in the way we do, it would be an effect of the existent
known, not its cause, and it has been definitely proved that it is the cause of
the existent. The plurality which the philosophers deny does not consist in its
knowing through its own essence, but in its knowing through a knowledge which is
additional to its essence; the denial, however, of this plurality in God does
not imply the denial of a plurality of things known, except through dialectics,
and Ghazali’s transference of the problem of
the plurality which is in the knowledge, according to the philosophers, to the
problem of plurality which is in the things known themselves, is an act of
sophistry, because it supposes that the philosophers deny the plurality which is
in the knowledge through the things known, in the way they deny the plurality
which arises through the duality of substratum and inherent.
But
the truth in this question is that there is not a plurality of things known in
the Eternal Knowledge like their numerical plurality in human knowledge. For the
numerical plurality of things known in human knowledge arises from two sources:
first the representations, and this resembles spatial plurality;’ secondly the
plurality of what is known in our intellect, namely the plurality which occurs
in the first genus-which we may call being-through its division into all the
species which are subsumed under it, for our intellect is one; with respect to
the universal genus which comprises all species existing in the world, whereas
it becomes manifold through the plurality of the species. And it is clear that
when we withhold the idea of the universal from the Eternal Knowledge, this
plurality is in fact abandoned and there only remains in the Divine a plurality
the perception of which is denied to our intellect, for otherwise our knowledge
would be identical with this eternal knowledge, and this is impossible. And
therefore what the philosophers say is true, that for the human understanding
there is a limit, where it comes to a stand, and beyond which it cannot
trespass, and this is our inability to understand the nature of this knowledge.
And again, our intellect is knowledge of the existents in potency, not knowledge
in act, and knowledge in potency is less perfect than knowledge in act; and the
more our knowledge is universal, the more it comes under the heading of
potential knowledge and the more its knowledge becomes imperfect . But it is not
true of the Eternal Knowledge that it is imperfect in any way, and in it there
is no knowledge in potency, for knowledge in potency is knowledge in matter.
Therefore the philosophers believe that the First Knowledge requires that there
should be a knowledge in act and that there should be in the divine world no
universal at all and no plurality which arises out of potency, like the
plurality of the species which results from the genus. And for this reason alone
we are unable to perceive the actually infinite, that the things known to us are
separated from each other, and if there exists a knowledge in which the things
known are unified, then with respect to it the finite and the infinite are
equivalent.
The
philosophers assert that there are definite proofs for all these statements, and
if we understand by `plurality in knowledge’ only this plurality and this
plurality is denied of the Divine, then the knowledge of God is a unity in act,
but the nature of this unity and the representation of its reality are
impossible for the human understanding, for if man could perceive the unity, his
intellect would be identical with the intellect of the Creator, and this is
impossible. And since knowledge of the individual is for us knowledge in act, we
know that God’s knowledge is more like knowledge of the individual than
knowledge of the universal, although it is neither the one nor the other. And he
who has understood this understands the Divine Words: `Nor shall there escape
from it the weight of an atom, either in the heavens or in the earth’, and
other similar verses which refer to this idea.
Ghazali
says:
Avicenna, however, has put himself in opposition to all the other philosophers who, in order not to commit themselves to the consequence of plurality, took the view that the First only knows itself; how, then, can he share with them the denial of plurality’ Still he distinguished himself from them by admitting its knowledge of other things, since he was ashamed to say that God is absolutely ignorant of this world and the next and knows only His own self-whereas all others know Him, and know also their own selves and other things, and are therefore superior to Him in knowledge-and he abandoned that blasphemous philosophical theory, refusing to accept it. Still he was not ashamed of persisting in the denial of this plurality in every respect, and he affirmed that God’s knowledge of Himself and of other things, yes, of the totality of things, is identical with His essence without this implying any contradiction, and this is the very contradiction which the other philosophers were ashamed to accept, because of its obviousness. And thus no party among the philosophers could rid itself of a blasphemous doctrine, and it is in this manner that God acts towards the man who strays from His path and who believes that he has the power through his speculation and imagination to fathom the innermost nature of the Divine.
I
say:
The
answer to all this is clear from what we have said already, namely that the
philosophers only deny that the First Principle knows other things than its own
self in so far as these other things are of an inferior existence, so that the
effect should not become a cause, nor the superior existence the inferior; for
knowledge is identical with the thing known. They do not, however, deny it, in
so far as it knows these other things by a knowledge, superior in being to the
knowledge by which we know other things; on the contrary, it is necessary that
it should know them in this way, because it is in this way that the other things
proceed from the First Agent. As to the inquiry about the possibility of a
plurality of things known in the Eternal Knowledge, that is a second question,
and we have mentioned it, and it is not because of this that the philosophers
sought refuge in the theory that the First knows only its own self, as Ghazali
wrongly supposes; no, only because in short-as we have dcclared already-its
knowledge should not be like our knowledge which differs from it in the extreme.
And Avicenna wanted only to combine these two statements, that it knows only its
own essence and that it knows other things by a knowledge superior to man’s
knowledge of them, since this knowledge constitutes its essence, and this is
clear from Avicenna’s words that it knows its own self and other things
besides itself, and indeed all things which constitute its essence, although
Avicenna does not explain this, as we have done. And, therefore, these words of
his are not a real contradiction, nor are the other philosophers ashamed of
them; no, this is a statement about which, explicitly or implicitly, they all
agree. And if you have grasped this well, you will have understood Ghazali’s
bad faith in his attack on the philosophers, although he agrees with them in the
greater part of their opinions.
Ghazali
says, on behalf of the philosophers:
It may be said that if it is asserted that the First knows its own self as a principle by way of relation, the knowledge of two correlatives is one and the same, for the man who knows the son knows him through one single knowledge in which the knowledge of the father, of fatherhood, and sonhood are comprised, so that the objects of knowledge are manifold, but the knowledge is one. ‘ And in the same way the First knows its essence as a principle for the other things besides itself and so the knowledge is one, although what is known is manifold. Further, if the First thinks this relation in reference to one single effect and its own relation towards it, and this does not imply a plurality, then a plurality is not implied by an addition of things which generically do not imply a plurality. ‘ And likewise he who knows a thing and knows his knowing this thing, knows this thing through this knowledge, and therefore all knowledge is self-knowledge connected with the knowledge of the thing known, ‘ and the known is manifold, but knowledge forms a unity. ; An indication of this is also that you theologians believe that the things known to God are infinite, but His knowledge is one, and you do not attribute to God an infinite number of cognitions; if, indeed, the manifoldness of the known implied a plurality in the knowledge itself, well, let there then be an infinite number of cognitions in the essence of God. But this is absurd.
Then Ghazali
says, answering the philosophers:
We say: Whenever knowledge is one in every respect, it cannot be imagined that it should be attached to two things known; on the contrary, this determines a certain plurality, according to the assumption and tenet of the philosophers themselves about the meaning of ‘plurality’, so that they even make the excessive claim that if the First had a quiddity to which existence were attributed, this would imply a plurality. And they do not think that to a single unity possessing reality existence also can be attributed; no, they assert that the existence is brought in relation to the reality and differs from it and determines a plurality, and on this assumption it is not possible that knowledge should attach itself to two objects of knowledge without this implying a greater and more important kind of plurality than that which is intended in the assumption of an existence, brought in relation to a quiddity. And as to the knowledge of a son and similarly of other relative concepts, there is in it a plurality, since there must necessarily be knowledge of the son himself and the father himself, and this is a dual knowledge, and there must be a third knowledge, and this is the relation; indeed, this third knowledge is implied in the dual knowledge which precedes it, as they are its necessary condition, for as long as the terms of relation are not known previously, the relation itself cannot be known, and there is thus a plurality of knowledge of which one part is conditioned through another. Likewise when the First knows itself as related to the other genera and species by being their principle, it needs the knowledge of its own essence and of the single genera and it must further know that there exists between itself and those genera and species the relation of being a principle, for otherwise the existence of this relation could not be supposed to be known to it. And as to their statement that he who knows something knows that he is knowing through this knowledge itself, so that the thing known can be manifold, but the knowledge remains one, this is not true; on the contrary, he knows that he knows through another knowledge, and this ends in a knowledge to which he does not pay attention and of which he is no longer conscious, and we do not say that there is an infinite regress, but there is a final term of knowledge attached to the thing known, and he is unconscious of the existence of the knowledge, but not of the existence of the known, like a man who knows the colour black and whose soul at the moment of his knowing it is plunged in the object of his knowledge, the colour black, and who is unconscious of his knowing this colour black and whose attention is not centred on it, for if it were, he would need another knowledge till his attention came to a stand. ‘ And as to the affirmation of the philosophers that this can be turned against the theologians concerning the things known by God, for they are infinite, whereas God’s knowledge according to the theologians is one, we answer, `We have not plunged ourselves into this book to set right, but to destroy and to refute, and for this reason we have called this book “The Incoherence of the Philosophers”, not “The Establishment of the Truth”, and this argument against us is not conclusive. ‘
And if the philosophers say: `We do not draw this conclusion against you theologians in so far as you hold the doctrine of a definite sect but in so far as this problem is applied to the totality of mankind, and the difficulty for all human understanding is the same, and you have no right to claim it against us in particular, for it can be turned against you also, and there is no way out of it for any party’-we answer: `No, but our aim is to make you desist from your claim to possess knowledge of the essential realities through strict proofs, and to make you doubt. And when your impotence becomes evident, we say that there are men who hold that the divine realities cannot be attained through rational inquiry, for it is not in human power to apprehend them and it was for this reason that Muhammad, the Lord of the Law, said “Ponder over God’s creation, but do not ponder over God’s essence”. Why then do you oppose this group of men who believe in the truth of the prophet through the proof of his miracles, ‘ who confine the judgement of the intellect to a belief in God, the Sender of the Prophets, who guard themselves against any rational speculation about the attributes, who follow the Lord of the Law in his revelations about God’s attributes, who accept his authority for the use of the terms “the knowing” “the wifer”, “the powerful”, “the living”, who refuse to acknowledge those meanings which are forbidden and who recognize our impotence to reach the Divine Intellect? You only refute these men in so far as they are ignorant of the methods of demonstration and of the arrangement of premisses according to the figures of the syllogisms, and you claim that you know these things by rational methods; but now your impotence, the breakdown of your methods, the shamelessness of your claim to knowledge, have come to light, and this is the intention of our criticism. And where is the man who would dare to claim that theological proofs have the strictness of geometrical proofs?’;
I
say:
All
this prolix talk has only a rhetorical and dialectical value. And the arguments
which he gives in favour of the philosophers about the doctrine of the unity of
God’s knowledge are two, the conclusion of which is that in our concepts there
are conditions which do not through their plurality bring plurality into the
concepts themselves, just as there appear in the existents conditions which do
not bring plurality into their essences, for instance that a thing should be one
and exist and be necessary or possible. And all this, if it is true, is a proof
of a unique knowledge comprising a multitude, indeed an infinite number, of
sciences.
The
first argument which he uses in this section refers to those mental processes
which occur to the concept in the soul and which resemble the conditions in the
existents with respect to the relations and negations, which exist in them; for
it appears from the nature of the relation which occurs in the concepts that it
is a condition through which no plurality arises in the concepts, ‘ and it is
now argued that the relation which presents itself in the related things belongs
to this class of conditions. Ghazali objects to
this that the relation and the terms of the relation form a plurality of
knowledge, and that for instance our knowledge of fatherhood is different from
our knowledge of the father and the son. Now the truth is that the relation is
an attribute additional to the terms of the relation outside the soul in the
existents, but as to the relation which exists in the concepts, it is better
suited to be a condition than an attribute additional to the terms of the
relation;’ however, all this is a comparison of man’s knowledge with the
Eternal Knowledge, and this is the very cause of the mistake. Everyone who
concerns himself with doubt about the Eternal Knowledge and tries to solve it by
what occurs in human knowledge does indeed transfer the knowledge from the
empirical to the Divine concerning two existents which differ in an extreme
degree, not cxistents which participate in their species or genus, but which are
totally unlike.
The
second proof is that we know a thing through a single knowledge and that we know
that we know by a knowledge which is a condition in the first knowledge, not an
attribute additional to it, and the proof of this is that otherwise there would
arise an infinite series. Now Ghazali’s
answer, that this knowledge is a second knowledge and that there is no infinite
series here, is devoid of sense, for it is self-evident that this implies such a
series, and it does not follow from the fact that when a man knows a thing but
is not conscious that he knows the fact that he knows, that in the case when lie
knows that he knows, this second knowledge is an additional knowledge to the
first; no, the second knowledge is one of the conditions of the first knowledge
and its infinite regress is therefore not impossible; if, however, it were a
knowledge existing by itself and additional to the first knowledge, an infinite
series could not occur. ‘
As
to the conclusion which the philosophers force upon the theologians, that all
the theologians recognize that God’s knowledge is infinite and that at the
same time it is one, this is an negumentum
ad hominem, not an objective argument based on the facts themselves. And
from this there is no escape for the theologians, unless they assume that the
knowledge of the Creator differs in this respect from the knowledge of the
creature, and indeed there is no one more ignorant than the man who believes
that the knowledge of God differs only quantitatively from the knowledge of the
creature, that is that He only possesses more knowledge. All these are
dialectical arguments, but one may be convinced of the fact that God’s
knowledge is one and that it is not an effect of the things known; no, it is
their cause, and a thing that has numerous causes is indeed manifold itself,
whereas a thing that has numerous effects need not be manifold in the way that
the effects form a plurality. And there is no doubt that the plurality which
exists in the knowledge of the creature must be denied of God’s knowledge,
just as any change through the change of the objects known must be denied of
Him, and the theologians assume this by one of their fundamental principles. ‘
But the arguments which have been given here are all dialectical arguments.
And
as to his statement that his aim here is not to reach knowledge of the truth but
only to refute the theories of the philosophers and to reveal the inanity of
their claims, this is not worthy of him-but rather of very bad men. And how
could it be otherwise? For the greater part of the subtlety this man
acquired-and he surpassed ordinary people through the subtlety he put in the
books he composed-he only acquired from the books of the philosophers and from
their teaching. And even supposing they erred in something, he ought not to have
denied their merit in speculative thought and in those ideas through which they
trained our understanding. Nay more, if they had only invented logic, he and
anyone else who understands the importance of this science ought to thank them
for it, and he himself was conscious of the value of logic and urged its study
and wrote treatises about it, and he says that there is no other way to learn
the truth than through this science, and he had even such an exaggerated view of
logic that he extracted it from the book of God, the holy Qur’an. ‘ And is
it allowed to one who is indebted to their books and to their teaching to such
an extent that he excelled his contemporaries and that his fame in Islam became
immense, is it really allowed to such a man to speak in this way of them, and to
censure them so openly, so absolutely, and condemn their sciences? And suppose
they erred in certain theological questions, we can only argue against their
mistakes by the rules they have taught us in the logical sciences, and we are
convinced that they will not blame us when we show them a mistake which might be
found in their opinions. And indeed their aim was only the acquisition of truth,
and if their only merit consisted in this, it would suffice for their praise,
although nobody has said anything about theological problems that can be
absolutely relied upon and nobody is guaranteed against mistakes but those whom
God protects in a divine, superhuman way, namely the prophets, and I do not know
what led this man to this attack against such statements; may God protect me
against failings in word and in deed and forgive me if I fail!
And
what he says of the belief held by those who follow the Divine Law in these
things is in agreement with what is said by the renowned philosophers, for when
it is said that God’s knowledge and attributes cannot be described by, or
compared to, the attributes of the creature, so that it cannot even be asserted
that they are essence or an addition to the essence, this expresses the thought
of genuine philosophers and other true thinkers, and God is the Saviour, the
Leader.
Ghazali
says:
It may be said, `This difficulty applies only to Avicenna in so far as he says that the First knows other things, but the acknowledged philosophers are in agreement that it does not know anything besides itself, and this difficulty is therefore set aside. ‘
But we answer, `What a terrible blasphemy is this doctrine! Verily, had it not had this extreme weakness, later philosophers would not have scorned it, but we shall draw attention to its reprehensible character, for this theory rates God’s effects higher than Himself, since angel and man and every rational being knows himself and his principle and knows also of other beings, but the First knows only its own self and is therefore inferior to individual men, not to speak of the angels; indeed, the animals besides their awareness of themselves know other things, and without doubt knowledge is something noble and the lack of it is an imperfection. And what becomes of their statement that God, because He is the most perfect splendour and the utmost beauty, is the lover and the beloved? But what beauty can there be in mere existence which has no quiddity, no essence, which i observes neither what occurs in the world nor what is a consequence or proceeds from its own essence? And what deficiency in God’s whole world could be greater? And an intelligent man may well marvel at a group of men who according to their statement speculate deeply about the intelligibles, but whose inquiry culminates in a Lord of Lords and Cause of causes who does not possess any knowledge about anything that happens in the world. What difference is there then between Him and the dead, except that He has self-consciousness? And what perfection is there in His self-knowledge, if He is ignorant of everything else? And the blasphemy of this doctrine releases us from the use of many words and explanations.
Further, there may be said to them: `Although you plunge yourselves in these shameful doctrines, you cannot free yourselves from plurality, for we ask: “Is the knowledge He has of His essence identical with His essence or not?” If you say, “No”, you introduce plurality, and if you say they are identical, what then is the difference between you and a man who said that a man’s knowledge of his essence was identical with his essence, which is pure foolishness? For the existence of this man’s essence can be conceived, while he gives no attention to his essence, ‘ whereas when afterwards his attention returns, he becomes aware of his essence. Therefore his awareness of his essence differs from his essence. ‘
If it is argued: `Certainly a man can be without knowledge of his essence, but when this knowledge occurs to him, he becomes a different being’, we answer: ‘Non-identity cannot be understood through an accident and conjunction, for the identical thing cannot through an accident become another thing and that other thing, conjoined with this, does not become identical with it, but keeps its individual otherness. And the fact that God is eternally self-conscious does not prove that His knowledge of His essence is identical with His essence, for His essence can be imagined separately and the occurrence of His awareness afterwards, and if they were identical this could not be imagined.
And if it be said: `His essence is intellect and knowledge, and He has not an essence in which afterwards knowledge exists’, we answer: `The foolishness of this is evident, for knowledge is an attribute and an accident which demands a subject, and to say, “He is in His essence intellect and knowledge” is like saying, “He is power and will, and power and will exist by themselves”, and this again is like saying of black and white, quantity, fourness and threeness and all other accidents that they exist by themselves. And in exactly the same way as it is impossible that the attributes of bodies should exist by themselves without a body which itself is different from the attributes, it is known to be impossible that attributes like the knowledge, life, power, and will of living beings should exist by themselves, for they exist only in an essence. For life exists in an essence which receives life through it, and the same is the case with the other attributes. And therefore they do not simply content themselves with denying to the First all qualities (and not merely its real essence and quiddity); no, they deny to it also its very existence by itself’ and reduce it to the entities of accidents and attributes which have no existence by themselves; and besides we shall show later in a special chapter their incapacity to prove that it is conscious either of itself or of other things. ‘
I
say:
The
problem concerning the knowledge of the Creator of Himself and of other things
is one of those questions which it is forbidden to discuss in a dialectical way,
let alone put them down in a book, for the understanding of the masses does not
suffice to understand such subtleties, and when one embarks on such problems
with them the meaning of divinity becomes void for them and therefore it is
forbidden to them to occupy themselves with this knowledge, since it suffices
for their blessedness to understand what is within their grasp. The Holy Law,
the first intention of which is the instruction of the masses, z does not
confine itself to the explanation of these things in the Creator by making them
understood through their existence in human beings, for instance by the Divine
Words: `Why dost thou worship what can neither hear nor see nor avail thee
aught?’, ‘ but enforces the real understanding of these entities in the
Creator by comparing them even to the human limbs, for instance in the Divine
Words: `Or have they not seen that we have created for them of what our hands
have made for them, cattle and they are owners thereof?’ and the Divine Words,
`I have created with my two hands’. s This problem indeed is reserved for the
men versed in profound knowledge to whom God has permitted the sight of the true
realities, and therefore it must not be mentioned in any books except those that
are composed according to a strictly rational pattern, that is, such books as
must be read in a rational order and after the acquisition of other sciences the
study of which according to a demonstrative method is too difficult for most
men, even for those w_ o possess by nature a sound understanding, although such
men are very scarce. But to discuss these questions with the masses is like
bringing poisons to the bodies of many animals, for which they are real poisons.
Poisons, however, are relative, and what is poison for one animal is nourishment
for another. The same applies to ideas in relation to men; that is, there are
ideas which are poison for one type of men, but which are nourishment for
another type. And the man who regards all ideas as fit for all types of men is
like one who gives all things as nourishment for all people; the man, however,
who forbids free inquiry to the mature is like one who regards all nourishment
as poison for everyone. But this is not correct, for there are things which are
poison for one type of man and nourishment for another type. ‘ And the man who
brings poison to him for whom it is really poison merits punishment, although it
may be nourishment for another, and similarly the man who forbids poison to a
man for whom it is really nourishment so that this man may die without it, he
too must be punished. And it is in this way that the question must be
understood. But when the wicked and ignorant transgress and bring poison to the
man for whom it is really poison, as if it were nourishment, then there is need
of a physician who through his science will exert himself to heal that man, and
for this reason we have allowed ourselves to discuss this problem in such a book
as this, and in any other case we should not regard this as permissible to us;
on the contrary, it would be one of the greatest crimes, or a deed of the
greatest wickedness on earth, and the punishment of the wicked is a fact well
known in the Holy Law. And since it is
impossible to avoid the discussion of this problem, let us treat it in
such a way as is possible in this place for those who do not possess the
preparation and mental training needed before entering upon speculation about
it.
So
we say that the philosophers, when they observed all perceptible things, found
that they fell into two classes, the one a class perceptible by the senses,
namely the individual bodies existing by themselves and the individual accidents
in these bodies, and the other a class perceptible by the mind, namely, the
quiddities and natures of these substances and accidents. And they found that in
these bodies there are quiddities which exist essentially in them, and I
understand by the `quiddities’ of bodies attributes existing in them, through
which these bodies become existent in act and specified by the act which
proceeds from them; and according to the philosophers these quiddities differ
from the accidental attributes, because they found that the accidents were
additions to the individual substance which exists by itself and that these
accidents were in need of the substances for their existence, whereas the
substances do not need the accidents for their own existence. And they found
also that those attributes which were not accidents were not additional to the
essence, but that they were the genuine essence of the individual which exists
by itself, so that if one imagined these attributes annulled, the essence itself
would be annulled. Now, they discovered these qualities in individual bodies
through the acts which characterize each of them; for instance they perceived
the attributes through which plants by their particular action become plants’
and the attributes through which animals by their particular actions become
animals, and in the same way they found in the minerals forms of this kind which
are proper to them, through the particular actions of minerals. Then, when they
had investigated these attributes, they learned that they were in a substratum
of this essence and this substratum became differentiated for them, because of
the changing of the individual existents from one species into another species
and from one genus into another genus through the change and alteration of these
attributes; for instance the change of the nature of fire into air by the
cessation of the attribute from which the actuality of fire, through which fire
is called fire, proceeds, and its change into the attribute from which the
actuality peculiar to air, through which air is called air, proceeds. They also
proved the existence of this substratum through the capacity of the individual
essence to receive an actuality from another, just as they proved by the
actuality the existence of form, for it could not be imagined that action and
passivity proceed from one and the same natures They believed therefore that all
active and passive bodies are composed of two natures, one active and the other
passive, and they called the active nature form, quiddity, and substance, and
the passive part subject, ultimate basis of existenceb and matter. And from this
it became clear to them that the perceptible bodies are not simple bodies as
they appear to be to the senses, nor compounded of simple bodies, since they are
compounded of action and passivity; and they found that what the senses perceive
are these individual bodies, which are compounded of these two things which they
called form and matter and that what the mind perceives of these bodies are
these forms which only become concepts and intellect when the intellect
abstracts them from the things existing by themselves, i. e. what the
philosophers call substratum and matter. ? And they found that the accidents
also are divided in the intellect in a way similar to those two natures, s
although their substratum in which they exist in reality is the bodies
compounded of these two natures. And when they had distinguished the
intelligibles from the sensibles and it had become clear to them that in
sensible things there are two natures, potency and act, they inquired which of
these two natures was prior to the other and found that the act was prior to the
potency, because the agent was prior to its object, ‘ and they investigated
also causes and effects, which led them to a primary cause which by its act is
the first cause of all causes, and it followed that this cause is pure act and
that in it there is no potency at all, since if there were potency in it, it
would be in part an effect, in part a cause, and could not be a primary cause.
And since in everything composed of attribute and subject there is potency and
act, it was a necessary implication for them that the First could not be
composed of attribute and subject, and since everything free from matter was
according to them intellect, it was necessary for them that the First should be
intellect.
This
in summary is the method of the philosophers, and if you are one of those whose
mind is sufficiently trained to receive the sciences, and you are steadfast and
have leisure, it is your duty to look into the books and the sciences of the
philosophers, so that you may discover in their works certain truths (or perhaps
the reverse) ; but if you lack one of these three qualities, it is your duty to
keep yourself to the words of the Divine Law, and you should not look for these
new conceptions in Islam; for if you do so, you will be neither a rationalist
nor a traditionalist. ‘
Such
was the philosophers’ reason for their belief that the essence which they
found to be the principle of the world was simple and that it was knowledge and
intellect. And finding that the order which reigns in the world and its parts
proceeds from a knowledge prior to it, they judged that this intellect and this
knowledge was the principle of the world, which gave the world existence and
made it intelligible. This is a theory very remote from the primitive ideas of
mankind and from common notions, so that it is not permitted to divulge it to
the masses or even to many people; indeed, the man who has proved its evidence
is forbidden to reveal it to the man who has no power to discover its truth, for
he would be like his murderer. And as to the term `substance’ which the
philosophers give to that which is separate from matter, the First has the
highest claim on the term `substance’, the terms `existent’, `knowing’,
`living’, and all the terms for the qualities it bestows on the existents and
especially those attributes which belong to perfection, for the philosophers
found that the proper definition of substance was what existed by itself and the
First was the cause of everything that existed by itself.
To
all the other reproofs which he levels against this doctrine no attention need
be paid, except in front of the masses and the ordinary man, to whom, however,
this discussion is forbidden.
And as to Ghazali’s
words:
What beauty can there be in mere existence which has no quiddity, no essence, which observes neither what occurs in the world nor what is a consequence or proceeds from its own essence? . . .
-this
whole statement is worthless, for if the philosophers assume a quiddity free
from a substratum it is also void of attributes, and it cannot be a substratum
for attributes except by being itself in a substratum and being composed of the
nature of potency and the nature of act. The First possesses a quiddity that
exists absolutely, and all other existents receive their quiddity only from it,
and this First Principle is the existent which knows existents absolutely,
because existents become existent and intelligible only through the knowledge
this principle has of itself; for since this First Principle is the cause of the
existence and intelligibility of existents, of their existence through its
quiddity and of their intelligibility through its knowledge, it is the cause of
the existence and intelligibility of their quiddities. The philosophers only
denied that its knowledge of existents could take place in the same way as human
knowledge which is their effect, whereas for God’s knowledge the reverse is
the case. For they had established this superhuman knowledge by proof. According
to the Ash’arites, however, God possesses neither quiddity nor essence at all
but the existence of an entity neither possessing nor being a quiddity cannot be
understood, ‘ although some Ash’arites believed that God has a special
quiddity by which He differs from all other existents, ‘ and according to the
Sufis it is this quiddity which is meant by the highest name of God.
And as to Ghazali’s
words:
Further, there may be said to them: `Although you plunge yourself in these shameful doctrines, you cannot free yourselves from plurality, for we ask: “Is the knowledge He has of His essence identical with His essence or not?” If you say, “No”, you introduce plurality, and if you say, “they are identical”, what then is the difference between you and a man who said that a man’s knowledge of his essence was identical with his essence?’
I
say:
This
is an extremely weak statement, and a man who speaks like this deserves best to
be put to shame and dishonoured. For the consequence he draws amounts to saying
that the perfect one, who is free from the attributes of becoming and change and
imperfection, might have the attribute of a being possessing imperfection and
change. For a man indeed it is necessary, in so far as he is composed of a
substratum and knowledge, which exists in this substratum, that his knowledge
should differ from his essence in such a way as has been described before, since
the substratum is the cause of change in the knowledge and the essence. And
since man is man and the most noble of all sentient beings only through the
intellect which is conjoined to his essence, but not by being essentially
intellect, it is necessary that that which is intellect by its essence should be
the most noble of all existents and that it should be free from the
imperfections which exist in the human intellect. ‘
And as to Ghazali’s
words:
And if it be said: His essence is intellect and knowledge and He has not an essence in which afterwards knowledge exists, we answer: `The foolishness of this is evident, for knowledge is an attribute and an accident which demands a subject, and to say “He is in His essence intellect and knowledge” is like saying “He is power and will, and power and will exist by themselves”, and this again is like saying of black and white, fourness and threeness, and all other accidents that they exist by themselves. ‘
I
say:
The
error and confusion in his statement is very evident, for it has been proved
that there is among attributes one that has a greater claim to the term
`substantiality’ than the substance existing by itself, and this is the
attribute through which the substance existing by itself becomes existing by
itself. For it has been proved that the substratum for this attribute is
something neither existing by itself nor existing in actuality; no, its existing
by itself and its actual existence derive from this attribute, and this
attribute in its existence is like that which receives the accidents, although
certain of these attributes, as is evident from their nature, need a substratum
in the changeable things, since it is the fundamental law of the accidents, that
they exist in something else, whereas the fundamental law of the quiddities is
that they exist by themselves, except when, in the sublunary world, these
quiddities need a substratum through being in transitory i things. But this
attribute is at the greatest distance from the nature of an accident, and to
compare this transcendent knowledge to sublunary accidents is extremely foolish,
indeed more foolish than to consider the soul an accident like threeness and
fourness.
And this suffices to show the incoherence and the foolishness of this whole argument, and let us rather call this book simply `The Incoherence’, not `The Incoherence of the Philosophers’. And what is further from the nature of an accident than the nature of knowledge, and especially the knowledge of the First? And since it is at the greatest distance from the nature of an accident, it is at the greatest distance from having a necessity for a substratum.
Ghazali says:
Indeed, they are all of this opinion, and they deduce from this that, since nothing can share its genus, it cannot be differentiated through a specific difference and cannot have a definition, since a definition is constructed out of genus and specific difference and what has no composition cannot have a definition, for a definition is a kind of composition. ‘ And they affirm that, since the First is said to resemble the first effect in being an existent and a substance and a cause for other things, and to differ from it in other respects, this certainly does not imply sharing in its genus; no, it is nothing but a sharing in a common necessary attribute. The difference between genus and necessary attribute consists in their content, not in universality, according to logical theory, for the genus, namely, the essential universal, is the answer to the question what the thing is, and is subsumed under the quiddity of the thing defined, and constitutes its essence: a man’s being alive is subsumed under the quiddity of man, i. e. his animality, and is his genus, but his being born and created are his necessary attributes, and, although they are universals which can never be separated from him, are not subsumed under his quiddity, according to logical theory, about which there can be no misgiving. ; And the philosophers affirm that existence is never subsumed under the quiddity of things, but stands in a relation to the quiddity, either necessarily and inseparably, like its relation to heaven, or subsequently, after their nonexistence, like its relation to temporary things, and that the sharing of existence does not imply a sharing in genus. And as to its sharing in ‘being a cause to other things’ with all the other causes, this is a necessary relation which likewise cannot be subsumed under the quiddity, s for neither the fact of being a principle nor existence constitutes the essence, but they are necessary attributes of the essence, consequent upon the constitution of the essence out of the parts of its quiddity, and this community is only the sharing of a necessary common attribute consecutive to the essence, not a community of genus. Things therefore are only defined by their constituents, and if they are defined by the necessary attributes this is only a description’ to differentiate them, not to define their essential forms; for the triangle is not defined by the fact that its angles are equal to two right angles, although this is a necessary and common attribute of all triangles, but it is defined as a figure bounded by three sides. And the same applies to its being a substance, and the meaning of its being a substance is that it is an existent which does not exist in a substratum. ‘ And the existent is not a genus, since, as it is related to a negation, namely not being in a substratum, it cannot become a constituent genus; indeed, even if it could be brought into a relation to something positive and it could be said that it existed in a substratum, it could not become a genus in the accident. And the reason is that the man who knows substance by its definition, which is rather its description, namely that it is an existent which does not exist in a substratum, does not know whether it exists, and a fortiori does not know whether it exists in a substratum or not; no, the meaning of the description of substance is that it is the existent which does not exist in a substratum, i. e. that it is a certain reality which, when it does exist, does not exist in a substratum, but we do not mean that it actually exists at the time of the definition, and its community is not the community of the genus, for only the constituents of the quiddity form the community of the genus which needs also a specific differences But the First has no other quiddity, except necessary existence, and necessary existence is its real nature and its own quiddity, exclusively confined to it, and since necessary existence is exclusively confined to the First, it cannot be shared by others, it cannot have a specific difference, and it cannot have a definition.
I say:
Here
ends what Ghazali says of the philosophical
views about this question, and it is partly true, partly false. As to his
statement that no other thing can share with the First its genus and be
distinguished from it through a specific difference, if he means by this the
genus and the difference that are predicated univocally, it is true, for
anything of this description is composed of a common form and a specific form,
and such things possess a definition. But if by ‘genus’ is meant what is
predicated analogically, I mean pier prius et piosterius, then it can have a
genus, e. g. existent, or thing, or identity, or essence, and it can have a kind
of definition, and this kind of definition is used in the sciences-for instance,
when it is said of the soul that it is the entelechy of the natural organic
body, a and when it is said of the substance that it is the existent which does
not exist in a substratum -but these definitions do not suffice for knowledge of
the thing, and they are only given to indicate through it the different
individuals which fall under such definitions and to represent their
peculiarities. But as to his statement that according to the philosophers the
term ‘existence’ only indicates a necessary attribute of the essences of
things, this is not true, and we have already explained this in another place
and none of the philosophers has said this but Avicenna. Having denied that
existence is a genus, predicted either univocally or equivocally, Avicenna
affirmed that it was a term which signified a common necessary attribute of
things. But the difficulty he found in regarding existence as an essence can be
held up against him when it is regarded as a necessary attribute, for if it were
a necessary attribute, this necessary attribute could not be given as an answer
to the question what a thing is. I And further, if ‘existence’ really
signifies a necessary attribute in things, does it signify this necessary
attribute univocally, or equivocally, or in some other mode of attribution? And
if it has a univocal meaning, how can there be an accident univocally predicated
of things essentially different (I believe that Avicenna regarded this as
possible)? z It is, however, impossible, because from different things the
congruous and identical can only derive, when these different things agree in
one nature, since necessarily a single necessary attribute must come from one
nature, just as a single act can proceed only from one nature. And since this is
impossible, the term ‘existence’ indicates essences which have analogical
meanings, essences some of which are more perfect than others; and therefore
there exists in the things which have such an existence a principle which is the
cause of that which exists in all the other things of this genus, just as our
term ‘warm’ is a term which is predicated per
prius et posterius of fire and all other warm things, and that of which it
is asserted first, i. e. fire, is the cause of the existence of warmth in all
other things, and the same is the case with substance, intellect, and principle
and such terms (most metaphysical terms are of this kind), and such terms can
indicate both substances and accidents.
And
what he says of the description of substance is devoid of sense, but existence
is the genus of substance and is included in its definition in the way the
genera of the sublunary things are included in their definitions, and Farabi
proved this in his book about demonstration, and this is the commonest view
amongst philosophers. Avicenna erred in this only because, since he thought that
the ‘existent’ means the ‘true’ in the Arabic language, and that what
indicates the true indicates an accident4-the true, however, really indicates
one of the second, predicates, i. e. a predicable-he believed that when the
translator used the word ‘existent’ it meant only the ‘true’. This,
however, is not so, for the translators meant only to indicate what is also
meant by ‘entity’ and ‘thing’. Farabi explains this in his Book of the Letters and he shows that one of the reasons for the
occurrence of this mistake is that the term ‘existent’ in Arabic is a
derivative in form and that a derivative signifies an accident, and in fact an
accident is linguistically a derivative. But since the translators did not find
in Arabic a term which signified that concept which the ancient philosophers
subdivided into substance and accident, potency and act, a term namely which
should be a primitive symbol, some translators signified that concept by the
term ‘existent’, not to be understood as having a derivative meaning and
signifying therefore an accident, but as having the same meaning as
‘essence’. It is thus a technical term, not an idiomatic word. Some
translators, because of the difficulty attached to it, decided to use for the
concept, which the Greek language tried to express by deriving it from the
pronoun which joins the predicate and the subject, the term which expresses
this, because they thought that this word comes nearer to expressing this
meaning, and they used instead of the term ‘existent’ the term ‘haeceitas’,
but the fact that its grammatical form is not found in Arabic hindered its use,
and the other party therefore preferred the term ‘existent’. -, And the term
‘existent’ which signifies the true does not signify the quiddity, and
therefore one may often know the quiddity without knowing the existence, and
this meaning of ‘existent’ of necessity does not signify the quiddity in the
compound substance, but is in the simple substance identical with the quiddity;
and this meaning is not what the translators intended by ‘existence’, for
they meant the quiddity itself, and when we say of the existent that it is in
part substance, in part accident, the sense meant by the translators must be
understood, and this is the sense which is predicated analogically of different
essences of things. When we say, however, that substance exists, it must be
understood in the sense of the true. And therefore if we have understood the
well-known discussion of the ancient philosophers, whether the existent is one
or more than one, which is found in the first book of Aristotle’s Physics
where he conducts a discussion with the ancient philosophers Parmenides and
Melissus, s we need only understand by ‘existent’ that which signifies the
essence. And if the ‘existent’ meant an accident in a substratum, then the
statement that the existent was one would be self-contradictory. ‘ And all
this is clear for the man who is well grounded in the books of the philosophers.
And having stated the views of the
philosophers, Ghazali begins to refute them, and
says:
This is the sense of the doctrine of the philosophers. And the discussion with them consists of two parts: a question and a refutation. The question is: This is the simple narration of your doctrine, but how do you know the impossibility of this with respect to God, so as to build on it the refutation of dualism, since you say that a second God would have to participate in something and differ from the first in something, and that which partly possesses something in common with another, partly is different from it, is compound, whereas that He should be compound is absurd?
I say:
I
have already said that this is only valid for something which possesses a common
feature through a genus which is predicated univocally, not analogically. For
if, by the assumption of a second God, a God were assumed of the same rank of
divinity as the first, then the name of God would be predicated univocally, and
He would be a genus, and the two Gods would have to be separated by a specific
distinction and both would be compounded of a genus and a specific distinction,
and the philosophers do not allow a genus to an eternal being; but if the term
‘existence’ is predicated per prius et
posterius, the prior will be the cause of the posterior.
Ghazali says, refuting the
philosophers:
But we say: How do you know the impossibility of this kind of composition? For there is no proof except your denial of the attributes, which has been mentioned, namely that the compound of genus and species is an aggregate of parts; thus if it is possible for one or for a collection of the parts to exist without the others, this single one will be the necessary existent and the others will not be necessary; and if it is possible neither for the parts to exist without the totality, nor for the totality to exist without the parts, then the whole is an effect needing something else as its cause. We have already discussed this in the case of the attributes, and have shown that their plurality is not impossible, since an end of the causal series is admitted and all that is proved is that there is an end of the causal series. For those enormous difficulties which the philosophers have invented concerning the inherence of attributes in the necessary existent there is no proof whatever. If the necessary existent is what the philosophers describe it to be, namely to possess no plurality and not to need anything else for its existence, then there is no proof of the existence of this necessary existent; the only thing proved is that there is an end of the causal series, and we have exhausted this subject in our discussion of attributes. And for this kind of plurality it is still more obvious, for the division of a thing into genus and specific difference is not like the division of the subject into essence and attribute, since, indeed, the attribute is not the essence and the essence is not the attribute, but the species is not in every way different from the genus, for whenever we mention the species, we mention the genus with an addition, and when we speak of a man we only mention animal with the addition of reason. ‘ And to ask whether humanity can be free from animality is like asking whether humanity can be without itself, when something is added to it. And indeed genus and species are more distant from plurality than attribute and subject. ‘ And why should it be impossible that the causal series should end in two causes, one the cause of the heavens and the other the cause of the elements, or one the cause of the intellects and the other the cause of all bodies, and that there should be between those two causes a conceptual difference and separation as between redness and warmth when they exist in one and the same place? For they differ in content without our being obliged to assume in the redness a compound of genus and specific difference through which this difference is established; indeed, if it possesses a plurality, this kind of plurality does not impair the singleness of its essence, and why should this be impossible with respect to the causes? Through this there is shown the weakness of their refutation of the existence of two Gods.
I say:
Composition
out of genus and specific difference is exactly the same as the composition of a
thing in potency and a thing in act, for the nature which is indicated by the
genus does not actually exist at any time without the presence of the nature
which is called specific difference and form. ; And everything which is composed
of these two natures is, according to the philosophers, transitory, and
possesses an agent, for the specific difference is one of the conditions for the
existence of the genus in so far as the genus is in potency and does not exist
without the specific difference. And the conjunction of either with its partner
is in a certain way a condition for the existence of the other. And as a thing
cannot itself be a cause of the condition of its existence, it necessarily
possesses a cause which provides it with existence by conjoining the condition
and the conditioned. Also, according to the philosophers the recipient is in
reality something which possesses only potency, and if it is actually, then only
accidentally; and what is received is actuality, and if it is potency, then only
accidentally; for the recipient and the thing it receives are only distinguished
by the fact that one of them is potentially something else, whereas actually it
is the thing received and whatever is potentially another thing must necessarily
receive this other thing and lose the thing it actually is. ‘ Therefore, if
there should exist a recipient in actuality and a thing received in actuality,
both would exist by themselves, but the recipient is necessarily body, for only
body, or what is in a body, possesses receptivity primarily, and receptivity
cannot be attributed to accidents and forms, nor to the plane, the line, and the
point, ‘ nor in general to what cannot be divided. As regards an incorporeal
agent, this has been already proved, and as to an incorporeal recipient, or a
recipient not embedded in matter, such a recipient is impossible, although there
is a problem for the philosophers about the potential intellects And indeed, if
the compound has a subject and an attribute which is not additional to its
essence, b it is transitory and necessarily a body, and if it has a subject and
an attribute additional to its essence, without its having any potency in its
substance even in respect of this attribute, as is the case according to the
ancients with the body of the heavens, ? it possesses quantity of necessity and
is a body. For, if from such an essence, supporting the attribute, bodiliness
were taken away, it would no longer be a perceptible recipient, and equally the
sensory perception of its attribute would be annulled and its attribute and
subject would both become intellect, and they would be reduced to one single
simple entity, for from the nature of the intellect and the intelligible it is
evident that they are both one and the same thing, since plurality exists in
them accidentally, namely through the substratum. ‘ And in short, when the
philosophers assume an essence and attributes additional to the essence, this
amounts to their assuming an eternal body with accidents inherent in it, and
they do not doubt that if they took away the quantity which is corporeity, the
perceptible element in it would be annulled, and neither substratum nor inherent
would exist any more; but if, on the other hand, they regarded the substratum
and the inherent as abstracted from matter and body, the substratum and inherent
would of necessity be both intellect and intelligible; but this is the Unique,
the Uncompounded, God, the Truth.
As
to his statement that the whole mistake of the philosophers consists in their
calling the First the ‘necessary existent’, and that if instead they called
it ‘the causeless”, the conclusion which they draw about the First,
concerning the necessary attributes of the necessary existent, would not
follow-this statement is not true. For since they assume an existent which has
no cause, it follows necessarily that it is in itself a necessary existent, just
as, when a necessary existent existing by itself is assumed, it follows
necessarily that it has no cause, and if it has no cause it is more appropriate
that it should not be divided into two things, cause and effect. The assumption
of the theologians that the First is composed of an attribute and a subject
implies that it has an efficient cause, ‘ and that therefore it is neither a
first cause nor a necessary existent, and this is in contradiction to their
assumption that it is one of those existents of which the attribute and the
subject are reduced to one single simple entity; but there is no sense in
repeating this and expatiating on it.
And
as to his statement that it is not impossible of God, the First, that He should
be composed of a substratum and an attribute additional to the substratum, and
that therefore a fortiori it is not impossible that He should be composed of a
substratum and an attribute which is identical with its substratum, we have
already explained the way in which this is not impossible, namely when both are
abstract from matter.
And
as to his statement that their refutation of dualism does not prevent the
possibility of the existence of two Gods, one of whom would be, for instance,
the cause of heaven and the other the cause of the earth, or one the cause of
the intelligible and the other the cause of the sensible in the bodies, and that
their differentiation and distinction need not determine a contradiction, as
there is no contradiction in redness and warmth which exist in one place-this
statement is not true. For if the production and creation of the existent is
assumed to be the effect of one nature and of one essence, not of two different
natures, it would necessarily follow that if a second thing of this nature were
assumed, similar in nature and intellect to the first, they would share in one
attribute and differ in another. And their difference would come about either
through the kind of differentiation which exists between individuals or through
the kind of differentiation which exists between species. In the latter case the
term ‘God’ would be predicated of them equivocally, and this is in
contradiction with their assumption, for the species which participate in the
genus are either contraries or stand between contraries, and this is wholly
impossible. And if they were individually differentiated, they would both be in
matter, and this is in opposition to what is agreed about them. But if it is
assumed that one of these natures is superior to the other and that this nature
is predicated of them per prius et posterius, then the first nature will
be superior to the second and the second will be necessarily its effect, so that
for instance the creator of heaven will be the creator of the cause which
creates the elements; and this is the theory of the philosophers. And both
theories lead to the acceptance of a first cause; that of those who believe that
the First acts through the mediation of many causes, and that of those who
believe that the First is directly the cause of all other things without
mediation. But according to the philosophers this latter theory cannot be true.
For it is evident that the worlds exist through cause and effect, and it is
inquiry concerning these causes which leads us to a first cause for everything.
And if some of these different principles were wholly independent of others-that
is, if some were not the cause of others-then the world could not be a single
well connected whole, and to the impossibility of this the Divine Words refer,
‘Were there in both heaven and earth Gods beside God, both surely would have
been corrupted’.
Ghazali says:
It may be said: This is impossible so far as the difference which exists between these two essences is either a condition for their necessary existence (and in that case it will exist in both the necessary existents, and then they will not differ anyhow), or neither the one nor the other specific difference is a condition (and since the necessary existence is able to exist without the things that are not a condition for it, the necessary existence will be perfected by something else).
But we reply: This is exactly the same answer as you gave concerning the attributes and we have already discussed it, ‘ and the source of confusion throughout this problem is the expression ‘necessary existent’; let us therefore get rid of this term; and indeed, we do not accept that demonstration proves a necessary existent, if anything else is meant by it but an eternal existent which has no cause, and if this is meant by it, let us abandon the term ‘necessary existent’ and let it be proved that an existent which has no cause and no agents cannot have a plurality and a distinctive mark, but indeed there is no proof of it. There remains therefore your question whether this specific difference is a condition of the causeless character of this causeless existent, and this is nonsense. For we have shown that there is no cause for its being without a cause, so as to make it possible to ask for its condition. It would be like asking whether blackness is a condition for the colour’s becoming a colour, and if it is a condition, why redness is then a colour. And the answer is: as to the essential nature of colour, i. e. in so far as the essence of colouredness is asserted in the intellect, neither of them is a condition, < and as to its existence, each of them is a condition for its existence, but not individually, since a genus cannot exist in reality without a specific differences And likewise the man who accepts two causes as starting-points of the series must say that they are differentiated through a specific difference, and both differences are a condition for their existence, no doubt, though not through their individuality.
I say:
The
summary of what he says here of the proof of the philosophers is that they say
that the specific difference through which the duality in the necessary existent
occurs is either a condition or not a condition for necessary existence. If the
specific difference through which they are distinguished is a condition for both
the necessary existents, they will no longer be separated in their necessary
existence and the necessary existent will be of necessity one and the same, just
as, if black were to be a condition for the necessity of colour and white a
condition for colouredness, they could not differ
in colouredness. If, on the other hand, the specific difference does not enter into the essence of necessary existence,
then both these necessary existents will have necessary existence only by
accident, and their duality will not be based on their both being necessary
existents. This, however, is not true, for the species are a condition for the
existence of the genus, and both colours are a condition for the existence of
the genus, though not individually (for in this case they could not exist
together in the existence of the colour).
Ghazali
opposes this statement with two arguments. The first is that this can only
happen in so far as ‘necessary existent’ means a special nature; according
to the theologians, however, this is not the case, for they understand by
‘necessary existent’ only something negative, namely something which has no
cause, and since negative things are not caused, how can, for the denial of the
causeless, an argument like the following be used: ‘That which distinguishes
one causeless entity from another causeless entity is either a condition of its
being causeless or not; if it is a condition, there cannot be any plurality or
differentiation; and if it is not a condition, it cannot occasion a plurality in
the causeless, which therefore will be one. ‘ However, the erroneous part in Ghazali’s reasoning is that he regards the causeless as a mere
negation, and, as a negation has no cause, he asks how it could possess a
condition which is the cause of its existence. But this is a fallacy, for
particular negations, which are like infinite terms and which are used for
distinguishing between existents, , have causes and conditions which determine
this negation in them, just as they have causes and conditions which determine
their positive qualities; and in this sense there is no difference between
positive and negative attributes, and the necessity of the necessary existent is
a necessary attribute of the causeless and there is no difference between saying
‘the necessary existent’ or ‘the causeless’.
And
the nonsense comes from those who talk like Ghazali,
not from his opponents.
And
the summary of Ghazali’s second objection is
that to say, as the philosophers do, that the specific difference through which
the necessary existent is distinguished is either a condition or not, that in
the former case the one necessary existent cannot be distinguished from the
other in so far as they are necessarily existent and that therefore the
necessary existent is one, and that in the latter case the necessary existent
has no specific difference through which it can be divided: that to speak like
this is like saying that if there exist more colours than one of the genus
colour, the difference through which one colour is distinguished from another is
either a condition for the existence of colour or not; that in the former case
the one cannot be distinguished from the other in so far as they are colour, and
colour is therefore one single nature; that in the latter case, if neither of
them is a condition for the existence of colouredness, one colour has no
specific difference through which it can be distinguished from another, and this
is not true. ‘
Ghazali says, answering this problem on
behalf of the philosophers:
It may be said perhaps: This is possible in the case of colour, for it has an existence related to the quiddity and additional to the quiddity, but it is not possible for the necessary existent, for it possesses only necessary existence, and there is therefore no quiddity to which its existence might be related, and just as the specific differences of black and red are not conditions for colouredness being colouredness, but only a condition for the actual realization of colour through a cause, , in the same way the specific difference cannot be a condition for necessary existence, for necessary existence is in relation to the First what colouredness is in relation to the colour, and not like the existence brought in relation to colouredness.
But we reply, we do not accept this; on the contrary, the necessary existent has a real essence to which existence is attributed, as we shall show in the next discussion, and their statement that the First is an existence without quiddity is incomprehensible. The trend of their argument is, in short, that they base their denial of dualism on the denial that the First is composed of the generic and the specific, then they base the denial of this on their denial that there is a quiddity behind the existence. Therefore as soon as we have refuted this last proposition, which is their fundamental principle, their whole structure (which is a very shaky fabrication, just like a spider’s web) tumbles down.
I say:
Ghazali builds
the answer he gives here in the name of the philosophers on their statement that
existence is an accident in the existent, i. e. the quiddity, and he objects
against them that the existence in everything is something different from the
essence, and he affirms that their whole argument is built only on this. ‘ But
the distinction which the philosophers make here does not save them from the
implication held against them about colouredness and its specific differences,
in whatever way they may turn the question. Indeed, nobody doubts that the
specific differences of the genus are the cause of the genus, whether it is
assumed that the existence of the genus is different from its essence, or that
the essence and existence of the genus are identical; for if the specific
differences were differences in the existence, and the existence of the colour
were different from the quiddity of the colour, it would follow that the
specific differences by which the colour is divided are not differences in the
quiddity of the colour, but differences in one of its accidents, and this is an
absurd assumption. Therefore the truth is to say, ‘When we divide colour by
its specific differences, the existence of the colour in so far as it is colour
is only actual, either because it is white, or because it is black or any other
colour. Thus we do not divide an accident of the colour, but we divide only the
essence of the colour. Through this solution the statement that existence is an
accident in the existent is seen to be false, and the argument and his answer
arc unsound.
As to Ghazali’s
words:
They base their denial of dualism on the denial that the First is composed of the generic and the specific, then they base the denial of this on the denial that there is a quiddity behind the existence. Therefore as soon as we have refuted this last proposition, which is their fundamental principle, their whole structure tumbles down.
I say:
This
argument is not sound, for their structure, the denial of individual duality
attributed to simple things univocally, is self-evident, for if we assume a
duality and two simple things possessing a common trait, the simple becomes a
compounds And the summary of the philosophical proof for this is that the nature
called ‘necessary existent’, i. e. the cause which has no cause and which is
a cause for other things, must be either numerically one or many; if many, it
must be many through its form, one through the genus predicated univocally of
it, or one through a relation, or one through the term only. b If it is like
Zaid and Amr individually differentiated and specifically one, then it
necessarily possesses hyle, and this is impossible. If it is differentiated
through its form, but one through the genus predicated univocally of it, then it
is necessarily composite. If it is one in its genus, predicated by analogy to
one thing, there is no objection, and one
part of it will be the cause of another and the series will end in a first
cause, and this is what happens with the forms abstracted from matter, according
to the philosophers. If it is only common through the term, then there is no
objection to its being more than one, and this is the case with the four primary
causes, i. e. the first agent, the ultimate form, the ultimate end, the ultimate
matter. ‘ Therefore, no strict proof is attained through this method, and one
does not arrive at the First Principle as Avicenna thought; nor to its being
necessarily one.
Ghazali says:
The second way is the drawing of the consequence, and we say: If existence, substantiality and being a principle are not a genus, because they do not give an answer to the question ‘What is it? ‘, then according to you the First is pure intellect just like the other intellects which are the principles of existence, called angels, according to the philosophers, and which are the effects of the First, are intellects separate from matter. And this abstract reality comprises the First and the first effect. This First, further, is according to the philosophers simple, and there is no compound in its essence except through its necessary attributes, and both the First Cause and the first effect participate in being intellect without matter. This, however, is a generic reality. Nor is intellectuality, separate from matter, a necessary attribute, for it is indeed a quiddity, and this quiddity is common to the First and all the other intellects. Therefore, if they do not differ in anything else, you have necessarily conceived a duality without a further difference; and if they do differ, what then is this distinction apart from their intellectuality, which they have in common? For what they have in common is participation in this abstract reality. For indeed the First is conscious of its own self and of others, according to those who believe that it is in its es3ence intellect separate from matter; and also the first effect, which is the first intellect which God has created without a mediator, participates in this characteristic. This proves that the intellects which are effects are different species, that they only participate in intellectuality and are besides this distinguished by specific differences, and that likewise the First participates with all the other intellects in this intellectuality. The philosophers, therefore, are either in plain contradiction to their own fundamental thesis, or have to affirm that intellectuality does not constitute God’s essence. And both positions are absurd according to them.
I say:
If you have understood what we have said before this, that there are
things which have a term in common not univocally or equivocally, but by the
universality of terms analogically related to one thing, and that the
characteristic of these things is that they lead upwards to a first term in this
genus which is the first cause of everything to which this word refers, like
warmth, which is predicated of fire and all other warm things, and like the term
‘existent’ which is predicated of the substance and all other accidents, and
like the term ‘movement’ predicated of motion in space and all the other
movements, you will not have to occupy yourself with the mistakes in this
reasoning. For the term ‘intellect’ is predicated analogically of the
separate intellects according to the philosophers, and there is among them a
first intellect which is the cause of all the other intellects, and the same
thing is true of substance. And the proof that they have not one nature in
common is that some of them are the causes of others and the cause of a thing is
prior to the effect, and the nature of cause and effect cannot be one in genus
except in the individual causes, and this kind of community is contradictory to
genuine generic community, for things which participate in genus have no first
principle which is the cause of all the others-they are all of the same rank,
and there is no simple principle in them-whereas the things which participate in
something predicated of them analogically must have a simple first principle.
And in this First no duality can be imagined, for if a second were assumed, it
must be of the same level of existence and of the same nature as the First, and
they would have one nature in common in which they would participate by generic
participation and would have to be distinguished through specific differences,
additional to the genus, and both would be composed of genus and specific
difference, and everything which is of this description is temporal; and lastly
that which is of the extreme perfection i of existence must be unique, for if it
were not unique, it could not be of the extreme perfection of existence, for
that which is in the extreme degree cannot participate with anything else, for
in the same way as one single line cannot have two extreme points at the same
end, things extended in existence and differentiated through increase s and
decrease have not two extremes at the same side. And since Avicenna was not
aware of this nature, which stands midway between the nature of that which is
univocally predicated and those natures which participate only through the
equivocation of the term or in a distant, accidental way, this objection was
valid against him.
Ghazali
says:
There are two ways of attacking this theory. The first is to demand a proof and to ask how you know this, through the necessity of the intellect, or through speculation and not by immediate necessity; and in any case you must tell us your method of reasoning.
If it is said that, if the First had a quiddity, its existence would be related to it, and would be consequent’ on this quiddity and would be its necessary attribute, and the consequent is an effect and therefore necessary existence would be an effect, and this is a contradiction, we answer: This is to revert to the source of the confusion in the application of the term ‘necessary existence’, for we call this entity ‘reality’ or ‘quiddity’ and this reality exists, i. e. it is not non-existent and is not denied, but its existence is brought into a relation with it, and if you like to call this ‘consequent’ and ‘necessary attribute’, we shall not quibble about words, if you have once acknowledged that it has no agent for its existence and that this existence has not ceased to be eternal and to have no efficient cause; if, however, you understand by ‘consequent’ and ‘effect’ that it has an efficient cause, this is not true. But if you mean something else, this is conceded, for it is not impossible, z since the demonstration proves only the end of a causal series and its ending in an existent reality; a positive quiddity, therefore, is possible, and there is no need to deny the quiddity.
If it is said: Then the quiddity becomes a cause for the existence which is consequent on it, and the existence becomes an effect and an object of the act, we answer: The quiddity in temporal things is not a cause of their existence, and why should it therefore be the case in the eternal, if you mean by ‘cause’ the agent? But if you mean something else by it, namely that without which it could not be, let that be accepted, for there is nothing impossible in it; the impossibility lies only in the infinite causal series, and if this series only comes to a final term, then the impossibility is cancelled; impossibility can be understood only on this point, therefore you must give a proof of its impossibility.
All the proofs of the philosophers are nothing but presumptions that the term has a sense from which certain consequences follow, and nothing but the supposition that demonstration has in fact proved a necessary existent with the meaning the philosophers ascribed to it. We have, however, shown previously that this is not true. In short, this proof of the philosophers comes down to the proof of the denial of attributes and of the division into genus and specific difference; only this proof is still more ambiguous and weak, for this plurality is purely verbal, for the intellect does allow the acceptance of one single existent quiddity. The philosophers, however, say that every existent quiddity is a plurality, for it contains quiddity and existence, and this is an extreme confusion; for the meaning of a single existent is perfectly understandable-nothing exists which has no essence, and the existence of an essence does not annul its singleness.
I
say:
Ghazali
does not relate Avicenna’s doctrine literally as he did in his book The Aims of the Philosophers.
‘ For since Avicenna believed that the existence of a thing indicated an
attribute additional to its essence, he could no longer admit that its essence
was the agent of its existence out of the possibles, for then the thing would be
the cause of its own existence and it would not have an agent. It follows from
this, according to Avicenna, that everything which has an existence additional
to its essence has an efficient cause, and since according to Avicenna the First
has no agent, it follows necessarily that its existence is identical with its
essence. z And therefore Ghazali’s objection
that Avicenna assimilates existence to a necessary attribute of the essence is
not true, because the essence of a thing is the cause of its necessary attribute
and it is not possible that a thing should be the cause of its own existence,
because the existence of a thing is prior to its quiddity. To identify the
quiddity and the existence of a thing is not to do away with its quiddity, as Ghazali
asserts, but is only the affirmation of the unity of quiddity and existence. If
we regard existence as an accidental attribute of the existent, and it is the
agent which gives possible things their existence, necessarily that which has no
agent either cannot have an existence (and this is absurd), or its existence
must be identical with its essence.
But
the whole of this discussion is built on the mistake that the existence of a
thing is one of its attributes. For the existence which in our knowledge is
prior to the quiddity of a thing is that which signifies the true. Therefore the
question whether a thing exists, either (i) refers to that which has a cause
that determines its existence, and in that case its potential meaning is to ask
whether this thing has a cause or not, according to Aristotle at the beginning
of the second chapter of the Posterior
Analytics;s or (2) it refers to that which has no cause, and then its
meaning is to ask whether a thing possesses a necessary attribute which
determines its existence. ‘ And when by ‘existent’ is meant what is
understood by ‘thing’ and ‘entity’, it follows the rule of the genus
which is predicated analogically, and whatever it is in this sense is attributed
in the same way to that which has a cause and to that which has none, and it
does not signify anything but the concept of the existent, and by this is meant
‘the true’, and if it means something additional to the essence, it is only
in a subjective sense which does not exist outside the soul except potentially,
as is also the case with the universal. And this is the way in which the ancient
philosophers considered the First Principle, and they regarded it as a simple
existent. As to the later philosophers in Islam, they stated that, in their
speculation about the nature of the existent qua
existent, they were led to accept a simple existent of this description.
The
best method to follow, in my opinion, and the nearest to strict proof, is to say
that the actualization of existents which have in their substance a possible
existence necessarily occurs only through an actualizer which is in act, i. e.
acting, and moves them and draws them out of potency into act. And if this
actualizer itself is also of the nature of the possible, i. e. possible in its
substance, there will have to be another actualizer for it, necessary in its
substance and not possible, so that this sublunary world may be conserved, and
the nature of the possible causes may remain everlastingly, proceeding without
end. And if these causes exist without end, as appears from their nature, and
each of them is possible, necessarily their cause, i. e. that which determines
their permanence, must be something necessary in its substance, and if there
were a moment in which nothing was moved at all, there would be no possibility
of an origination of movements The nexus between temporal existence and eternal
can only take place without a change affecting the First through that movement
which is partly eternal, partly temporal. b And the thing moved by this movement
is what Avicenna calls ‘the existence necessary through another’, and this
‘necessary through another’ must be a body everlastingly moved, and in this
way it is possible that the essentially temporal and corruptible should exist in
dependence on the eternal, and this through approach to something and through
recession from it, as you observe it happen to transitory existents in relation
to the heavenly bodies. ? And since this moved body is necessary in its
substance, possible in its local movement, it is necessary that the process
should terminate in an absolutely necessary existent in which there is no
potency at all, either in its substance, or locally or in any of the other forms
of movement; and that which is of this description is necessarily simple,
because if it were a compound, it would be possible, not necessary, and it would
require a necessary existent. And this method of proving it is in my opinion
sufficient, and it is true.
However,
what Avicenna adds to this proof by saying that the possible existent must
terminate either in an existent necessary through another or in an existent
necessary through itself, and in the former case that the necessary through
another should be a consequence of the existent necessary through itself, for he
affirms that the existent necessary through another is in itself a possible
existent and what is possible needs something necessary-this addition, is to my
mind superfluous and erroneous, for in the necessary, in whatever way you
suppose it, there is no possibility whatsoever and there exists nothing of a
single nature of which it can be said that it is in one way possible and in
another way necessary in its existence. ‘ For the philosophers have proved
that there is no possible whatsoever in the necessary; for the possible is the
opposite of the necessary, and the only thing that can happen is that a thing
should be in one way necessary, in another way possible, as they believed for
instance to be the case with the heavenly body or what is above the body of the
heavens, namely that it was necessary through its substance and possible in its
movement and in space. What led Avicenna to this division was that he believed
that the body of the heavens was essentially necessary through another, possible
by itself, and we have shown in another place that this is not true. And the
proof which Avicenna uses in dealing with the necessary existent, when this
distinction and this indication are not made, is of the type of common
dialectical notions; when, however, the distinction is made, it is of i the type
of demonstrative proof.
You
must know further that the becoming of which the Holy Law speaks is of the kind
of empirical becoming in this world, and this occurs in the forms of the
existents which the Ash’arites call mental qualitiesand the philosophers call
forms, and this becoming occurs only through another thing and in time, and the
Holy Words: ‘Have not those who have disbelieved considered that the heavens
and the earth were coherent, and we have rent them . . . ‘and the Divine Words
‘then he straightened himself up to the sky which was smoke . . . ‘, refer
to this. But as to the relation which exists between the nature of the possible
existent and the necessary existent, about this the Holy Law is silent, because
it is too much above the understanding of the common man and knowledge of it is
not necessary for his blessedness. When the Ash’arites affirm that the nature
of the possible’ is created and has come into existence in time out of nothing
(a notion which all the philosophers oppose, whether they believe in the
temporal beginning of the world or not), they do not say this, if you consider
the question rightly, on the authority of the law of Islam, and there is no
proof for it. What appears from the Holy Law is the commandment to abstain from
investigating that about which the Holy Law is silent, and therefore it is said
in the Traditions: ‘The people did not cease thinking till they said: God has
created this, but who has created God? And the Prophet said: When one of you
finds this, this is an act of pure faith’, and in another version: ‘When one
of you finds this, let him read the verse of the Qur’an: Say, He, God is one.
And know that for the masses to turn to such a question comes from the
whisperings of Satan and therefore the prophet said: This is an act of pure
faith.
Ghazali
says:
The second way is to say that an existence without quiddity or essence cannot be conceived, and just as mere non-existence, without a relation to an existent the non-existence of which can be supposed, cannot be conceived, in the same way existence can be only conceived in relation to a definite essence, especially when it is defined as a single essence; for how could it be defined as single, conceptually differentiated from others, if it had not a real essence? For to deny the quiddity is to deny the real essence, and when you deny the real essence of the existent, the existent can no longer be understood. It is as if the philosophers affirmed at the same time existence and a non-existent, which is contradictory. This is shown by the fact that, if it were conceivable, it would be also possible in the effects that there should be an existence without an essence, participating with the First in not having a real essence and a quiddity, differing from it in having a cause, whereas the First is causeless. And why should such an effect not be imagined? And is there any other reason for this than that it is inconceivable in itself? But what is inconceivable in itself does not become conceivable by the denial of its cause, nor does what is conceivable become inconceivable because it is supposed to have a cause. Such an extreme negation is the most obscure of their theories, although they believe indeed that they have proved what they say. Their doctrine ends in absolute negation, and indeed the denial of the quiddity is the denial of the real essence, and through the denial of this reality nothing remains but the word ‘existence’, which has no object at all when it is not related to a quiddity. ‘
And if it is said: ‘Its real essence is that it is the necessary, and the necessary is its quiddity’, we answer: ‘The only sense of “necessary” is “causeless”, and this is a negation which does not constitute a real essence; and the denial of a cause for the real essence presupposes the real essence, and therefore let the essence be conceivable, so that it can be described as being causeless; but the essence cannot be represented as non-existent, since “necessity” has no other meaning than “being causeless”. ‘ Besides, if the necessity were added to the existence, this would form a plurality; and if it is not added, how then could it be the quiddity? For the existence is not the quiddity, and thus what is not added to the existence cannot be the quiddity either. ‘
I
say:
This
whole paragraph is sophistry. For the philosophers do not assume that the First
has an existence without a quiddity and a quiddity without an existence. They
believe only that the existence in the compound is an additional attribute to
its essence and it only acquires this attribute through the agent, and they
believe that in that which is simple and causeless this attribute is not
additional to the quiddity and that it has no quiddity differentiated from its
existence; but they do not say that it has absolutely no quiddity, as he assumes
in his objection against them.
Having
assumed that they deny the quiddity-which is false Ghazali
begins now to charge them with reprehensible theories and says:
If this were conceivable it would also be possible in the effects that there should be an existence without an essence, participating with the First in not having a real essence.
I
say:
But
the philosophers do not assume an existent absolutely without a quiddity: they
only assume that it has not a quiddity like the quiddities of the other
existents; and this is one of the sophistical fallacies, for the term
‘quiddity’ is ambiguous, and this assumption, and everything built upon it,
is a sophistical argument, for the non-existent cannot be described either by
denying or by affirming something of
it. And Ghazali, by fallacies of the kind
perpetrated in this book, is not exempt from wickedness or from ignorance, and
he seems nearer to wickedness than to ignorance-or should we say that there is a
necessity which obliged him to do this?
And
as to his remark, that the meaning of ‘necessary existent’ is ,
causeless’, this is not true, but our expression that it is a necessary
existent has a positive meaning, consequent on a nature which has absolutely no
cause, no exterior agent, and no agent which is part of it.
And
as to Ghazali’s words:
If the necessity were added to the existence, this would form a plurality; and if it is not added, how then could it be the quiddity? For existence is not the quiddity, and thus what is not added to the existence cannot be the quiddity either.
I
say:
According to the philosophers necessity is not an attribute added to the essence, and it is predicated of the essence in the same way as we say of it that it is inevitable and eternal. ‘ And likewise if we understand by ‘existence’ a mental attribute, it is not an addition to the essence, but if we understand it as being an accident, in the way Avicenna regards it in the composite existent, then it becomes difficult to explain how the uncompounded can be the quiddity itself, although one might say perhaps: ‘In the way the knowledge in the uncompounded becomes the knower himself. ‘ If, however, one regards the existent as the true, all these doubts lose their meaning, and likewise, if one understands ‘existent’ as having the same sense as ‘entity’, and according to this it is true that the existence in the uncompounded is the quiddity itself.
Ghazali
says:
There is a proof only for him who believes that body is only temporal, because it cannot be exempt from what is temporal and everything that is temporal needs a creator. But you, when you admit an eternal body which has no beginning for its existence, although it is not exempt from temporal occurrences, why do you regard it as impossible that the First should be a body, either the sun, or the extreme heaven, or something else?
If the answer is made ‘Because body must be composite and divisible into parts quantitatively, and into matter and form conceptually, and into qualities which characterize it necessarily so that it can be differentiated from other bodies (for otherwise all bodies in being body would be similar) and the necessary existent is one and cannot be divided in any of these ways’ we answer: ‘We have already refuted you in this, and have shown that you have no proof for it except that a collection is an effect, since some of its parts require others, and we have argued against it and have shown that when it is not impossible to suppose an existent without a creator, it is not impossible to suppose a compound without a composing principle and to suppose many existents without a creator, since you have based your denial of plurality and duality on the denial of composition and your denial of composition on the denial of a quiddity distinct from existence, and with respect to the last principle we have asked for its foundation and we have shown that it is a mere presumption. ‘
And if it is said: ‘If a body has no soul, it cannot be an agent, and when it has a soul, well, then its soul is its cause, and then body cannot be the First’, we answer: ‘Our soul is not the cause of the existence of our body, nor is the soul of the sphere in itself a cause of its body, according to you, but they are two, having a distinct cause; and if they can be eternal, it is possible that they have no cause. ‘
And if the question is asked, ‘How can the conjunction of soul and body come about? ‘, we answer, ‘One might as well ask how the existence of the First comes about; the answer is that such a question may be asked about what is temporal, but about what is eternally existent one cannot ask how it has come about, and therefore” since body and its soul are both eternally existent, it is not impossible that their compound should be a creator. ‘
I
say:
When
a man has no other proof that the First is not body than that he believes that
all bodies are temporal, how weak is his proof, and how far distant from the
nature of what has to be proved!-since it has been shown previously that the
proofs on which the theologians build their statement that all bodies are
temporal are conflicting; and what is more appropriate than to regard an eternal
composite as possible, as I said in this book when speaking of the Ash’arites,
i. e. in saying that according to them an eternal body is possible, since in the
accidents there is some eternal element, according to their own theory, for
instance, the characteristic of forming a compound; and therefore their proof
that all bodies are temporal is not valid, because they base it exclusively on
the temporal becoming of the accidents. ‘ The ancient philosophers do not
allow for the existence of a body eternal through itself, but only of one
eternal through another, and therefore according to them there must be an
existent eternal through itself through which the eternal body becomes eternal.
But if we expound their theories here, they have only a dialectical value, and
you should therefore instead ask for their proofs in their proper place.
And
as to Ghazali’s refutation of this, and his
words:
We answer: ‘We have already refuted you in this, and we have shown that you have no proof for this except that a collection is an effect, since some of its parts require others.
I
say:
He
means that he has discussed this already previously, and he says that the
philosophers cannot prove that the existent necessary through itself is not a
body, since the meaning of ‘existent necessary through itself’ is ‘that
which has no efficient cause’, and why should they regard an eternal body
which has no efficient cause as impossible-and especially when it should be
supposed to be a simple body, indivisible quantitatively or qualitatively, and
in short an eternal composite, without a composing principle? This is a sound
argument from which they cannot escape except through dialectical arguments. z
But all the arguments which Ghazali gives in
this book either against or on behalf of the philosophers or against Avicenna
are dialectical through the equivocation of the terms used, and therefore it is
not necessary to expatiate on this.
And
as to his answer on behalf of the Ash’arites that what is eternal through
itself does not need a cause for its eternity, and that when the theologians
assume something eternal through itself and assume its essence as the cause of
its attributes, this essence does not become eternal because of something else,
I
say:
It
is a necessary consequence to be held up against Ghazali
that the Eternal will be composed of a cause and an effect, and that the
attributes will be eternal through their cause, i. e. the essence. And since the
effect is not a condition for its own existence, the Eternal is the cause. And
let us say that the essence which exists by itself is God and that the
attributes are effects; then it can be argued against the theologians that they
assume one thing eternal by itself and a plurality of things eternal through
another, and that the combination of all these is God. But this is exactly their
objection against those who say that God is eternal through Himself and the
world eternal through another, namely God. Besides, they say that the Eternal is
one, and all this is extremely contradictory.
And
as to Ghazali’s statement that to assume a
compound without the factor which composes it, is not different from assuming an
existent without a creator, and that the assumption either of a single existent
of this description or of a plurality is not an impossible supposition for the
mind, all this is erroneous. For composition does not demand a composing factor
which again itself is composed, but there must be a series leading up to a
composing factor composing by itself, just as, when the cause is an effect,
there must finally be a cause which is not an effect. Nor is it possible, by
means of an argument which leads to an existent without a creator, to prove the
oneness of this existent. ‘
And
as to his assertion that the denial of the quiddity implies the denial of the
composition, and that this implies the assertion of composition in the First,
this is not true. And indeed the philosophers do not deny the quiddity of the
First, but only deny that it has the kind of quiddity which is in the effects,
and all this is a dialectical and doubtful argument. And already previously in
this book we have given convincing arguments, according to the principles of the
philosophers, to prove that the First is incorporeal, namely that the possible
leads to a necessary existent and that the possible does not proceed from the
necessary except through the mediation of an existent which is partly necessary,
partly possible, and that this is the body of the heavens and its circular
motion; and the most satisfactory way of expressing this according to the
principles of the philosophers is to say that all bodies are finite in power,
and that they only acquire their power of infinite movement through an
incorporeal being. ‘
Ghazali
answering the objection which infers that according to the philosophers the
agent is nothing but the sphere, composed of soul and body, says:
If it is answered: ‘This cannot be so, because body in so far as it is body does not create anything else and the soul which is attached to the body does not act except through the mediation of the body, but the body is not a means for the soul in the latter’s creating bodies or in causing the existence of souls and of things which are not related to bodies’, we answer: ‘And why is it not possible that there should be amongst the souls a soul which has the characteristic of being so disposed that both bodies and incorporeals are produced through it? The impossibility of this is not a thing known necessarily, nor is there a proof for it, except that we do not experience this in the bodies we observe; but the absence of experience does not demonstrate its impossibility, and indeed the philosophers often ascribe things to the First Existent which are not generally ascribed to existents, and are not experienced in any other existent, and the absence of its being observed in other things is not a proof of its impossibility in reference to the First Existent, and the same holds concerning the body and its soul. ‘
I
say:
As
to his assertion that bodies do not create bodies, if by ‘creating’ is
understood producing, the reverse is true, for a body in the empirical world can
only come into being through a body, , and an animated body only through an
animated body, but the absolute body does not come into being at all, for, if it
did, it would come into being from non-existence, not after
non-existence. ‘ Individual bodies only come into being out of individual
bodies and through individual bodies, and this through the body’s being
transferred from one name to another and from one definition to another, so that
for instance the body of water changes into the body of fire, because out of the
body of water is transformed the attribute through the transformation of which
the name and definition of water is transferred to the name and definition of
fire, and this happens necessarily through a body which is the agent,
participating with the becoming body specifically or generically in either a
univocal or an analogical ways and whether the individual special corporeality
in the water is transformed into the individual special corporeality of the fire
is a problem to be studied.
And
as to Ghazali’s words:
But the body is not a means for the soul in the latter’s creating bodies or in causing the existence of souls,
I
say:
This
is an argument which he builds on an opinion some of the philosophers hold, that
the bestower of forms on inanimate bodies and of souls is a separate substance,
either intellect or a separate soul, and that it is not possible that either an
animated body or an inanimate body should supply this. And if this opinion is
held and at the same time it is assumed that heaven is an animated body, it is
no longer possible for heaven to supply any of the transitory forms, either the
soul or any other of these forms. For the soul which is in the body only acts
through the mediation of the body, and that which acts through the mediation of
the body can produce neither form nor soul, since it is not of the nature of the
body to produce a substantial form, either a soul or any other substantial form.
And this theory resembles that of Plato about forms separate from matter, and is
the in theory of Avicenna and others among the Muslim philosophers; their proof
is that the body produces in the body only warmth or cold or moisture or
dryness, ? and only these are acts of the heavenly bodies according to them. But
that which produces the substantial forms, and especially those which are
animated, is a separate substance which they call the giver of forms. ‘ But
there are philosophers’ who believe the contrary and affirm that what produces
the forms in the bodies is bodies possessing forms similar to them either
specifically or generically, those similar specifically being the living bodies
which produce the living bodies of the empirical world, like the animals which
are generated from other animals, whereas those forms produced by forms
generically similar, and which are not produced from a male or a female, receive
their lives according to the philosophers from the heavenly bodies, since these
are alive. And these philosophers have non-empirical proofs which, however, need
not be mentioned here.
And
therefore Ghazali argues against them in this
way:
And why is it not possible that there should be among the souls a soul which has the characteristic of being so disposed that both bodies and incorporeals are produced through it?
I
say:
He
means: ‘Why should it not be possible that there should be among the souls in
bodies souls which have the characteristic of generating other animate and
inanimate forms? ‘ And how strange it is that Ghazali
assumes that the production of body out of body does not happen in the empirical
world, whereas nothing else is ever observed.
But
you must understand that when the statements of the philosophers are abstracted
from the demonstrative sciences they certainly become dialectical, whether they
are generally acknowledged, or, if not, denied and regarded as strange. The
reason is that demonstrative statements are only distinguished from statements
which are not demonstrative, by being considered in the genus of science which
is under investigation. Those statements which can be subsumed under the
definition of this genus of science, or which comprise in their definition this
genus of science, are demonstrative, and those statements which do not seem to
fulfil these conditions are not demonstrative. Demonstration is only possible
when the nature of this genus of science under investigation is defined, and the
sense in which its essential predicates exist is distinguished from the sense in
which they do not, and when this is retained in mind by keeping to that sense in
every statement adopted in this science, and by having the identical meaning
always present in the mind. And when the soul is convinced that the statement is
essential to this genus or a necessary consequence of its essence, the statement
is true; but when this relation does not enter into the mind, or when it is only
weakly established, the statement is only an opinion, and is not evident. And
therefore the difference between proof and convincing opinion is more delicate
than the appearance of a hair and more completely hidden than the exact limit
between darkness and light, especially in theological questions which are laid
before the common people, because of the confusion between what is essential and
what is accidental. Therefore we see that Ghazali,
by relating the theories of the philosophers in this and others of his books and
by showing them to people who have not studied their works with the necessary
preparation the philosophers demand, changes the nature of the truth which
exists in their theories or drives most people away from all their views. And by
so doing he does more harm than good to the cause of truth. And God knows that I
should not have related a single one of their views, or regarded this as
permissible, but for the harm which results from Ghazali’s
doings to the cause of wisdom; and I understand by ‘wisdom’ speculation
about things according to the rules of the nature of proof.
Ghazali
says, on behalf of the philosophers:
If it is said that the highest sphere, or the sun, or whatever body you may imagine, possesses a special size which may be increased or decreased, and this possible size needs for its differentiation a differentiating principle and can therefore not be the First, ‘ we answer: By what argument will you refute the man who says that this body must have the size it possesses for the sake of the order of the universe, and this order could not exist if this body were smaller or larger-since you philosophers yourselves affirm that the first effect’ determines the size of the highest sphere because all sizes are equivalent in relation to the essence of the first effect, but certain sizes are determined for the sake of the order which depends on them and therefore the actual size is necessary and no other is possible; and all this holds just as well when no effect is assumed. Indeed, if the philosophers had established in the first effect, which is according to the philosophers the cause of the highest sphere, a specifying principle, as for instance the will, a further question might be put, since it might be asked why this principle willed this actual size rather than another, in the way the philosophers argued against the Muslims about their theory of the relation between the temporal world and the Eternal Will, an argument which we turned against them with respect to the problems of the determination of the direction of the heavenly movement and of the determination of the points of the poles. And if it is clear that they are forced to admit that a thing is differentiated from a similar one and that this happens through a cause, it is unessential whether this differentiation be regarded as possible without a cause or through a cause, for it is indifferent whether one puts the question about the thing itself and asks why it has such-and such a size, or whether one puts the question about the cause, and asks why it gave this thing this special size; and if the question about the cause may be answered by saying that this special measure is not like any other, because the order depends on it exclusively, the same answer may be made about the thing itself, and it will not need a cause. And there is no escape from this. For if the actual size which has been determined and has been realized were equivalent to the size which has not been realized, one might ask how one thing comes to be differentiated from a similar one, especially according to the principle of the philosophers who do not admit a differentiating will. If, however, there is no similar size, no possibility exists, and one must answer: ‘This has been so from all eternity, and in the same way therefore as, according to the philosophers, the eternal cause exists. “ And let the man who studies this question seek help from what we said about their asking about the eternal will, a question which we turned against them with respect to the points of the poles and the direction of the movement of the sphere. It is therefore clear that the man who does not believe in the temporal creation of the bodies cannot establish a proof that the First is incorporeal.
I
say:
This indeed is a very strange argument of Ghazali’s. For he argues that they cannot prove another creator than the heavenly body, since they would have to give an answer by a principle in which they do not believe. For only the theologians accept this principle, since they say that heaven receives the determinate size it has, to the exclusion of other sizes it might have, from a differentiating cause, and that the differentiating principle must be eternal. He either attempted to deceive in this matter or was himself deceived. For the differentiation which the philosophers infer is different from that which the Ash’arites intend, for the Ash’arites understand by ‘differentiation’ the distinguishing of one thing either from a similar one or from an opposite one without this being determined by any wisdom in the thing itself which makes it necessary to differentiate one of the two opposite things. The philosophers, on the other hand, understand here by the differentiating principle only that which is determined by the wisdom in the product itself, namely the final cause, for according to them there is no quantity or quality in any being that has not an end based on wisdom, an end which must either be a necessity in the nature of the act of this being or exist in it, based on the principle of superiority. ‘ For if, so the philosophers believe, there were in created things a quantity or quality not determined by wisdom, they would have attributed to the First Maker and Creator an attitude in relation to His work which may be only attributed to the artisans among His creatures, with the intention of blaming them. For when one has observed a work with respect to its quantity and quality, and asked why the maker of this work chose this quantity or this quality to the exclusion of all other possible quantities and qualities, there is no worse mistake than to answer ‘Not because of the intrinsic wisdom and thoughtfulness in the product itself, but because he willed it, ‘ since according to this view all quantities and qualities are similar with respect to the end of this product, which in fact the maker produced for its own sake, namely for the sake of the act for whose purpose it exists. For indeed every product is produced in view of something in it which would not proceed from it, if this product had no definite quantity, quality and nature, although in some products an equivalent is possible. If any product whatever could determine any act whatever, there would exist no wisdom at all in any product, and there would be no art at all, and the quantities and qualities of the products would depend on the whim of the artisan and every man would be an artisan. Or should we rather say that wisdom exists only in the product of the creature, not in the act of the Creator? But God forbid that we should believe such a thing of the First Creator; on the contrary, we believe that everything in the world is wisdom, although in many things our understanding of it is very imperfect and although we understand the wisdom of the Creator only through the wisdom of nature. And if the world is one single product of extreme wisdom, there is one wise principle whose existence the heavens and the earth and everything in them need. Indeed, nobody can regard the product of such wonderful wisdom as caused by itself, and the theologians in their wish to elevate the Creator have denied Him wisdom and withheld from Him the noblest of His qualities.
Ghazali
says:
Their statement that body needs a creator and a cause can be understood from the theory of those’ who argue that all bodies are temporal, because they cannot exist without what is temporal. But what keeps you philosophers from the doctrine of the materialists, namely that the world is eternal in the condition in which it actually is, and that it has no cause and no creator, that there is only a cause for temporal events and that no body comes into existence and no body is annihilated, and that only forms and accidents come into existence, for the bodies are the heavens (which are eternal) and the four elements, which are the stuff of the sublunary world, and their bodies and matters are eternal too, and there is only a change of forms in them through mixtures and alterations ;and that the souls of men and animals and plants come into existence, that all the causes of these temporal events terminate in the circular movement, and that the circular movement is eternal and its source the eternal soul of the sphere. Therefore there is no cause for the world and no creator for its bodies, but since the world, as it is, is eternal, there is no cause for it, i. e. no cause for its bodies. For indeed, what sense is there in the doctrine of the philosophers that these bodies exist through a cause, although they are eternal?
I
say:
The
philosophers assert that the man who says that all bodies have been produced
(and by ‘produced’ must be understood creation ex
nihilo) gives a meaning to the term ‘produced’ which is never found in
the empirical world, and his statement surely stands in need of a proof. As to
his attacks on the philosophers in this passage, so that he even forces on them
the implication of atheism, we have already answered them previously and there
is no sense in repeating ourselves, but, in short, the philosophers hold that
body, be it temporal or eternal, cannot be independent in existence through
itself; and this principle is, according to the philosophers, binding for the
eternal body in the same way as for the temporal, although imagination does not
help to explain how this is the case with the eternal body in the way it is with
the temporal body. Aristotle therefore, in the second book of De caelo et mundo, when he wanted to explain the fact that the earth
was circular by nature, first assumed it to have come into being in time so that
the intellect might imagine its cause, and then transferred its existence to
eternity.
Having
forced on the philosophers these reprehensible deductions, Ghazali
now gives an answer in defence of them and objects then to their answer.
Ghazali
says:
And if the philosophers say: ‘Everything that has no cause is of a necessary existence, and we philosophers have already mentioned the qualities of the necessary existent through which it is proved that body cannot be the necessary existent, ‘ we answer: We have shown the mistake in your claim about the attributes of the necessary existent, and that your proof does not demonstrate anything but the termination of a causal series, and this termination also exists for the materialists at the beginning of things, , for they say that there is no cause for the bodies, and the forms and accidents are causes for each other and terminate in the circular movement part of which is the cause of another part in the same way as it takes place according to the doctrine of the philosophers, and this causal series’ ends in this circular movement.
And the man who observes what we have related will understand the inability of those who believe in the eternity of bodies to claim at the same time that they have a cause, and the consequence of their theory is atheism and apostasy, which one party has clearly admitted, those namely who rely solely on the determinations of the intellect.
I
say:
All
this has been already answered, and its degree of truth has been stated, and
there is no reason to repeat ourselves. And as to the materialists, they rely
only on the senses, and when according to them the movements had terminated in
the heavenly body and through this the causal series was ended, they thought
that where sensation had come to a limit, the intellect also had come to a
limit; but this is not true. But the philosophers considered the causes till
they ended in the heavenly body, then they considered the intelligible causes
and arrived at an existent which cannot be perceived and which is the principle
of perceptible being, and this is the meaning of the words: ‘Thus did we show
Abraham the Kingdom of Heaven and of the earth . . . . ‘The Ash’arites,
however, rejected sensible causes; that is, they denied that certain sensible
things are the causes of other sensible things, and they made the cause of
sensible being a nonsensible being by a way of becoming which is neither
experienced nor perceived, and they denied causes and effects; and this is a
kind of view which is inconsistent with the nature of man in so far as he is
man.
Ghazali
says, objecting to the argument of the philosophers:
If it is said that the proof that body is not a necessary existent is that, if it were a necessary existent, it would have neither an external nor an internal cause, but if it has a cause for its being composed, it will be possible in respect of its essence, and every possible needs a necessary existent, we answer: The terms ‘necessary existent’ and ‘possible existent’ are devoid of sense, and your whole confusion lies in these terms; but let us revert to their plain sense, which is the denial and the affirmation of a cause, for then your words amount to nothing else but saying that bodies either have a cause or not, and the materialists affirm the latter, ‘ and why should you deny it? And when this is understood by ‘possibility’ and ‘necessity’, we say body is necessary and not possible, and your statement that body cannot be necessary is pure presumption without any foundation.
I
say:
We
have already said that if by ‘necessary existent’ is understood the
causeless and by ‘possible existent’ is understood that which has a cause,
the division of being into these two sections is not acknowledged, and opponents
might say that this division is not true, but that, indeed, all existents are
causeless. But when by ‘necessary existent’ is understood absolute necessary
being and by ‘possible’ the genuinely possible, then we must arrive at a
being which has no cause, for we can say that every being is either possible or
necessary; if possible, it has a cause, and if this cause is of the nature of
the possible, we have a series which ends in a necessary cause. Then, concerning
this necessary cause it may be asked again whether some necessary beings might
have a cause and other necessary beings none, and if a cause is ascribed to the
nature of the necessary being which can have a cause, there will follow a series
which ends in a necessary being which has no cause. Avicenna wanted by this
division only to conform to the opinion of the philosophers concerning
existents, for all philosophers agree that the body of the heavens is necessary
through something else; whether, however, this thing necessary through another
is possible by itself is a problem which has to be studied.
And this argument is therefore faulty when this method is followed, and
this method is of necessity faulty, because being is not primarily divided into
the genuinely possible and the necessary, for this is a division which is only
known through the nature of existing things.
Then
Ghazali answers the philosophers’ statement
that body cannot be a necessary existent by itself, because it
has parts which are its cause.
If it is said: ‘It cannot be denied that body has parts, and that the whole is only constituted through the parts, and that the parts in a thing are prior to the whole, ‘ we answer: ‘Let it be so; certainly, the whole is constituted by the parts and their aggregation, but there is no cause for the parts nor for their aggregation, which on the contrary are eternally in the condition in which they are without an efficient cause. ‘ And the philosophers cannot refute this, except by the argument of theirs which we have mentioned, which is based on the denial of plurality in the First; we have shown its futility, and apart from it there is no other method. It is therefore clear that for the man who does not believe in the temporal creation of bodies there is no foundation for believing in a creator at all.
I
say:
This
argument is, without doubt, binding for the man who follows the method of a
necessary existent to prove the existence of an incorporeal being, but this is
not the method followed by the ancient philosophers, and the first, so far as we
know, who used it was Avicenna. He said that it was superior to the proof of the
ancients, because the ancients arrived only at an immaterial being, the
principle of the universe, through derivative things, namely motion and time;
whereas this proof, according to Avicenna, arrives at the assertion of such a
principle as the ancients established, through the investigation of the nature
of the existent in so far as it is an existent. If indeed it did arrive at such
an affirmation, what Avicenna says would be true; however, it does not. ‘ For
the most that could be affirmed of the existent necessarily existing by itself
would be that it is not composed of matter and form, and generally speaking that
it has no definition. But if it is supposed to exist as composed of eternal
parts which are continuous by nature, as is the case with the world and its
parts, it may indeed be said of the world with its parts that it is a necessary
existent, z it being of course understood that there is a necessary existent.
And we have already said that the method Avicenna followed to establish an
existent of this description is not demonstrative and does not by nature lead to
it, except in the way we have stated. The utmost consequence of this
argument-and this constitutes its weakness-is the theory of those, namely the
Peripatetics, who assume that there exists a simple body not composed of matter
and form. For the man who assumes an eternal compound of actual parts must
necessarily acknowledge that it is essentially one, and every oneness in a
compound is one through an essential unity, namely a simple, and through this
unity the world becomes one, and therefore Alexander of Aphrodisias says that
there must exist a spiritual force which is diffused in all the parts of the
universe in the same way as there is a force in all the parts of a single animal
which binds them together, and the difference between the two forces is that the
binding force in the world is eternal, because the conjoining principle is
eternal, whereas the conjunction between the parts of the sublunary animal is
individually transitory-although, through the eternal conjunction, not
specifically transitory-since it cannot be individually imperishable like the
world . z And through this theory the Creator will be deprived of that very kind
of perfection which nothing else can equal, as Aristotle says in his book De
animalibus. And we see nowadays that many of Avicenna’s followers because
of this aporia ascribe this opinion to him, and they say that he does not
believe that there exists a separate existence, and they assert that this can be
seen from what he says about the necessary existent in many passages, and that
this is the view which he has laid down in his Oriental
Philosophy, and they say that he only called this book Oriental Philosophy’ because it is the doctrine of the Orientals;
for they believed that according to the Orientals divinity is located in the
heavenly bodies, as Avicenna himself had come to believe. However,
notwithstanding this they accept Aristotle’s argument to prove the First
Principle through movement.
And
as for ourselves, we have discussed this argument at other times and have shown
in what sense it can be regarded as evident, and we have solved all the doubts
concerning it; we have also discussed Alexander’s argument on this question,
namely the one he uses in his book called On
the printiples. s For Alexander imagined that he was turning from
Aristotle’s argument to another; his argument, however, is taken from the
principles which Aristotle proved, and both arguments are sound, though the more
usual is Aristotle’s.
And
when the argument for a necessary existent is verified, it is true according to
me in the way I shall describe it, although it is used too generally and its
different senses must be distinguished. It must, namely, be preceded by
knowledge of the different kinds of possible existents in substance and the
different kinds of necessary existents in substance. And then this argument
takes this form: The possible existent in bodily substance must be preceded by
the necessary existent in bodily substance, and the necessary existent in bodily
substance must be preceded by the absolute necessary existent which does not
possess any potency whatsoever, either in its substance or in any other of the
different kinds of movements, and such an entity is not a body. For instance, it
appears from the nature of the body of the heavens that it is a necessary
existent in its bodily substance, ‘ for otherwise there would have to be a
body prior to it, and it appears also from its nature that it is a possible
existent in its local movement; it is therefore necessary that its mover should
be a necessary existent in its substance, and that there should be in it no
potency whatsoever, either as regards movement or in any other respect, and that
neither movement nor rest could be ascribed to it nor any other kind of change,
and such an entity is absolutely without body and without any potency in a body.
But the eternal parts of the world are only necessary existents in their
substance, either universally like the four elements, or individually like the
heavenly bodies. ,
Ghazali says:
Since for the Muslims existence is confined to the temporal and the eternal, and there is for them nothing eternal except God and His attributes, and everything besides Him is temporally created by Him through His will, according to them the existent of necessity exists previously in His knowledge, for the object willed must be known by the willer. They deduced from this that the universe is known to Him, for the universe was willed by Him and produced by Him, and nothing comes into existence but what is produced through His will, and nothing is everlasting but His essence alone. And when once it was established that God wills and knows what He wills, He must be necessarily living, ; and every living being is conscious of its own self, and He is the most capable of knowing Himself. Therefore the whole universe is known to God, and they understood this through this argument, since they had found that He willed everything that happens in the world.
I
say:
He
says this only as an introduction and preparation for the comparison between his
theory and that of the philosophers about eternal
knowledge, because his theory seems at
first sight more satisfactory than that of the philosophers. But when the theory
of the theologians is tested, and shown up to him for whom such an exposure is
necessary, it becomes clear that they only made God an eternal man, , for they
compared the world with the products of art wrought by the will and knowledge
and power of man. And when it was objected against them that He must then have a
body, they answered that He is eternal and that all bodies are temporal. They
were therefore forced to admit an immaterial man who produces all existents. But
this theory is nothing but a metaphor and a poetical expression; and
metaphorical expressions are certainly very convincing, till they are explored,
but then their deficiency becomes evident. For indeed there is no nature more
distant from that of the transitory than that of the eternal. And if this is
true, it cannot be that there should exist one single species which is
differentiated by eternity and non-eternityz as one single genus is
differentiated through the various differences into which it is divided. For the
distance between the eternal and the temporal is far greater than that between
the different species which participate in temporality. And if the distance
between eternity and non-eternity is greater than that between the various
species, how then is it possible to apply a judgement about the empirical world
to the invisible: for those two are opposite extremes? And when you have
understood the sense of the attributes which exist in the visible world and
those which exist in the invisible world, it will be clear to you that through
the ambiguity of the terms they are so equivocal that they do not permit a
transference from the visible to the invisible.
Life,
for instance, added to the intellect of man only applies to the potentiality of
motion in space through will and sense-perception, ; but senses are impossible
for the Creator and still more impossible for Him is motion in space. But the
theologians ascribe to the Creator the faculty of sense-perception without
sense-organs, and deny His movement absolutely. Therefore either they do not
ascribe life to the Creator in the sense it has in the animal and which is a
condition for the existence of knowledge in man, or they identify it with
perception in the way the philosophers say that perception and knowledge in the
First are identical with life. Further, the meaning of ‘will’ in man and in
animal is a desire which rouses movement and which happens in animal and man to
perfect a deficiency in their essence, and it is impossible that there should be
in the Creator a desire because of an imperfection in His essence, which could
be a cause of movement and action either in Himself or in something different
from Himself. And how could an eternal will be imagined which should be the
cause of an act occurring without an increase of the desire at the time of the
act, , or how could a will and a desire be imagined which would be before,
during, and after the act in the same state without any change occurring to
them? And again, desire (in so far as it is _the cause of movement) and movement
are only found in body, and desire is only found in the animate body. Therefore
according to the philosophers the meaning of ‘will’ in God is nothing but
that every act proceeds from Him through knowledge, and knowledge in so far as
it is knowledge is the knowledge of opposites, either of which can proceed from
Him. And the Knower is called excellent by the fact that there always proceeds
from Him the better of the opposites to the exclusion of the worse. Therefore
the philosophers say that three attributes are most appropriate to the Creator,
namely that He has knowledge, excellence, and power. And they say that His power
is not inferior to His will, as is the case with man.
All
this is the theory of the philosophers on this problem and in the way we have
stated it here with its proofs, it is a persuasive not a demonstrative
statement. It is for you to inquire about these questions in the places where
they are treated in the books of demonstration, if you are one of the people of
perfect eudaemonia, and if you are one of those who learn the arts the function
of which is proof. For the demonstrative arts are very much like the practical;
for just as a man who is not a craftsman cannot perform the function of
craftsmanship, in the same way it is not possible for him who has not learned
the arts of demonstration to perform the function of demonstration which is
demonstration itself: indeed this is still more necessary for this art than for
any other-and this is not generally acknowledged in the case of this practice
only because it is a mere act-and therefore such a demonstration can proceed
only from one who has learned the art. The kinds of statement, however, are
many, some demonstrative, others not, and since non-demonstrative statements can
be adduced without knowledge of the art, it was thought that this might be also
the case with demonstrative statements; but this is a great error. And therefore
in the spheres of the demonstrative arts, no other statement is possible but a
technical statement which only the student of this art can bring, just as is the
case with the art of geometry. Nothing therefore of what we have said in this
book is a technical demonstrative proof; they are all non-technical statements,
some of them having greater persuasion than others, and it is in this spirit
that what we have written here must be understood. So this book of Ghazali
might be best given the name of the ‘Incoherence of both parties together’.
All
this in my opinion is in excess of the Holy Law, and an inquiry into something
not ordered by a religious law because human power does not suffice for it. For
not all knowledge about which the Holy Law is silent needs to be explored and
explained to the masses as being, according to speculative thought, part of the
dogmas of religion; for from this the greatest confusion arises. One must not
speak about those things concerning which the Holy Law is silent; the masses
must learn that human understanding is not sufficient to treat these problems,
and must not go beyond what the teaching of the Holy Law explains in its texts,
since this is teaching in which all can participate and which suffices for the
attainment of their happiness. And just as the physician investigates the
measure of health which agrees most with the healthy for the preservation of
their health, and with the sick for the curing of their illness, so the Lord of
the Holy Law instructs the masses only in so far as is needed for their
acquisition of happiness. And the same thing holds in respect of the facts of
human behaviour, only the investigation of these facts in so far as the Holy Law
is silent about them is more legitimate, especially when they are of the same
genus as those about which the Law pronounces judgement. For this reason the
lawyers disagree about this kind of facts; some of them, the Zahirites, deny the
use of analogy, whereas others, the analogists, admit it, , and this is
absolutely the same thing as happens in the sphere of knowledge, only perhaps
the Zahirites are happier in the purely intellectual sphere than in the
practical.
And
anyone amongst the two opposing parties who inquires after these questions must
either belong to the followers of proof, i. e. the rationalists, or not; in the
former case he will speak about them and base his statements on demonstration,
he will know that this way of discussion is limited to the followers of proof,
and he will know the places in which the Holy Law gives to the people who
possess this kind of knowledge a hint about the conclusions to which
demonstration leads; in the latter case he will be either a believer or an
unbeliever: if he is a believer he will know that to discuss those questions is
forbidden by the Holy Law, and if he is an unbeliever, it is not difficult for
the followers of proof to refute him with the stringent proofs they possess. The
rationalist must act in this way in every religion, but especially in our Divine
Revelation, which although it is silent on certain intellectual problems
nevertheless hints at the conclusions about them to which demonstration leads,
without, however, mentioning these problems in its instruction of the masses.
Since
this is established, we shall revert now to our subject, which is forced upon us
by necessity-for otherwise, by God, the Knower, the Witness, the Revealer, we
should not think it permissible to discuss such questions in this way. And Ghazali,
having described the arguments through which the theologians prove the attribute
of knowledge and other attributes, and shown that they are very evident because
they are generally admitted and extremely easy to accept, begins to compare
these arguments with those of the philosophers about these attributes, and this
is an act of rhetoric. ‘
Ghazali
says, addressing the philosophers:
And you, philosophers, when you affirm that the world is eternal and not produced by God’s will, how do you know that He knows something beside His essence, for you require a proof of this?
Then
Ghazali says:
And the summary of what Avicenna says to prove this in the course of his argument can be reduced to two heads: First, that the First does not exist in matter, and everything which does not exist in matter is pure intellect and all the intelligibles are revealed to it, for the obstacle to perceiving all things is attachment to matter and being occupied with matter, and the human soul is occupied by directing matter, i. e. its body, and when this occupation is terminated and it is not any longer defiled by the bodily passions and the despicable conditions which affect it through the things of nature, all the realities of the intelligibles are revealed to it, and therefore is it asserted that all the angels know all the intelligibles without exception, for they too are pure immaterial intellects.
And
having related their theory; Ghazali argues
against them:
But we say: If by your assertion that the First does not exist in matter, you mean that it is not a body, nor impressed on a body, but exists by itself not comprised by space nor locally specified by a direction, this is admitted by us. There remains then your answer to the question what its attribute is, namely that it is pure intellect-and what do you understand by ‘intellect’? If you mean by it that which thinks all the other things, this is just what we are trying to find out and the point under discussion, and how, therefore, can you take it as the premiss of a syllogism which must prove it? And if you mean by it something else, namely that it thinks its own self-and some of your fellow-philosophers may concede this to you, but this amounts again to your saying that what thinks its own self thinks other things also-the answer to be made is ‘Why do you claim this? For this is not known by necessity, and only Avicenna of all the philosophers affirmed it; and how can you claim this as necessary knowledge, or, if you know it by deduction, what is your proof? ‘
And if the assertion is made: ‘Because what prevents the perception of things is matter, and the First is not matter’, we answer: We concede that matter is an impediment, but we do not admit that it is the only impediment; and let them arrange their syllogism in the figure of the hypothetical syllogism and say: ‘If this First is in matter it cannot think things, but it is not in matter, therefore it thinks things’. ‘ And this is the assumption as a minor premiss of the opposite of the antecedent, but such an assumption does not lead to a conclusion in all cases, for it is like saying: ‘If this is a man, it is an animal, but it is not a man, therefore it is not an animal’. But this is not a necessary conclusion, for although not a man, it might be a horse, and therefore an animal. The assumption as a minor premiss of the opposite of the antecedent is valid only conditionally, as we have shown in our logic-namely, when the consequent is universally convertible with the antecedent, as when the logicians say: ‘If the sun has risen, it is day, but the sun has not risen, therefore it is not day’, for the only cause of its being day is the fact that the sun has risen-an example in which antecedent and consequent are convertible with each other-and the explanation of these theories and terms can be understood from our book ‘The Touchstone of Knowledge’, which we have written as an appendix to this book. If, however, they say ‘We claim that antecedent and consequent are here convertible, and that the one and only obstacle to thinking is being in matter’, we answer: ‘This is a pure presumption; where is your proof? ‘
I
say:
The
first mistake he makes here is that, in relating the theory and the proof, he
regards the premisses he mentions as first principles, whereas for the
philosophers they are conclusions from many premisses. For the philosophers had
seen that every sensible existent is composed of matter and form, and that the
form is the entity through which the existent becomes existentand that it is the
form which is designated by the name and the definitions and that the specific
act proceeds from the form in every existent, and it is this act which shows the
existence of the forms in the existent. b For they had found that in substances
there are active potencies, particular to every single existent, and passive
potencies, either particular or common, ? and that a thing cannot be passive by
reason of the same thing as it is active; for activity is the opposite of
passivity, and opposites do not admit each other, and it is only their
substratum which admits them successively, e. g. hotness does not accept
coldness, it is simply the hot body that accepts coldness by divesting itself of
hotness and accepting coldness, and vice versa. Now when the philosophers found
that this was the case with activity and passivity, they understood that all
existents of this description were composed of two substances, a substance which
is the act and a substance which is the potency, and they realized that the
substance in act is the perfection of the substance in potency and that the
substance in act stands in relation to the substance in potency as if it were
the end of its actualization, for there is no actual difference between them.
‘ Then, when they looked through all the different forms of existents, they
found that all these substances must necessarily lead up to a substance in act
which is absolutely devoid of matter, and this substance must necessarily be
active and cannot have any passivity and cannot be subject to exhaustion,
weariness, and decay; for such things occur to the substance in act only because
it is the perfection of the substance in potency, not because it is pure act.
For since the substance in potency only goes forth into act through a substance
in act, the series of substances which are at the same time both active and
passive must terminate in a substance which is pure act, and the series must
terminate in that substance. And the proof of the existence of this substance,
in so far as it is a mover and agent, through essential particular premisses,
can be found in the eighth book of Aristotle’s Physics.
Having
established the existence of this substance by special and general arguments
according to what is known in their books, the philosophers now investigated the
nature of the forms in matter which produce motion, and they found some of them
nearer to actuality and farther from potency because they are less than others
involved in passivity, which is the special sign of the matter which exists in
them. And they realized that that which among these forms is most destitute of
matter is the soul, and especially the intellect, so that they started to doubt
whether the intellect belongs to the forms which are in matter or not. z But
when they investigated the perceiving forms amongst the forms of the soul and
found that they were free from matter, they understood that the cause of
perception consists in freedom from matter, ; and since they discovered that the
intellect is without passivity they understood that the reason why one form is
inorganic and another perceptive consists in the fact that when it is the
perfection of a potency it is inorganic or not percipient, ‘ and when it is
pure perfection with which no potency is mixed it is intellect. ‘ All this
they proved in a demonstrative order and by natural deductions which cannot be
reproduced here in this demonstrative sequence, for this would involve
collecting in one place what by its nature is treated in many different books,
and anyone who has the slightest experience of the science of logic will
acknowledge that this is an impossibility. Through arguments of this kind they
came to realize that what has no passivity whatever is intellect and not body,
for what is passive is body which exists in matter according to them.
An
objection against the philosophers in these questions ought to be made only
against the first principles they use in the proof of these conclusions, not
against those conclusions themselves, as it is made by Ghazali.
Through this they came to understand that there exists here an existent which is
pure intellect, and when they saw further that the order which reigns in nature
and in the act of nature follows an intellectual plan very much like the plan of
the craftsman, they realized that there must exist an intellect which causes
these natural potencies to act in an intellectual way, and through these two
points they received the conviction that this existent which is pure intellect
is that which bestows on the existents the order and arrangement in their acts.
And they understood from all this that its thinking its own self is identical
with its thinking all existents, and that this existent is not such that its
thinking its own self is something different from the thought by which it thinks
other things, as is the case with the human intellect. And about this intellect
the disjunction assumed as a premiss, that every intellect either thinks its own
self or thinks something else or thinks both together, is not valid. For when
this disjunction is admitted, what is said is: ‘If it thinks other things, it
is self-evident that it must think its own self; however, if it thinks its own
self, it is not at all necessary that it should think other things. ‘ And we
have discussed this previously.
And
all the things which he says about the hypothetical syllogism which he formed in
the figure he explained are not true. For the hypothetical syllogism is only
valid when the minor and the legitimacy of the inferenceare proved through one
or more categorical syllogisms. For correct hypothetical inference in this
question is: ‘If what does not think is in matter, then what is not in matter
thinks. ‘ But, of course, first the truth of this conjunction and disjunction
must be proved. ‘ And these are the premisses of which we said that they are
according to the philosophers conclusions, whereas Ghazali
pretends they are first principles for them, or nearly so. And when it is
explained as we have done, it is a syllogism of a legitimate figure and of true
premisses. As to its legitimate form, the minor is the opposite of the
consequent and the conclusion is the opposite of the antecedent, not as Ghazali
believed, the minor the opposite of the antecedent and the conclusion the
opposite of the consequent. ‘ But since they are not first principles, nor
generally acknowledged, nor evident at first sight, they are regarded, no doubt,
by those who have never heard anything of these things as very much open to
objection. But indeed Ghazali confused the sciences in a most terrible way, and he
uprooted science from its foundation and its method.
Ghazali says:
The second argument is that the philosophers say: ‘Although we assert neither that the First wills temporal production nor that it produces the world in time by secondary intention, we nevertheless affirm that the First has made the world and that indeed the world has its existence through the First only, the First never losing its character as an agent and never ceasing to act; our theory only distinguishes itself from others in this point, in no way however with respect to the principle of the act. And since the agent must have knowledge in conformity with its act, the universe, according to us, exists through its act. ‘
But there are two ways to answer this, of which the first is: ‘There are two kinds of action: voluntary, like the action of animal and man; and involuntary, like the action of the sun in producing light, of fire in producing heat, of water in producing cold. Now knowledge of the act is only necessary in voluntary acts, as in the human products of art, not in the acts of nature. But according to you philosophers, God has made the world consequent on His essence by nature and by necessity, not through will and choice; indeed, the universe is consequent on His essence, as light is on the sun, and just as the sun has no power to check its light, nor fire to repress its producing heat, so the First cannot check its acts. Now this kind of occurrence, although it may be called an act, does not imply knowledge at all. ‘ And if it is answered that there is a difference between the two things, in that the procession of the universe from God’s essence occurs through His knowledge of the universe and His representing the universal order in the course of the emamation of the universe, and He has no other cause than His knowledge of the universe, and His knowledge of the universe is identical with His essence, and if He had not this knowledge of the universe, the universe would not exist through Him, which is not the case with light in relation to the sun, we answer: ‘In this you are in contradiction to your fellow-philosophers, for they say that His essence is the essence from which the existence of the universe in its order follows naturally and necessarily, and it is not because He knows this. ‘ And what is wrong with this conception, once you agree with them in denying His will? And since the sun’s knowledge of its light is no condition for its light, but its light is necessarily consequent on the sun, so let us accept this also in the case of the First; and nothing prevents this. ‘
I say:
In
this section Ghazali begins by saying something
reprehensible about the philosophers, namely that the Creator possesses a will
neither with respect to the things produced nor with respect to the universe as
a whole, because His act proceeds from His essence necessarily like the
procession of light from the sun. Then he says of them that they say that
through His acting He must have knowledge. The philosophers, however, do not
deny the will of God, nor do they admit that He has a human will, for the human
will implies a deficiency in the willer and a being affected by the object
willed, and when the object is attained, the deficiency is completed and the
passivity, which is called will, ceases. The philosophers only attribute a will
to God in the sense that the acts which proceed from Him proceed through
knowledge, and everything which proceeds through knowledge and wisdom proceeds
through the will of the agent, not, however, necessarily and naturally, since
the nature of knowledge does not imply (as he falsely affirms of the
philosophers) the proceeding of the act. For if the nature of knowledge did
imply this, then, when we say that God knows the opposites, it would be
necessary that the opposites should proceed from Him together, and this is
absurd. The fact that only one of the opposites proceeds from Him shows that
there is another attribute present beside knowledge, namely will, and it is in
this way that the affirmation of will in the First must be understood according
to the philosophers. z For God, according to the philosophers, necessarily knows
and wills through His knowledge. As to Ghazali’s
assertion that the act can be subdivided into two, into a natural act and a
voluntary act, this is false. God’s act according to the philosophers is in a
certain way not natural, nor is it absolutely voluntary; it is voluntary without
having the deficiency which is attached to the human will. Therefore the term
‘will’ is attributed to the Divine Will and the human in an equivocal way,
just as the term ‘knowledge ‘is attributed equivocally to eternal knowledge
and to temporal. For the will in animals and man is a passivity which occurs to
them through the object of desire
and is caused by it. This is the
meaning of ‘will’ in the case of the human will, but the Creator is too
exalted to possess an attribute which should be an effect. Therefore by
‘will’ in God only the procession of the act joined to knowledge can be
understood. And ‘knowledge’, as we said, refers to the two opposites, and in
the knowledge of God there is knowledge of the opposites in a certain way, and
His performing only the one shows that there exists in Him another attribute
which is called ‘will’.
Ghazali says:
The second way of answering is to concede that the procession of a thing from the agent implies knowledge of the thing which proceeds. Now, according to them, the act of God is one, namely the effect which is pure intellect, and God can only know this effect. The first effect again will only know what proceeds from it. For the universe does not proceed from God immediately, but through mediators and derivation and a series of consequences. For that which proceeds from what proceeds from Him need not be known to Him, and from Him Himself only one thing proceeds. And how should He know everything that proceeds mediately from Him? For this is not even necessary in voluntary acts, and how could it be necessary in natural acts? For the movement of a stone from the top of a mountain can occur through a voluntary propulsion which implies knowledge of the principle of motion, but does not imply knowledge of all the consequences which may occur through its knocking and breaking something. ‘ And to this again the philosophers have no answer.
I
answer:
The
answer to this is that the Agent whose knowledge is of the highest perfection
knows everything which proceeds from Him and which proceeds from that which
proceeds from Him, and so from the first term to the last. And if the knowledge
of the First is of the highest perfection, the First must know everything that
proceeds from it either mediately or immediately, and its knowledge need not be
of the same kind as our knowledge, for our knowledge is imperfect and posterior
to the thing known.
Then
Ghazali says, answering the objection he brought
forward against the philosophers:
If, however, the philosophers should say: ‘If we declared that the First only knows its own self, this would be a very reprehensible doctrine, for all other beings know themselves and know the First, and would therefore be superior to it; and how can the effect be superior to the cause?
I
say:
This
is an insufficient answer, for it opposes a rational argument with a moral one.
Then Ghazali
answers this and says:
We should answer: ‘This reprehensible doctrine is a necessary consequence for those who follow the philosophers in denying the Divine Will and the production of the world, and one must either adhere to it as the other philosophers do, or abandon the philosophers and acknowledge that the world is produced through will. ‘
I
say:
Ghazali
means that if they belong to those who affirm that God knows His work, only to
avoid the reprehensible doctrine that He does not know anything but His own
self, they are forced to acknowledge this reprehensible doctrine just as well,
since they affirmed another reprehensible doctrine, namely the eternity of the
world and the denial of the Will. ‘ However, the philosophers do not deny the
Will, and only deny that part of it which implies a deficiency.
Then
Ghazali says:
How will you refute those philosophers who say that this knowledge does not add to God’s dignity, since other beings need knowledge only in order to acquire perfection (for in their essence there is a deficiency) and man receives dignity through the intelligibles either that he may see his advantage in the coming events of this world and the next, or that his obscure and insufficient essence may be perfected, and likewise all the other creatures, but that the essence of God does not stand in need of perfection: nay, if a knowledge could be imagined through which He would be perfected, His essence, in so far as it is His essence, would be imperfect’
This is just the same kind of remark as your assertions, Avicenna, concerning His hearing and seeing and His knowing the particular beings which fall under the concept of time, for you agree with all the other philosophers in saying that God is too exalted for that, and that the changes which fall under the concept of time and which are divided into past and future events are not known to the First, since this would imply a change in its essence and a being influenced, and the denial of this does not imply an imperfection, but rather a perfection, and there is only an imperfection in the senses and the need for them. ‘ If there were not this human imperfection, man would not be in need of the senses to guard himself against any change which might affect him. And in the same way you affirm that the knowledge of particular events is an imperfection. And if it is true that we can know all particular events and perceive all sensible things, whereas the First cannot know anything of the particulars nor perceive anything of sensible things without this implying any imperfection in the First, it may also be permitted to ascribe to others knowledge of the intelligible universals but to deny it of the First without this implying any imperfection in the First. There is no way out of this.
I say:
This
is the proof of those who say that the First knows only itself, and we have
already spoken of the theory of those who combine the doctrine that the First
knows only itself with the theory that it knows all existents; and for this
reason some of the best known philosophers affirm that God the Creator is
Himself all existents and that He grants them in His benevolence, and there is
no sense in repeating ourselves. The premisses used in this section are common
dialectical propositions, since they all belong to those which compare the
Divine to the empirical, although no common genus unites these two spheres and
they do not possess any common factor at all. In general his discussion in this
section, when he argues with Avicenna, who adduces the argument of those
philosophers who believe that God in knowing Himself must know other things,
since He must necessarily know what proceeds from Himself, and all the other
assertions of Avicenna to prove this, which he relates, and which he uses
himself again to refute Avicenna, are all taken from human conditions which he
tries to refer to the Creator; and this is false, since the terms of these two
types of knowledge are predicated equivocally.
Avicenna’s
assertion that any intelligent being from whom an act proceeds knows this act is
a true proposition; not, however, in the sense in which the word ‘knowledge’
is used of the human intellect, when it understands a thing, for the human
intellect is perfected by what it perceives and knows, and is affected by it,
and the cause of action in man is the representation he forms in his intellect.
‘ And Ghazali argues against this kind of
proposition by saying that when a man acts and there follows
from his act another act and from the second act a third and from the third
a fourth, it is not necessary that the conscious agent should know all the
consequences which follow from his
first act; and Ghazali says to his opponent this
is a fact which concerns voluntary acts, but how is it when one assumes an agent
whose acts are not voluntary? And he only says this because he means that the
affirmation of God’s knowledge implies the affirmation of God’s will.
And
therefore Ghazali says:
To this again the philosophers have no answer.
I
say:
Ghazali
means that it does not follow that the First according to Avicenna thinks
anything but the act which proceeds from it primarily, and this act is the
second cause and the first effect. Neither is there an answer to the other
difficulty which he states that if the First thinks only itself and nothing
else, man would be more noble than it. And the reason why Ghazali’s
words carry a certain conviction is that if one imagines two men, one of whom
thinks only his own self, whereas the other thinks his own self and other things
besides, the latter intellect is regarded as superior to the former. However, as
the term ‘intellect’ is applied to the human intellect and to this Divine
Intellect in a purely equivocal way, since the latter is an agent and not a
patient and the former a patient and not an agent, this analogy does not hold
any longer.
Having
given as Avicenna’s argument the maxim which Avicenna applies to every
intelligent being, ‘ that the more knowledge an intellect possesses the nobler
it is, and having affirmed that, according to him (Ghazali),
it is just the philosophers’ denial of God’s will and of temporal creation
which forces them to deny to God a knowledge of anything but Himself, since the
conscious agent knows his effect only in so far as it differs from himself by
being an object of his will, he says that this reprehensible assertion, i. e.
the assertion that the effect which is man must be nobler than the cause which
is the Creator, is a consequence for the philosophers only, sincc as the
philosophers deny the coming into being of the world, they deny the Divine Will,
as he affirms, and as they deny the Divine Will, they deny that God knows what
proceeds from Him. But all this, namely the denial of God’s will, has been
shown previously not to be true; for they deny only His temporal will. And
having repeated Avicenna’s arguments, which he regarded as being applicable
both to the knowledge of the temporal and the knowledge of the eternal, he
begins to argue against him, showing the distinction which the philosophers
established on this point between these two sciences, and indeed this
consequence is incumbent on Avicenna.
And
Ghazali says:
How will you refute those philosophers who say that this knowledge does not add to God’s dignity, for only other beings need knowledge. . . ?
I
say:
The
summary of this is that, if all these perceptions exist only because of man’s
imperfection, then God is too exalted for them; and therefore Ghazali
says to Avicenna: Just as you acknowledge with your fellow-philosophers that
God’s not perceiving individual things is not a consequence of an imperfection
in Him, for you have proved
that the perception of individuals
rests on an imperfection in the perceiver, in the same way the perception of
other things than Himself need not derive from an imperfection in Him, since the
perception of these other things depends on the imperfection of the perceiver.
‘
The
answer to all this is that God’s knowledge cannot be divided into the
opposites of true and false in which human knowledge is divided; for instance,
it may be said of a man that either he knows or he does not know other things,
because these two propositions are contradictory, and when the one is true the
other is false; but in the case of God both propositions, that He knows what He
knows and that He does not know it, are true, for He does not know it through a
knowledge which determines an imperfection, namely human knowledge, but knows it
through a knowledge which does not carry with it any imperfection, and this is a
knowledge the quality of which nobody but God Himself can understand. And
concerning both universals and individuals it is true of Him that He knows them
and does not know them. This is the conclusion to which the principles of the
ancient philosophers led; but those who make a distinction, and say that God
knows universals but does not know particulars have not fully grasped their
theory, and this is not a consequence of their principles. For all human
sciences are passivities and impressions from the existents, and the existents
operate on them. But the knowledge of the Creator operates on existents, and the
existents receive the activities of His knowledge.
Once
this is established, the whole quarrel between Ghazali
and the philosophers comes to an end in regard to this chapter as well as the
next two. We shall, however, give an account of these chapters and mention in
them both what is particular to them and those arguments which have been already
discussed above.
Ghazali
says:
We say that when the Muslims understood that the world was created through the will of God, they proved His knowledge from His will, then His life from His will and His knowledge together, ‘ then from His life, according to the principle that every living being knows itself, they proved that He too must know His own essence, since He is alive. And this is a rational procedure of extreme force. For you philosophers, however, since you deny the divine will and the world’s coming into existence, and since you affirm that what proceeds from Him proceeds in a necessary and natural sequence, why should it be impossible that His essence should be of such a nature that only the first effect proceeded from it, and that then the second effect followed the first till the whole order of existents was completed, but, notwithstanding this, the First would not know itself, just as neither fire from which heat proceeds, nor the sun from which light proceeds, know themselves or anything else? For only that which knows itself knows what proceeds from itself, and therefore knows other things besides itself. And we have already shown that, according to the theory of the philosophers the First does not know other things, and we have forced those who do not agree with them on this point to acknowledge this consequence which follows from their assumption. And if it does not know others, it is not absurd to suppose that it does not know its own self.
If they say: ‘Everyone who does not know himself is dead, and how could the First be dead? ‘-we answer: ‘This is indeed a conclusion which follows from your theory, since there is no difference between you and those who say that every one who does not act through will, power and choice, who neither hears nor sees, is dead, and he who does not know other things is dead. And if it is possible that the First is destitute of all these attributes, what need has it of knowing itself? ‘ And if they return to the doctrine that everything which is free from matter is intellect by itself and therefore thinks itself, we have shown that this is an arbitrary judgement without any proof.
And if they say: ‘The proof is that what is existent is divided into what is alive and what is dead, and what is alive is prior and superior to what is dead, and the First is prior and superior: therefore let it be alive; and every living being knows itself, since it is impossible that the living should be amongst its effects and should not itself be alive’, we answer: ‘All this is pure presumption, for we affirm that it is not impossible that that which knows itself should follow from that which does not, either through many intermediaries or without mediation. And if the reason for its impossibility is that in that case the effect would be superior to the cause, well, it is not impossible that the effect should be superior to the cause, for the superiority of the cause to the effect is not a fundamental principle. Further, how can you refute the view that its superiority might consist not in its knowledge but in the fact that the existence of the universe is a consequence of its essence? For the proof is that, whereas the First neither sees nor hears, there are many other beings who know other things than themselves and who do see and hear. ‘
And if it were said, ‘Existents are divided into the seeing and the blind, the knowing and the ignorant’, we answer: ‘Well, let the seeing then be superior and let the First see and have knowledge of things!” But the philosophers deny this, and say that its excellence does not consist in seeing and knowing things, but in not being in need of sight and knowledge and being the essence from which t